Skip to main content

Implications of the Nonidentity Problem for State Regulation of Reproductive Liberty

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 35))

Abstract

Many proposed laws regulating the use of reproductive technology will not protect identifiable children from harm but will instead reduce future suffering by changing the identities of the children who are born. Because the “injuries by substitution” caused by these uses of technology are not person-affecting—they have no individual victims—the state’s interest in preventing them might be considered less powerful than its interest in preventing person-affecting harms. This paper argues, however, that the framework of U.S. constitutional democracy does not require that we think of the state’s interest in preventing impersonal injuries by substitution as less than compelling. Accordingly, the fact that such laws (including laws against incest) fail to protect offspring against person-affecting harm is not sufficient to establish that they represent unconstitutional interferences with procreative liberty. Naked “moral” objections to the exercise of a fundamental right will not give the Supreme Court ground to uphold a law, but the fact that the law is closely tied to the prevention of injuries by substitution may and should be enough to do the trick.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Aleinikoff, T.A. 1987. Constitutional law in the age of balancing. Yale Law Journal 96: 943.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Associated Press. 2002. Study downgrades risk of birth defects in children of couples who are cousins, Thur. April 4, 2002, St. Louis Post-Dispatch, p. A11 (suggesting that close cousins face an additional risk of birth defects of 1.7–2.8 percent, a smaller difference than expected).

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, R.E. 2003. Justice Kennedy’s libertarian revolution: Lawrence v. Texas. In Cato Supreme Court Review 2002–2003, ed. J. Swanson, 21. Washington, DC: Center for Constitutional Studies, Cato Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayles, M. 1976. Harm to the unconceived. Philosophy & Public Affairs 5: 292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhagwat, A. 1997. Purpose scrutiny in constitutional analysis. California Law Review 85: 299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D. 1995a. Procreative liberty. Texas Law Review 74: 187 (1995).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D. 1995b. The non-identity problem and genetic harms: The case of wrongful handicaps, Bioethics 9: 269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemerinsky, E. 1997. Constitutional law principles and policies. New York: Aspen Law & Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. A. 2004. Of same sex relationships and affirmative action: The covert libertarianism of the United States Supreme Court. Supreme Court Economic Review 12: 75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fallon, Jr., R. 1993. Individual rights and the powers of government. Georgia Law Review 27: 343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1986. Wrongful life and the counterfactual element in harming. Social Philosophy & Policy 4: 145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, S. 1988. Compelling government interest: An essential but unanalyzed term in constitutional adjudication. Boston University Law Review 68: 917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunther, G. 1972. Foreword: In search of evolving doctrine on a changing court: A model for a newer equal protection. Harvard Law Review 86: 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. 1983. Value and population size. Ethics 93: 496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudor, M. 1994. In defense of wrongful life: Bringing political theory to the defense of a tort. Fordham Law Review 62: 1675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S., 1985. On liberty, ed. D. Bromwich and G. Kate. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. 1976. Moral problems of population. In Ethics & population, ed. M. Bayles, 59. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1976. On doing the best for our children. In Ethics & population, ed. M. Bayles, 100–115. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Jr. P. 1989. Protecting the unconceived: Nonexistence, avoidability, and reproductive technology. Arizona Law Review 31: 487.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Jr., P. 2004. How safe is safe enough? Obligations to the children of reproductive technology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pildes, R. 1994. Avoiding balancing: The role of exclusionary reasons in constitutional law. Hastings Law Journal 45: 711.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, J. 1997. Wrongful life, federalism, and procreative liberty: A critique of the NBAC cloning report. Jurimetrics 38: 69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheppard. S. 1994. The state interest in the good citizen: Constitutional balance between the citizen and the perfectionist state. Hastings Law Journal 45: 969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Secunda, P.M. 2005. Lawrence’s quintessential Millian moment and its impact on the doctrine of unconstitutional conditions. Villanova Law Review 50: 117.

    Google Scholar 

  • St. Louis Post-Dispatch, Diseases sperm forces fertility clinics to close, Nov. 30. 1997, p. A5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. 2002. Is there a constitutional right to clone? Hastings Law Journal 53: 987.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Peters, P.G. (2009). Implications of the Nonidentity Problem for State Regulation of Reproductive Liberty. In: Roberts, M.A., Wasserman, D.T. (eds) Harming Future Persons. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5697-0_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics