Skip to main content

Three Conceptions of Explaining How Possibly—and One Reductive Account

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings ((EPSP,volume 1))

Abstract

Philosophers of science have often favoured reductive approaches to how-possibly explanation. This chapter identifies three varieties of how-possibly explanation and, in so doing, helps to show that this form of explanation is a rich and interesting phenomenon in its own right.

The first variety approaches “How is it possible that X?” by showing that, despite appearances, X is not ruled out by what was believed prior to X. This can sometimes be achieved by removing misunderstandings about the implications of one’s belief system (prior to observing X), but more often than not it involves a modification of this belief system so that one’s acceptance of X does not generate a contradiction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    However, the reductive perspective is often formulated and motivated rather casually: Cohen (1950, 259) requires of any explanation that it be an “appropriate answer to the question ‘why’ the explicandum is the case”; Braithwaite (1946, ii) states that an explanation is simply “any answer to a ‘why’ question which in any way answers the question, and thereby gives some degree of intellectual satisfaction to the questioner” (see Dray 1957, 156); van Fraassen (1980) echoes the remarks of these forerunners. Given their sweeping formulations, it is perhaps misleading to understand the positions of Cohen and his contemporaries as serious attempts at reduction at all.

  2. 2.

    Its epistemic counterpart will be dealt with, briefly, at the end of the paper.

  3. 3.

    According to Resnik, the lack of adequate empirical support is definitive of how-possibly explanation. How-possibly explanations may become how-actually explanations as science progresses. This position is reminiscent of Levi’s (2003) understanding of dispositions, since the latter’s dispositions can become real as science progresses. See also Persson (2006). Machamer et al. (2000) seem to be attracted to a similar idea.

  4. 4.

    And, as already noted, in some places Craver and Darden might add the further restriction that the how-possibly explanation is actually false.

  5. 5.

    It is trivial that this how-possibly explanation does not imply that the explanans is inadequate or—worse still—false.

  6. 6.

    Of course, a number of complications should be contemplated at this point—especially the possibility that several mechanisms yielding the same outcome exist. However, these complications do not matter in the present context, where the only thing I wish to point out is the distinctness of this variety of how-possibly explanation in comparison with the other varieties I have identified.

References

  • Braithwaite, R.B. 1946. Teleological explanations: The presidential address. Proceedings of the Aristotelian society 47: i–xx.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleveland, L.R. 1925. The effects of oxygenation and starvation on the symbiosis between the termite, Termopsis, and its intestinal flagellates. Biological Bulletin 48(5): 309–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. 1950. Teleological explanation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 51: 225–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. 2007. Explaining the brain. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., and L. Darden. 2005. Introduction. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36(2): 233–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. 1957. Laws and explanations in history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. 1960. The competitive exclusion principle. Science 131: 1292–1298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1970. Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press Paperback.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hille, B. 1992. Ion channels of excitable membranes, 2nd ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, G.E. 1961. The paradox of the plankton. American Naturalist 95(882): 137–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutay, U., F. Bischoff, S. Kostka, R. Kraft, and D. Görlich. 1997. Export of importin alpha from the nucleus is mediated by a specific nuclear transport factor. Cell 90(September 19): 1061–1071.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. 2003. Dispositions and conditionals. In Real metaphysics, eds. H. Lillehammar and G. Rodriguez-Pereyra, 137–153. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 57: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. 1916. On the classification of systems of hypotheses. In Philosophical papers 1913-1946, eds. R.S. Cohen and M.D. Neurath, 172–182. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Persson, J. 2006. Levi on the reality of dispositions. In Knowledge and inquiry: Essays on the pragmatism of Isaac Levi, ed. E. Olsson, 313–326. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G.A. 1994. Planning science: Otto Neurath and the “International Encyclopedia of Unified Science”. The British Journal for the History of Science 27(2): 153–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D.B. 1991. How-possibly explanations in biology. Acta Biotheoretica 39: 141–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richmond, R.H. 1997. Reproduction and recruitment in corals: Critical links in the persistence of reefs. In Life and death of coral reefs, ed. C. Birkeland, 175–197. New York: Chapman & Hall.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1984. Scientific explanation: Three basic conceptions. PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1984, Volume Two: Symposia and Invited Papers: 293–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1989. Four decades of scientific explanation. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johannes Persson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this paper

Cite this paper

Persson, J. (2012). Three Conceptions of Explaining How Possibly—and One Reductive Account. In: de Regt, H., Hartmann, S., Okasha, S. (eds) EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. The European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2404-4_24

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics