Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T01:10:32.463Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

the Analysis of Faith in St Thomas Aquinas

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Terence Penelhum
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy and Religious Studies, University of Calgary

Extract

My intent in this paper is to give an account of Aquinas' analysis of the nature of Christian faith, to indicate some difficulties to which it seems to me, and has seemed to others, to give rise, to try to evaluate the degree to which his analysis can suggest answers to those difficulties, and then to conclude with some general comments about the sources of those perplexities that still remain.*

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 134 note 1 For an extended discussion of this question, see Chapter 6 of my Problems of Religious Knowledge (Macmillan, London, 1971).Google Scholar

page 134 note 2 Summa Theologiae Ia2ae.55,4. In the case of long quotations I have used the new Blackfriars, edition of the Summa, published by Eyre and Spottiswoode, London.Google Scholar

page 135 note 1 S.T. Ia2ae.63, I; see also 51, 4.

page 135 note 2 See De Veritate 14,10, reply to second difficulty; also S.T. 2a2ae.5,1.

page 135 note 3 S.T. 1a2ae.63,2.

page 135 note 4 De Veritate 14,10, reply to tenth difficulty.

page 135 note 5 S.T. Ia2ae.64,3.

page 135 note 6 Ia2ae.64,3.

page 135 note 7 Ia2ae.62,2.

page 135 note 8 Ia2ae.62,1.

page 136 note 1 On the unsuitability of ‘habit’ as a translation of habitus, see Anthony Kenny's introduction to his translation of Ia2ae. 49–54 in Vol. 22 of the Blackfriars, edition of the Summa, 1964.Google Scholar

page 136 note 2 1a2ae.52,1.

page 136 note 3 la2ae.66,1 ad 3.

page 136 note 4 Ia2ae.65,1.

page 136 note 5 Ia2ae.65,4.

page 136 note 6 Ia2ae.65,5.

page 136 note 7 Ia2ae.65,5.

page 136 note 8 De Veritate 14,6.

page 137 note 1 S.T. 2a2ae.2.

page 137 note 2 2a2ae.3.

page 137 note 3 2a2ae.3,1 ad 3.

page 137 note 4 2a2ae.3,1.

page 137 note 5 See the discussion of cognitive dispositions in 1a2ae.50,4 and 53,1 and 2. See also Appendix 10 to Kenny's Vol. 22 of the Blackfriars Summa.

page 138 note 1 Dr Kenny's comments on the conference version of this essay have made it clear to me that credere is used by Aquinas as a success-term – so that, in contrast to opinio, it can only have truth as its object. This restriction, required by his theological understanding of faith as excluding the acceptance of falsehoods, is obviously not a feature of the English ‘belief’, which is an additional reason for treating it with caution as a translation, though of course in this last respect ‘assent’ does not carry this restriction either.

page 138 note 2 Trans. Gilby, Blackfriars Vol. 17, page 197.

page 139 note 1 De Ver. 14, 1.

page 139 note 2 S.T. 2a2ae.2, 1.

page 139 note 3 2a2ae.2,1.

page 141 note 1 He uses this argument in Article 12 of the De Veritate discussion to establish the indivisibility of the articles of faith themselves. I am indebted here to a valuable essay by Tad, W.. Guzie, S.J., ‘The Act of Faith According to St. Thomas: a Study in Theological Methodology’, The Thomist, XXIX (1965), 239–80.Google Scholar

page 142 note 1 S.T. 1a2ae.65,5.

page 142 note 2 De Ver.14,7.

page 142 note 3 14,6. Translation by McGlynn, James V. in vol. II of Truth (Chicago, 1953), p. 237.Google Scholar

page 142 note 4 S.T. 2a2ae. 6,2 ad 1.

page 143 note 1 I am indebted here to Hick's, John treatment of this theme in chapter 1 of Faith and Knowledge, 2nd edition (Cornell, Ithaca, N.Y., 1966).Google Scholar

page 143 note 2 See, for example, Summa Contra Gentiles Book One, chapters 1–8; S.T. 1a.1,1; 2a2ae.2,4.

page 144 note 1 See 2a2ae.1,1 ad 1.

page 144 note 2 S.C.G. 1, 5–6; S.T. 1a2ae.1, 1 ad 3.

page 144 note 3 Chapter III of the Dogmatic Constitution of the Catholic Faith, trans. Cardinal Manning.

page 145 note 1 2a2ae.5,2; Blackfriars translation by T. C. O'Brien.

page 147 note 1 2a2ae.4,8.

page 148 note 1 2a2ae.4,7.

page 148 note 2 De Ver. 14,1.

page 148 note 3 McGlynn translation, page 212.

page 150 note 1 S.T. 2a2ae.4,8 ad I.

page 150 note 2 2a2ae.I,3.

page 150 note 3 De Ver. 14,12.

page 150 note 4 S.T. 2a2ae.5,3.

page 151 note 1 One cannot strive to perfect the degree of one's possession of a virtue if one cannot, by definition, possess it less than perfectly.

page 151 note 2 See, for example, Maclntyre, Alasdair, ‘The Logical Status of Religious Belief’’ in Metaphysical Beliefs (SCM Press, London, 1957), esp. pp. 195205.Google Scholar

page 153 note 1 I have attempted to outline such an analysis in Problems of Religious Knowledge, esp. chapter 6.

page 153 note 2 It is this understanding of faith that is developed in Mitchell's, BasilThe Justification of Religious Belief (Macmillan, London, 1973).CrossRefGoogle Scholar