Skip to main content
Log in

Much Ado About Nothing: The Bergsonian and Heideggerian Roots of Sartre’s Conception of Nothingness

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The question of nothingness occupies the thinking of a number of philosophers in the first half of the twentieth-century, with three of the most important responses being those of Henri Bergson, Martin Heidegger, and Jean-Paul Sartre. Surprisingly, however, there has been little discussion of their specific comments on nothingness either individually or comparatively. This paper starts to remedy this by suggesting that, while Bergson dismisses nothingness as a pseudo-problem based in a flawed metaphysical understanding, Heidegger, in What is Metaphysics?, claims that metaphysics entails a covering of being meaning that Bergson’s analysis actually depends on and so brings thinking to a questioning of being (=ontology). In turn, Heidegger’s insight acts as the transitional point for Sartre who criticizes Bergson’s description of nothingness to show that, following Heidegger, nothingness is a real ontological problem. From this insight, Sartre distinguishes between negativity, nothingness, and nihilation to show that the issue of nothingness is intimately connected to the freedom of human consciousness, which, by distinguishing between ontological and practical freedom, reveals that nothingness has ethical and political significance. By way of conclusion, a number of problems in Sartre’s account are identified.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout I use the terms ‘nothing’ and ‘nothingness’ interchangeably.

  2. Given that it focuses on the phenomenological tradition, this paper will not engage with ‘analytical’ discussions/critiques (see Carnap 1966) of the notion. I highlight them, however, to support my claim about the important role ‘nothingness’ plays in early twentieth-century philosophy.

  3. Gale (1974) and Käufer (2005) are notable exceptions.

  4. For more on this, see (Rae 2011: 64–66).

  5. Much has been written on Bergson’s theory of time. For example, Ansell-Pearson (2002) provides a very detailed account of Bergson’s theory of time that situates it in relation to other figures (Russell, Popper, Einstein, Dennett, Deleuze, Kant, and Nietzsche) in the history of philosophy. Al-Saji (2004) offers an interesting reconstruction of Bergson’s account of time by contrasting and comparing it to Deleuze’s, while Lazzarato (2007) shows how and why Bergson’s notion of time is useful when thinking about certain technologies.

  6. See (Rae 2013) for a detailed discussion of the different forms of philosophy/thinking in Heidegger.

  7. See (Rae 2014) for greater discussion of Heidegger’s tri-partite understanding of metaphysics.

  8. In his later Zolikon Seminar, Heidegger claims that “rather than speaking about possibilities as constituents of Dasein, it is always better to speak about potentiality-to-be [Seinkönnen] in the sense of the potentiality for being-in-the-world” (2001: 158). In other words, being is now connected to potential rather than possibility. This does not, however, change my basic point. Being is intimately connected to options as opposed to the fixed presence of actuality.

  9. McCulloch (1994: 3) notes that there are, in fact, two senses to being-in-itself: (1) being-in-itself as the ontological characteristic of a particular entity, and (2) being-in-itself as a mode of being consciousness can adopt.

  10. See (Rae 2009) for a detailed discussion of Sartre’s conception of ‘conversion’ and its ethical implications.

  11. See (Rae 2012) for a detailed discussion of this.

  12. See (Rae 2011) and Heter (2009) for more detailed discussions on Sartrean ethics and its relationship to politics.

  13. See (Rae 2011: 115–117) for a comparison of Sartre’s and Hegel’s analyses on this point.

References

  • Al-Saji, A. (2004). The memory of another past: Bergson, Deleuze and a new theory of time. Continental Philosophy Review, 37, 203–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T. C. (1993). Sartre’s two ethics: From authenticity to integral humanity. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ansell-Pearson, K. (2002). Philosophy and the adventure of the virtual: Bergson and the time of life. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1944). Creative evolution (A. Mitchell, Trans.). New York: Random House.

  • Bergson, H. (2001). Time and free will (F. L. Pogson, Trans.). London: Dover.

  • Breeur, R. (2001). Bergson’s and Sartre’s account of the self in relation to the transcendental ego. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 9(2), 177–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1966). The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language (A. Pap, Trans.). In A. J. Ayer (Ed.), Logical positivism (pp. 60–81). New York: The Free Press.

  • Detmer, D. (1988). Freedom as a value: A critique of the ethical theory of Jean-Paul Sartre. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrell-Fox, N. (2003). The new Sartre: Exploration in postmodernism. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fell, J. (1983). Heidegger and Sartre. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gale, R. M. (1974). Bergson’s analysis of the concept of nothing. The Modern Schoolman, 51, 269–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, S. (2009). Sartre’s being and nothingness. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert-Walsh, J. (2010). Revisiting the concept of time: Archaic perplexity in Bergson and Heidegger. Human Studies, 33, 173–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gunter, P. (2010). A criticism of Sartre’s concept of time. In M. R. Kelly (Ed.), Bergson and phenomenology. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). Letter on humanism. In David Farrell-Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (pp. 217–265). London: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2000). Introduction to metaphysics (G. Fried & R. Polt, Trans.). London: Yale University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Zolikon seminars: ProtocolsConversationsLetters (F. Mayr & R. Askay, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2002). Identity and difference (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2003). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). London: Blackwell.

  • Heidegger, M. (2006). Mindfulness (P. Emad & T. Kalary, Trans.). New York: Continuum.

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Towards the definition of philosophy (T. Sadler, Trans.). London: Continuum.

  • Heidegger, M. (2013). The event (R. Rojcewicz, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heter, T. S. (2009). Sartre’s ethics of engagement. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Käufer, S. (2005). The nothing and the ontological difference in Heidegger’s what is metaphysics? Inquiry, 48(6), 482–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazzarato, M. (2007). Machines to crystallize time: Bergson. Theory, Culture, Society, 24(6), 93–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2002). Sartre. Oxford: OneWorld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J. (2006). Heidegger’s topology: Being, place, world. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch, G. (1994). Using Sartre: An Analytical introduction to early sartrean themes. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2009). Sartre and the other: Conflict, conversion, language, and the we. Sartre Studies International, 15(2), 52–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2011). Realizing freedom: Hegel, Sartre, and the alienation of human being. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2012). Sartre, group formations, and practical freedom in the critique of dialectical reason. Comparative & Continental Philosophy, 3(2), 183–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2013). Overcoming philosophy: Heidegger on the destruction of metaphysics and the transformation to thinking. Human Studies, 36(2), 235–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2014). Ontology in Heidegger and Deleuze. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richmond, S. (2007). Sartre and Bergson: A disagreement about nothingness. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 15(1), 77–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1992). Notebooks for an ethics (D. Pellauer, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2003). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology (H. Barnes, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2004a). Critique of dialectical reason: Vol. I (A. Sheridan-Smith, Trans). London: Verso.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2004b). The imaginary (J. Webber, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2006). Critique of dialectical reason: Vol. II (Q. Hoare, Trans). London: Verso.

  • Sartre, J. P. (2007). What is literature? (B. Frechtman, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Scott, D. (2006). The “concept of time” and the “being of the clock”: Bergson, Einstein, Heidegger, and the interrogation of the temporality of modernism. Continental Philosophy Review, 39(2), 183–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, M. (2014). Inheritance, originality, and the will: Bergson and Heidegger on creation. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 22(5), 655–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprigge, T. (1984). Theories of existence. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theunissen, M. (1984). The other: Studies in the social ontology of Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, and Buber. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gavin Rae.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rae, G. Much Ado About Nothing: The Bergsonian and Heideggerian Roots of Sartre’s Conception of Nothingness. Hum Stud 39, 249–268 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-015-9368-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-015-9368-y

Keywords

Navigation