Skip to main content
Log in

Robustness in evolutionary explanations: a positive account

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Robustness analysis is widespread in science, but philosophers have struggled to justify its confirmatory power. We provide a positive account of robustness by analysing some explicit and implicit uses of within and across-model robustness in evolutionary theory. We argue that appeals to robustness are usually difficult to justify because they aim to increase the likeliness that a phenomenon obtains. However, we show that robust results are necessary (under certain conditions) for explanations of phenomena with specific properties. Across-model robustness is necessary for how-possibly explanations of multiply instantiated phenomena, while within-model robustness is necessary for explanations of phenomena with multiple evolutionary starting points. In such cases, the appeal of robustness is explanatory rather than confirmatory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The how-actually/how-possibly distinction, due to Dray (1957), is taken up by Brandon (1990) in the context of evolutionary theory.

  2. McElreath and Boyd (2007) also mention one of the benefits of modelling approaches as providing ‘existence proofs’ (p. 6).

  3. This idea has been recently defended by Ylikoski and Aydinonat (2014), according to whom ‘the main point of theoretical how-possibly explanations is to refine, systematize, and expand the menu of available explanations’ (31). They particularly develop and emphasise this latter point.

  4. We are grateful to [redacted] for raising this issue.

  5. Bokulich’s account has been attacked for being too liberal; for instance, Saatsi and Pexton (2013) doubt “that capturing a mere abstract structure ‘up to isomorphism’ of counterfactual relations can be explanatory” (223–224), if such counterfactual relations cannot be causally interpreted. This need not concern us, as the explanatory targets of evolutionary models are fundamentally causal—although not necessarily governed by factors on which one could intervene.

  6. Brian Skyrms’ (2010) analysis of signalling systems contains other examples of this kind of reasoning.

  7. As noted by an anonymous referee, this is not to say that basin comparisons cannot be unproblematic in some cases, for instance when we compare basin sizes in two models that accurately represent two different systems.

  8. When the models differ E should not be considered as the same evidence for both, as it stands for “the behaviour of interest was obtained in some runs of the simulation”; strictly speaking we should write E1 and E2. However, this modification would only strengthen our point that the direct comparison between P(E|M1) and P(E|M2) is not necessarily insightful.

  9. One may further object that even if we accept that we can attribute probabilities to models, we could never assess these probabilities precisely. This does not matter here, as our discussion does not hinge on the precise values of the P(Mi) but on their equality.

  10. However, authors such as Sugden (2000) would disagree: he sees models as ‘credible fictions’, where credibility is not to be expressed in terms of a probability of being true – models are credible in the way fictions are.

  11. Two possible objections to the use of Bayesian formalism are that P(E) cannot be determined, as it involves considering an infinite number of models. However, only finitely many models can ever be considered. Moreover, the precise value of P(E) does not impinge on our discussion, provided it is not 0.

  12. We thank [redacted] for recommending the use of this Bayesian perspective.

  13. Specifically, if an equilibrium is a global, asymptotically stable attractor then the population reaches that equilibrium eventually. Alexander (2007) relies on similar robustness claims for spatially structured populations.

  14. This might for instance be true of models in which preferential interaction is not based on conditional strategies but on other sources of correlation such as spatially structured interactions or limited dispersal (not included in Skyrms’ aforementioned models).

  15. Since the model uses simulations to estimate basin sizes we cannot, in this case be sure that such a requirement is met.

  16. In a similar spirit, D’Arms et al.’s (1998) criticism of some earlier work of Skyrms can be read as mitigating conclusions drawn from considerating basins by emphasising the greater prior plausibility of alternative modelling assumptions.

  17. Skyrms at least has claimed that within-model robustness has explanatory value, although for unstated reasons: “The fact that the signalling system equilibrium is a global attractor […] and remains so if the replicator dynamics is replaced by any qualitatively adaptive dynamics, strikes me as explanatorily powerful.” (2000, 110).

  18. It corresponds to Woodward’s (2006) ‘causal robustness’ and to Calcott’s (2011) ‘robust phenomena’.

  19. Note that in the case of physical robustness, basin comparison approaches could be defended; our criticisms of “The basin comparison problem” section only bear on such approaches in the context of within-model robustness.

  20. Odenbaugh and Alexandrova (2011) also highlight a heuristic (rather than confirmatory) role of robustness analysis: it helps us identify acceptable candidate hypotheses. For Forber (2010), this role has indirect confirmatory consequences, as it affects the list of competing hypotheses later to be confirmed or disconfirmed.

  21. Again, this is not to say that models always need to represent the robustness of properties, if only because phenomena of interest may be robust with respect to myriad of parameters not represented in the model.

  22. Note that although Sugden (Ibid., 21–23) takes robustness as warranting model-to-model inferences, our defence argues for a model-to-world inference, in which a property of the target system should be similar to the robust model itself.

  23. For relevant examples about experiments on cooperative behaviour in microorganisms see Diggle et al. 2007, Gore et al. 2009, Popat et al. 2012 and Sanchez and Gore 2013.

  24. This is not to say that evolutionary theory is never mentioned in literature on robustness. For instance, Levins’ (1966) seminal paper deals with population biology, and Weisberg’s (2006) analysis focuses on Lotka–Volterra predator–prey models.

  25. Although the mechanisms of social learning and of natural selection differ, they share similar principles: a trait’s fixation respectively depends on its effect on fitness or its consequences for rewards (see Benaim et al. 2004). Moreover, models and their basins have similar importance for both, as Skyrms’ analysis renders manifest. Accordingly, we consider our focus on evolutionary models to include social learning.

  26. However, they do refer to general mechanisms and conditions not limited to signalling behaviour, such as imitative learning or freedom of interaction. These may constitute necessary conditions for a signalling model, but not its common core, because following Weisberg’s condition (2), the presence of such a common core would have to entail the evolution of signalling (to lead to a robust theorem), rather than being able to produce it. Imitative learning and freedom interaction are too general and high level to constitute a common core.

  27. Still, this is not impossible, as pointed out by [redacted].

  28. Note that if the phenomenon really is multiply instantiated, then we should only be satisfied with how-possibly explanations that are different enough, that is, that do not only aim to represent different causal scenarios but different causal mechanisms—a distinction found in Ylikoski and Aydinonat (2014). Where two causal scenarios are just alternative causal histories, which may disagree regarding only one fact, causal mechanisms are more general and involve types of causal links (and so may constitute ‘skeletons of causal processes’ (27) upon which detailed causal scenarios can be built).

  29. Also note that it does not draw on Bokulich’s account of explanation.

  30. Our positive take applies to robustness within one model and with respect to very different models, but probably not to robustness with respect to tractability or modelling assumptions, which have no clear real-world counterparts.

  31. If robustness analysis à la Weisberg aims to identify the common causal core responsible for a target phenomenon that occurs in several (possibly similar) contexts, then the absence of homogenous across-model robustness would actually provide reasons to look for heterogeneous across-model robustness.

References

  • Alexander JM (2007) The structural evolution of morality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett J (2007) The evolution of coding in signaling games. Theor Decis 67:223–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett JA (2014) The evolution, appropriation, and composition of rules. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0421-6

  • Benaim M, Schreiber SJ, Tarres P (2004) Generalized Urn models of evolutionary processes. Ann Appl Probab 14:1455–1478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2006) Why do people cooperate? Politics Philos Econ 5(1):81–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich A (2011) How scientific models can explain. Synthese 180:33–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourke A (2011) Principles of social evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B (2008) The other cooperation problem: generating benefit. Biol Philos 23:179–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B (2011) Wimsatt and the robustness family: review of Wimsatt’s Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Biol Philos 26(2):281–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver C (2006) When mechanistic models explain. Synthese 153:355–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms J, Batterman R, Górny K (1998) Game theoretic explanations and the evolution of justice. Philos Sci 65:76–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diggle SP, Griffin AS, Campbell GS, West SA (2007) Cooperation and conflict in quorum-sensing bacterial populations. Nature 450:411–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dray W (1957) Law and explanation in history. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar R (1993) Coevolution of neocortical size, group size and language in humans. Behav Brain Sci 16:681–735

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin M, Sober E (2002) Cartwright on explanation and idealization. Erkenntnis 57:441–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber P (2010) Confirmation and explaining how possible. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 41:32–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber P, Smead R (2014) The evolution of fairness through spite. Proc R Soc Lond B 281:20132439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frean M, Abraham ER (2001) ‘Rock–scissors–paper and the survival of the weakest. Proc R Soc Lond B 268(1474):1323–1327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A, Varian H (1978) Economic models. J Philos 75:664–677

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H (2011) Gene–culture coevolution and the nature of human sociality. Philos Trans R Soc B 366:878–888

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gore J, Youk H, van Oudenaarden A (2009) Snowdrift game dynamics and facultative cheating in yeast. Nature 459:253–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houkes W, Vaesen K (2012) Robust! Handle with care. Philos Sci 79:1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huttegger S (2007) Robustness in signaling games. Philos Sci 74:839–847

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huttegger S, Zollman K (2010) Dynamic stability and basins of attraction in the Sir Philip Sidney game. Proc R Soc Lond B 277:1925–1932

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huttegger S, Zollman K (2013) Methodology in biological game theory. Br J Philos Sci 64:637–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huttegger S, Skyrms B, Tarrès Pierre, Wagner E (2014) Some dynamics of signalling games. Proc Natl Acad Sci 111(Supplement 3):10873–10880

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston MD, Edwards CM, Bodmer WF, Maini PK, Chapman SJ (2012) Examples of mathematical modelling: tales from the crypt. Cell Cycle 6(17):2106–2112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen ID, Flemming JM, Myers RA (2005) Robust state-space modeling of animal movement data. Ecology 86(11):2874–2880

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Justus J (2010) Complexity, diversity and stability. In: Sarkar S, Plutynski A (eds) A companion to the philosophy of biology, vol 90. Wiley, New York, pp 321–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Justus J (2012) The elusive basis of inferential robustness. Philos Sci 79(5):795–807

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski J, Lehtinen A, Marchionni C (2009) Economic modelling as robustness analysis. Br J Philos Sci 61(3):541–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54(4):421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd E (2010) Confirmation and robustness of climate models. Philos Sci 77:971–984

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1994) Isolation, idealization and truth in economics. Poznan Stud Philos Sci Humanit 38:147–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey D (1983) The rhetoric of economics. J Econ Lit 21:481–517

    Google Scholar 

  • McElreath R, Boyd R (2007) Mathematical models for social evolution: a guide for the perplexed. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1985) Galilean idealization. Stud Hist Philos Sci 16:247–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J, Alexandrova A (2011) Buyer beware: robustness analyses in economics and biology. Biol Philos 26:757–771

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1993) A critical assessment of Levins’s the strategy of model building in population biology (1966). Q Rev Biol 68(4):533–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popat R, Crusz SA, Messina M, Williams P, West SA, Diggle P (2012) Quorum-sensing and cheating in bacterial biolfiilms. Proc R Soc Lond B 279:4765–4771

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raerinne J (2013) Robustness and sensitivity of biological models. Philos Stud 166:285–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi J, Pexton M (2013) Reassessing Woodward’s account of explanation: regularities, counterfactuals, and noncausal explanations. Philos Sci 80(5):613–624

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanchez A, Gore J (2013) Feedback between population and evolutionary dynamics determines the fate of social microbial populations. PLoS Biol 11(4):e1001547

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinervo B, Lively CM (1996) The rock-paper-scissors game and the evolution of alternate male strategies. Nature 380:240–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (1996) Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (2010) Signals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smead R (2010) Indirect reciprocity and the evolution of moral signals. Biol Philos 25:33–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2000) Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. J Econ Methodol 7(1):1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner EO (2012) Deterministic chaos and the evolution of meaning. Br J Philos Sci 63(3):547–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2006) Robustness analysis. Philos Sci 73:730–742

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M, Reisman K (2008) The robust Volterra principle. Philos Sci 75:106–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2007) Social semantics: altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. J Evol Biol 20:415–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodcock S, Heath J (2002) The robustness of altruism as an evolutionary strategy. Biol Philos 17:567–590

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2006) Some varieties of robustness. J Econ Methodol 13:219–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Conor Mayo-Wilson, Seamus Bradley, Catherine Herfeld and Aidan Lyon for comments on previous versions of this paper, as well as the audiences of the Philosophy of Biology in the UK (2012) and of the BSPS 2013 conferences. The remarks of several anonymous referees also proved extremely valuable. Cédric Paternotte was supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cédric Paternotte.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Paternotte, C., Grose, J. Robustness in evolutionary explanations: a positive account. Biol Philos 32, 73–96 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9539-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9539-x

Keywords

Navigation