Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Rational Agent or the Relational Agent: Moving from Freedom to Justice in Migration Systems Ethics

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most accounts of immigration ethics implicitly rely upon neoclassical migration theory, which understands migration as the result of poverty and unemployment in sending countries. This paper argues that neoclassical migration theory assumes an account of the human person as solely an autonomous rational agent which then leads to ethics of migration which overemphasize freedom and self-determination. This tendency to assume that migration works as neoclassical migration theory describes is shared by political philosophers, such as Joseph Carens, Michael Walzer, and David Miller. This paper argues that all three philosophers incorrectly frame migration as a contest between the freedom of the migrant and the communal self-determination of the political community. Migration systems theory is presented as a theory that draws upon a relationally embedded understanding of autonomy in order to begin to develop a migration systems ethics. This paper concludes by arguing that the central ethical category for an ethics of migration is not freedom or self-determination, but justice-in-relation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a thorough review of the literature of each theory, see (Massey et al. 2005) and (Castles and Miller 2009).

  2. An additional explanation for the proliferation of different migration theories is that no one migration theory seems to be able to account for all of the data (Portes 1997: 810; Massey et al. 2005).

  3. For an excellent layperson’s summary of the debates between economists on immigration and its impact on domestic labor markets, see (Lowenstein 2006).

  4. While Borjas does acknowledge that individuals are members of families that often play a role in making decisions about migration, Borjas uses the same assumptions when he makes families the subject of decision-making rather than individuals: “In fact, it is families who enter the immigration market, compare the various offers, and choose the option that maximizes the household’s economic well-being” (Borjas 1990: 188). In this case, it is the family who are the rational actors instead of individuals. Borjas is drawing on the research of migration systems theorists who would not support the neoclassical model by mapping the data onto his own anthropological assumptions.

  5. Borjas attributes this to the fact that the cost of migrating from Sweden to the United States would exceed the small benefit of increased wages (Borjas 1999: 49).

  6. There was some migration from Sweden to the U.S. at the turn of the 20th century. However, the circumstances that began that particular migration flow ended with the Swedish reforms of 1907. Soon after, World War I interrupted that particular migration flow.

  7. See, for example, Skeldon 1997; Sassen 1999: Preface; Massey et al. 2005: 8–11.

  8. For a brief overview of the phenomenon of “brain drain,” see (Carrington 1999)

  9. Walzer does limit Australia’s claim to unoccupied land in the face of tremendous need of its neighbors, but Walzer affirms that Australia could have ceded land without granting admission to non-whites.

  10. For example, see (Rawls 1999: 39n)

  11. There are instances where small migration flows have been initiated by one person or a small group of people. See Kritz and Zlotnik 1992.

  12. For a summary of feminist philosophical critiques of autonomy, see (Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000)

  13. Walzer does acknowledge that guestworker policies have had such unintended consequences, but the continued presence of guestworkers in the territory is presented as an exception to Walzer’s strong account of self-determination and not as a typical example of how migration occurs.

  14. Jean Porter points out this distinction between justice in the thought of Aquinas and justice in the thought of contemporary philosophers like John Rawls (Porter 2002: 277).

  15. For an extensive discussion of social sin and immigration, see (Heyer 2010).

  16. Aquinas does consider the question of the love of the near and distant neighbor, but this is considered under questions about charity, not justice (Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, II-II, Q. 26) (See also Pope 1994: Ch. 2.).

  17. Elsewhere, I have addressed the responsibilities that such relationships generate (Rajendra TM (forthcoming) Justice, not benevolence: catholic social thought, migration theory and the rights of migrants. Political Theology)

  18. For a historical account of deportation in the United States, see (Kanstroom 2007)

  19. This point comes from a conversation with Daniel Kanstroom.

References

  • Borjas GJ (1990) Friends or strangers: the impact of immigrants on the U.S. economy. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Borjas GJ (1999) Heaven’s door: immigration policy and the American economy. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (1987) Aliens and citizens: the case for open borders. Rev Polit 49:251–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (1996) Realistic and idealistic approaches to the ethics of migration. Int Migr Rev 30:156–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (1997) The philosopher and the policy maker: two perspective of the ethics of immigration with special attention to the problem of restricting asylum. In: Hailbronner K, Martin DA, Motumora H (eds) Immigration admissions: the search for workable policies in Germany and the United States. Berghan Books, Providence, pp 3–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (2000) Open borders and liberal limits: a response to Isbister. Int Migr Rev 34(2):636–643

    Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (2003) Who should get in?: the ethics of alien admissions. Ethics Int Aff 17:95–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (2008) Live-in domestics, seasonal workers, and others hard to locate on the map of democracy. J Polit Philos 16:419–445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carens JH (2013) The ethics of immigration. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrington WJ (1999) International migration and the “brain drain.” J Soc Polit and Econ Stud 24:163–171

  • Castles S, Miller MJ (2009) The age of migration: international population movements in the modern world. Guilford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Faist T (2000) The volume and dynamics of international migration and transnational social spaces. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Farley MA (1993) A feminist version of respect for persons. J Fem Stud Relig 9:183–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyer KE (2010) Social sin and immigration: good fences make bad neighbors. Theol Stud 71:410–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanstroom D (2007) Deportation nation: outsiders in American history. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kritz MM, Zlotnik H (1992) Global interactions: migration systems, processes, and policies. In: Kritz MM, Lim LL, Zlotnik H (eds) International migration systems: a global approach. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowenstein R (2006) The immigration equation. Times, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie C, Stoljar N (eds) (2000) Relational autonomy: feminist perspectives on automony, agency, and the social self. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Massey DS, Arango J, Hugo G, Pellegrino A, Taylor JE (2005) Worlds in motion: understanding international migration at the end of the millennium. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller D (2007) National responsibility and global justice. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pope SJ (1994) The evolution of altruism and the ordering of love. Georgetown University Press, Washington, D.C

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter J (2002) The virtue of justice (IIa IIae, qq. 58–122). In: Pope SJ (ed) The ethics of aquinas. Georgetown University Press, Washington, D.C, pp 273–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Portes A (1997) Immigration theory for a new century: some problems and opportunities. Int Migr Rev 31:799–825

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portes A, Böröcz J (1989) Contemporary immigration: theoretical perspectives on its determinants and modes of incorporation. Int Migr Rev 23:606–630

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The law of peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sassen S (1988) The mobility of labor and capital: a study in international investment and labor flow. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sassen S (1996) Losing control?: sovereignty in an age of globalization. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sassen S (1999) Guests and aliens. New Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Skeldon R (1997) Migration and development: a global perspective. Addison-Wesley Longman Higher Education, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M (1983) Spheres of justice: a defense of pluralism and equality. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This article has greatly benefitted from the revisions suggested by Hille Haker, Sandra Sullivan Dunbar, the attendees of the 2012 Conference on Poverty, Coercion and Human Rights at Loyola University Chicago and the anonymous peer reviewers for this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tisha M. Rajendra.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rajendra, T.M. The Rational Agent or the Relational Agent: Moving from Freedom to Justice in Migration Systems Ethics. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 18, 355–369 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9522-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9522-z

Keywords

Navigation