Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The katechon in the age of biopolitical nihilism

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article addresses the ‘messianic turn’ in contemporary continental philosophy, focusing on the concept of the katechon as the restraining force that delays the advent of the Antichrist in the Second Letter to the Thessalonians. While Carl Schmitt held the passage on the katechon to ground the Christian doctrine of state power, Giorgio Agamben’s reading of Pauline messianism rather posits the ‘removal’ of the katechon as the pathway for messianic redemption. In our argument, the significance of this text goes beyond the persistence of a vestige of the theological in modern politics. On the contrary, the logic of the katechon only comes into its own under modern nihilism as the resolution of the problem of social order in the absence of the eschatological dimension. The article focuses on the lethal paradox of the logic of the katechon, whereby the function of protection and restraint is converted into violence and anomie, and global political order becomes indistinguishable from global civil war. We conclude by outlining the conditions for suspending the katechonic function in a critical engagement with Agamben’s messianic politics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 2 Thessalonians 2, 6–8, cited in Agamben (2005a, p. 109). Since we shall primarily deal with Agamben’s interpretation of this passage, we rely on Patricia Dailey’s translation of the Pauline text in the Time that Remains.

  2. For theological interpretations of the Letter see e.g. Best (1972), Jones (2005).

  3. Schmitt (2003, p. 60). For other references to the katechon in Schmitt’s texts see Schmitt (1997, pp. 8, 43, 2008, p. 92). In his late writings Schmitt designated numerous institutions and persons as the katechons of their time (the Jesuit Order, Emperor Franz Joseph, Jus Publicum Europeaum, Masaryk, Pilsudski, etc.) yet this designation arguably remained allegorical. See e.g. Palaver (1996, pp. 123–124), Meier (1988, pp. 158–166).

  4. Schmitt (2003, p. 60).

  5. Cf. Balakrishnan (2002, p. 224).

  6. Schmitt (2003, p. 63).

  7. Schmitt (2003, p. 238).

  8. See Strauss (1976, p. 103), Palaver (1996, pp. 105–127), Ojakangas (2006, pp. 189–201).

  9. Schmitt cited in Meier (1988, p. 162).

  10. Agamben (2005a, p. 110).

  11. Agamben (2007, p. 77).

  12. Rasch (2007, pp. 102–108).

  13. Agamben (1998, pp. 15–36).

  14. Agamben (1998, pp. 105–106).

  15. Agamben (2005a, pp. 95–101).

  16. Agamben (2005a, p. 111).

  17. Agamben (2005a, p. 111).

  18. Cf. Schmitt (1985).

  19. Agamben (2005a, p. 111).

  20. Virno (2008, p. 45).

  21. Schmitt (1976, pp. 58–66).

  22. Virno (2008, p. 16).

  23. Virno (2008, p. 21).

  24. Virno (2008, p. 31).

  25. Virno (2008, pp. 56, 189).

  26. Virno (2008, p. 57).

  27. Virno (2008, p. 59).

  28. Virno (2008, p. 60).

  29. Virno (2008, pp. 60–61).

  30. Derrida (1985, pp. 1–28).

  31. Derrida (1981, pp. 61–172).

  32. Agamben (1993, p. 7, see more generally pp. 39–41, 79–105).

  33. Virno (2008, p. 61).

  34. Hardt and Negri (2000).

  35. Virno (2008, p. 64).

  36. Virno (2008, p. 54).

  37. Virno (2008, p. 190).

  38. See Virno (2008, p. 60).

  39. Esposito (2008a, pp. 50–51).

  40. Esposito (2008a, p. 46).

  41. Esposito (2008a, p. 56).

  42. Esposito (2008a, p. 58).

  43. See Derrida (1998, pp. 145–146).

  44. Derrida (1998, p. 92).

  45. Derrida (1998, p. 112).

  46. See Esposito (2008b, p. 640).

  47. Esposito (2008a, p. 115).

  48. Esposito (2008a, p. 138). See also Derrida (2004, pp. 33–37).

  49. Esposito (2008a, p. 54).

  50. Benjamin (2003). For a detailed discussion of the Benjamin–Schmitt debate see Agamben (2005b, pp. 53–57), Weber (1992, pp. 5–18), Bredekamp (1999, pp. 247–266).

  51. Schmitt (1985, pp. 13–32, 35–63). Cf. Schmitt (1994).

  52. Benjamin (2003, p. 88).

  53. Foucault (2007, p. 260).

  54. Benjamin (2003, p. 81).

  55. Benjamin (2003, p. 66). In State of Exception Agamben contested the conventional version of this fragment, arguing that Benjamin’s editors have erroneously replaced the original “there is a baroque eschatology” (Es gibt eine barocke Eschatologie) by “there is no baroque eschatology” (Es gibt keine barocke eschatology), distorting the meaning of the text. In Agamben’s (2005b, p. 57) reading, Benjamin’s point is precisely that the baroque age knows an eschaton, but this eschaton is wholly immanent to this world, consigning the world “to an absolutely empty sky.” The plausibility of Agamben’s correction is somewhat tempered, since he does not consider another occasion on which the absence of eschatology is invoked in Benjamin’s text: “[Consequent] upon the total disappearance of eschatology is the attempt to find, in a reversion to a bare state of creation, consolation for the renunciation of a state of grace.” Benjamin (2003, p. 81, see also the passage on the “rejection of eschatology” on the same page). On the other hand, Agamben’s correction does not entirely modify the conventional reading but rather adds an insightful nuance to it: the vacuity of the eschaton is not the same as its absence, as the “white eschatology” without any content persists in this world and configures it as a permanent state of exception, a site of “catastrophe.” Benjamin (2003, p. 66).

  56. Benjamin (2003, p. 66).

  57. Benjamin (2003, p. 55).

  58. Agamben (2005b, p. 57).

  59. Benjamin (2003, p. 85).

  60. Benjamin (2003, p. 70).

  61. Benjamin (2003, p. 70).

  62. Benjamin (2003, p. 88).

  63. Benjamin (2003, p. 95).

  64. Weber (1992, p. 12).

  65. Foucault (2007, pp. 87–133).

  66. Foucault (1990, pp. 133–159, 2008, pp. 27–73).

  67. Benjamin (2003, p. 96). See also Weber (1992, p. 17).

  68. See also Badiou (2003), Zizek (2003).

  69. Milbank (2008, pp. 159, 161).

  70. See Agamben (1991, p. 39, 2005a, p. 102, 2005b, p. 64).

  71. Derrida (1994, pp. 15–38, 56–74).

  72. Agamben (1995, p. 82).

  73. Agamben (1991, p. 106).

  74. Agamben (2007, pp. 73–92).

  75. Agamben (1993, p. 106).

  76. Agamben (1993, p. 102).

  77. See e.g. Agamben (1991, pp. 49–53, 99–101, 1998, pp. 60–62, 2000, pp. 109–111, 2005a, pp. 99–103).

  78. Benjamin (2003, p. 92).

  79. Agamben (1993, p. 57).

References

  • Agamben, G. 1991. Language and death: The place of negativity. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, C. 1993. The coming community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 1995. Idea of prose. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign power and bare life. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 2000. Means without end: Notes on politics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 2005a. The time that remains: A commentary on the Letter to the Romans. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 2005b. State of exception. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. 2007. Profanations. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badiou, A. 2003. St. Paul: The foundation of universalism. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balakrishnan, G. 2002. The enemy: An intellectual portrait of Carl Schmitt. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, W. 2003. The origin of German tragic drama. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Best, E. 1972. The first and second epistles to the Thessalonians. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bredekamp, H. 1999. From Walter Benjamin to Carl Schmitt, via Thomas Hobbes. Critical Inquiry 25: 247–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1981. Dissemination. London: Athlone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1985. Margins of philosophy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1994. Spectres of Marx: The state of the debt, the work of mourning and the new international. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1998. Of grammatology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 2004. Rogues: Two essays on reason. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, R. 2008a. Bios: Biopolitics and philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, R. 2008b. Totalitarianism and biopolitics? Concerning a philosophical interpretation of the twentieth century. Critical Inquiry 34: 633–644.

  • Foucault, M. 1990. The history of sexuality, vol. 1: An introduction. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. 2007. Security, territory, population: Lectures at the College de France 1977–1978. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. 2008. The birth of biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France 1977–1978. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, M., and A. Negri. 2000. Empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, I.H. 2005. The epistles to the Thessalonians. Peterborough: Epworth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meier, H. 1988. The lesson of Carl Schmitt: Four chapters on the distinction between political theology and political philosophy. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milbank, J. 2008. Paul against biopolitics. Theory, Culture and Society 25: 125–172.

  • Ojakangas, M. 2006. A philosophy of concrete life: Carl Schmitt and the political thought of late modernity. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palaver, W. 1996. Carl Schmitt on nomos and space. Telos 106: 105–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasch, W. 2007. From sovereign ban to banning sovereignty. In Giorgio Agamben: Sovereignty and life, ed. M. Calarco, and S. DeCaroli. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 1976. The concept of the political. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 1985. Political theology: Four chapters on the concept of sovereignty. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 1994. Die Diktatur. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 1997. Land and sea. Washington, DC: Plutarch Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 2003. The nomos of the earth in the international law of Jus Publicum Europaeum. New York: Telos Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. 2008. Political theology II: The myth of the closure of any political theology. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. 1976. Comments on Carl Schmitt’s Der Begriff Des Politischen. In Schmitt, C. 1976. The concept of the political. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

  • Virno, P. 2008. Multitude between innovation and negation. New York: Semiotext(e).

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, S. 1992. Taking exception to decision: Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt. Diacritics 22(3–4): 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zizek, S. 2003. The puppet and the dwarf: The perverse core of Christianity. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sergei Prozorov.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Prozorov, S. The katechon in the age of biopolitical nihilism. Cont Philos Rev 45, 483–503 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-012-9232-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-012-9232-y

Keywords

Navigation