Skip to main content
Log in

Rethinking Pātañjala Yoga Through the Concepts of Abhyāsa and Vairāgya

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a close reading of Patañjali’s Yogasūtra through the concepts of abhyāsa and vairāgya, “repetitive practice” and “dispassion,” drawing on Patañjali’s classical commentators and on Krishnachandra Bhattacharyya’s “Studies in Yoga Philosophy,” an (almost) forgotten chapter of his corpus. I open with a critical examination of Patañjali’s citta-vṛtti scheme, his attempt of “mapping” the contents of consciousness. Thereafter, I discuss the “procedure of yoga,” based on the mutual operation of abhyāsa and vairāgya for the sake of nirodha, cessation of the vṛttis, or “movements” of consciousness. A close analysis of Patañjali and his commentators indicates that both abhyāsa and vairāgya are depicted as consisting of a strong reflective dimension. This is to say that the radical meditative act of “emptying” the consciousness of its objective content is in fact a rational conclusion of the mind, as it reflects upon itself. This reflection is both sensitive to the “limitedness” of the objective world and “receptive” to the silent presence of the “unlimited” selfhood beyond, which Patañjali, following the Sāṃkhya tradition, refers to as puruṣa. It is implied here that the yogic act of disengagement from the worldly and objective (conveyed by the notions of pratyāhāra, vairāgya, and kaivalya) is as much an act of will (emphasized and “taken forward” by Krishnachandra Bhattacharyya), as it is an act of self-sacrifice. Finally, the analysis offered here reveals substantial “philosophical threads” in the Yogasūtra, a text which is usually considered as too “practical,” or “therapeutic,” or “spiritual,” to be “really” philosophical.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I work with the Yogasūtra text as it occurs in Sri Narayana Mishra (1998) and Swami Hariharananda Aranya (2012)

  2. YS 1.3: Hence (when mental activity ceases), the seer is established in his “real essence” (tadā draṣṭuḥ sva-rūpe 'vasthānam). [Unless stated otherwise, the translations from Sanskrit are mine].

  3. Mahāvākya—By referring to Descartes’ famous statement as mahāvākya, “great sentence,” a phrase which “belongs” to Śaṅkara’s “tat tvam asi,” my intention is not just to argue that both sentences are culturally significant, each in its own context, but also that Descartes’ maxim, like Śaṅkara’s, has a transformative quality. Śaṅkara’s sentence, extracted from the sixth chapter of the Chāndogya-Upaniṣad is supposed to enable the listener to cut through the veil of avidyā and to transcend the “phenomenal I.” Descartes’ sentence has had enormous impact on Western formulations of self-identity, emphasizing the importance of, and encouraging the identification with the thinking faculty, with the “I think.” It is not about transcendence of one’s phenomenal existence as in Śaṅkara, but about the definition of one’s phenomenal existence primarily in terms of thinking, marginalizing every other aspect.

  4. Descartes (1911) Third Meditation, p. 12

  5. Aranya (2012) p. 28

  6. Personal communication, September 2015

  7. Bhattacharyya (2008) p. 263

  8. It would be an interesting exercise to read closely the different examples given by Patañjali’s commentators to the language uses which belong to the category of vikalpa. The first example given by Vyāsa is “Caitanya (consciousness) is the nature of puruṣa” (caitanyaṃ puruṣasya svarūpamiti). For him, this sentence is a tautology. Thus tautology can be listed as the first instance of vikalpa, at least according to the Bhāṣya-kāra.

  9. YS 1.16, 1.24, 3.36, 3.50, 3.56, 4.18, 4.34

  10. YS 1.11: anubhūta-viṣaya-asaṃpramoṣaḥ smṛtiḥ

  11. As quoted in Larson (1993) p. 375

  12. Larson (1993) p. 376

  13. Vyāsa is the author of the Yogasūtra-bhāṣya, or at least, this important commentary is ascribed to a scholar by this name, about whom, just like Patañjali, we know literally nothing. Most scholars believe that he was Patañjali’s contemporary or lived shortly after him. Philipp Maas, the praiseworthy compiler of a critical edition of the first chapter of what he refers to as Pātañjala Yogaśāstra, namely Patañjali’s Yogasūtra and Vyāsa's commentary together, argues that Patañjali and Vyāsa are two names of a single author, who assembled sūtras from different sources (Buddhist, Sāṃkhyan, bhakti sūtras on Īśvara etc.) and commented upon them. See Maas (2010).

  14. Aranya (2012) p. 30; Rukmani (1981) p. 80

  15. sukham aham asvāpsam prasannaṃ me manaḥ prajñāṃ me viśāradīkaroti duḥkham aham asvāpsam styānaṃ me mano bhramaty anavasthitam gāḍhaṃ mūḍho 'ham asvāpsam gurūṇi me gātrāṇi klāntaṃ me cittam alasaṃ muṣitam iva tiṣṭhatīti (YSb 1.10). Text and translation are Rukmani's (ibid.)

  16. Bhattacharyya (2008) p. 26

  17. YS 1.12: The cessation of these (vṛttis) is accomplished through repetitive practice and dispassion (abhyāsa-vairāgyābhyāṃ tan-nirodhaḥ)

  18. YS 1.13: tatra sthitau yatno'bhyāsaḥ

  19. YS 1.14: sa tu dīrgha-kāla-nairantarya-satkāra-āsevito dṛḍha-bhūmiḥ

  20. YS 2.33: vitarka-bādhane pratipakṣa-bhāvanam

  21. YS 2.34: vitarkā hiṃsā-ādayaḥ kṛta-kārita-anumoditā lobha-krodha-moha-pūrvakā mṛdu-madhya-adhimātrā duḥkha-ajñāna-ananta-phalā iti pratipakṣa-bhāvanam.

  22. I found this question-answer session in Hebrew translation in the book Awareness and Deathlessness: Questions and Answers with Ramana Maharshi (1935–1939), Gal Publishers, Tel Aviv, 1994. I translate Maharshi’s words from Hebrew into English. Despite the “long distance” (Tamil to English, English to Hebrew, Hebrew back into English), I feel that Ramana’s point is not (totally) “lost in translation,” especially since he uses a simple (but profound) illustration to elucidate the notion of abhyāsa. It should be noted that the context of Ramana Maharshi's discussion is not necessarily Patañjali’s Yogasūtra. The notions of abhyāsa and vairāgya also occur in Bhagavadgītā 6.35.

  23. Ramana Maharshi, Ibid.

  24. Sāṃkhya-kārikā (SK) 19: tasmāc ca viparyāsāt siddhaṃ sākṣitvam asya puruṣasya kaivalyaṃ mādhyasthyaṃ draṣṭṛtvam akartṛbhāvaś ca (Therefore, since [puruṣa is] the opposite [of the unmanifest], it is established that puruṣa is a witness, possessed of isolation or freedom, indifferent, a spectator and inactive). Larson 1979, pp. 261–2. The translation (including the square brackets) is his.

  25. I’m writing “to isolate puruṣa,” having in mind the term kaivalya (literally “isolation”), depicted in SK 19 as one of puruṣa's “inherent traits.”

  26. SK 59: raṅgasya darśayitvā nivartate nartakī yathā nṛtyāt, puruṣasya tathā'tmānaṃ prakāśya vinivartate prakṛtiḥ (As a dancer ceases from the dance after having been seen by the audience; so also prakṛti ceases after having manifested herself to puruṣa). Larson, ibid. p. 273; the translation is his.

  27. I am not delving into the differences between the Upaniṣadic-Advaitic notion of the ātman and the Sāṃkhya-Yoga notion of puruṣa. Despite the obvious differences, such as the oneness of the ātman, as against the manyness of puruṣa (puruṣa-bahutva), both notions refer to a metaphysic essence or selfhood, transcending the phenomenal, worldly self.

  28. Up-Sā 19.2: tataś ca yuktaḥ śama eva te manaḥ (Swami Jagadananda 2001, pp. 288–289)

  29. Tapas is listed both as a component of kriyā-yoga in YS 2.1 and as one of the niyamas in YS 2.32 and YS 2.43; brahmacarya is listed as one of the yamas in YS 2.30 and YS 2.38; śraddhā is mentioned as one of the means of attaining asaṃprajñāta samādhi (“trans-cognitive” samādhi) in YS 1.20; regarding śraddhā, Vyāsa beautifully writes (in YSb 1.20) that it protects the yogin “like a good mother” (jananīva kalyāṇī).

  30. Smṛti is initially memory. However in YS 1.6 Patañjali lists memory among the vṛttis or mental activities which the process of yoga aims at stopping. Vācaspatimiśra therefore suggests (Mishra 1998, p. 62) that in the present case, the term smṛti is synonymous with dhyāna, a preliminary state of meditation which paves the way to samādhi. I translate dhyāna (and smṛti in the sense of dhyāna) as “mindfulness.”

  31. See YS 2.5: anitya-aśuci-duḥkha-anātmasu nitya-śuci-sukha-ātma-khyātir avidyā (avidyā is misidentification of the impermanent as permanent, the impure as pure, the painful as joyous, and non-selfhood as selfhood).

  32. yama-niyamādi-yoga-sādhana-anuṣṭhānam-abhyāsa-iti (Rukmani 2001, p. 77)

  33. YS 3.9: vyutthāna-nirodha-saṃskārayor abhibhava-prādur-bhāvau nirodha-kṣaṇa-citta-anvayo nirodha-pariṇāmaḥ

  34. Pātañjalayogadarśana with the Rājamārtaṇda of Bhojarāja et al. (1930)

  35. YS 1.15: dṛṣṭa-ānuśravika-viṣaya-vitṛṣṇasya vaśīkāra-saṃjñā vairāgyam

  36. YS 1.16: tat-param puruṣa-khyāter-guṇa-vaitṛṣṇyam

  37. The commentators distinguish between “apara” and “para,” “lower” and “ultimate” vairāgya. See for instance Vācaspatimiśra (TV 1.16 in Mishra 1998, p. 52) and the author of the Vivaraṇa (Rukmani 2001, p.80)

  38. See YS 1.19: bhava-pratyayo videha-prakṛti-layānām ([In the case of] “bodiless” and “merged into prakṛti” yogins, [samādhi] occurs from birth [hence the “path” depicted by Patañjali becomes redundant]).

  39. KCB’s “Studies in Yoga Philosophy” (unpublished in his lifetime) is included in his collected essays Studies in Philosophy (1958, 2008) edited by his son Gopinath Bhattacharyya. It is the text of one of his last lecture series and is hardly referred to by those who write on KCB’s philosophical work. They usually focus on his earlier writings on Emmanuel Kant and Advaita Vedānta, as well as on his acclaimed essay “The Subject as Freedom.” The important place of “Studies in Yoga Philosophy” in KCB’s corpus is yet to be highlighted.

  40. Bhattacharyya (2008) p. 303

  41. KCB works with freedom in the realm of knowledge through Advaita-Vedānta and Sāṃkhya. He thinks of freedom in the emotive realm through Rasa aesthetics. And through Pātañjala-yoga and Kant’s philosophy, he conceptualizes freedom in the realm of action.

  42. Tattvavaiśāradī 1.15 (Mishra 1998 p. 62)

  43. Rukmani (2001) p. 79

  44. See for example Vijñānabhikṣu (Rukmani 1981, p. 98), who quotes an unknown source, or paraphrases a general saying, according to which doṣa-darśanena vaitṛṣṇyam bhavati (it is the observation of a flaw, or a defect, which leads to thirstlessness).

  45. Bhattacharyya (2008) p. 306

  46. BG 6.35: asaṃśayaṃ mahābāho mano durnigrahaṃ calaṃ |abhyāsena tu kaunteya vairāgyeṇa ca gṛhyate || (see Śrīmadbhagavadgītā Śankara-bhāṣya, 1976)

  47. Berlin (1969)

  48. Mishra (1998), p. 52; the three guṇas or “forces”, which “activate” prakṛti, namely sattva, rajas and tamas, are referred to by Patañjali (in YS 2.18) as prakāśa (brightness), kriyā (action) and sthiti (inertia).

  49. Bhattacharyya (2008) pp. 303–304

  50. YS 2.54: sva-viṣaya-asaṃprayoge cittasya sva-rūpa-anukāra iva-indriyāṇāṃ pratyāhāraḥ

  51. YS 2.55: tataḥ paramā vaśyatā-indriyāṇām

  52. SK 62: tasmān na badhyate 'addhā na mucyate nā 'pi saṃsarati kaścit, saṃsarati badhyate mucyate ca nānāśrayā prakṛtiḥ (Larson 1979, p. 274; the translation is his, the square brackets are mine).

References

Source texts in Sanskrit

  • Pātañjalayogadarśana with the Rājamārtaṇda of Bhojarāja, Pradīpikā of Bhāvāgaṇeśa, Vṛtti of Nāgojībhaṭṭa, Maṇiprabhā of Rāmānanda Yati, Padacandrikā of Anantadeva Pandit, and Yogasudhākara of Sadāśivendra Sarasvatī (1930). Varanasi: Caukhambā Vidyābhavan.

  • Pātañjalayogadarśanam with Vyāsa’s Bhāṣya, Vācasptimiśra’s Tattvavaiśāradī and Vijñānabhikṣu’s Yogavārttika (1998). Mishra, Sri Narayaṇa (Ed.), Varanasi and Delhi: Bhāratīya Vidyā Prakāśan.

  • Yogasūtra, P., Yogasūtra-bhāṣya, V., & Hariharananda, A.S. (2012). Yoga Philosophy of Patañjali with Bhāsvatī. Kolkata: University of Calcutta Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Śrīmadbhagavadgītā Śān karabhāsya (1976). Śrī Harikṛṣṇadās Goyandakā (ed.), Gorakhpur: Gita Press.

The Yogasūtra and its commentaries in translation

  • Karambelkar, P.V. (2008). Pātañjala Yoga Sūtra, Lonavla: Kaivalyadhama.

  • Feuerstein, G. (1989). [1979] The Yoga-Sūtra of Patañjali: A New Translation and Commentary, Vermont: Inner Traditions India.

  • Rukmani, T.S. (2001). Yogasūtrabhāṣyavivaraṇa of Śankara (Vol. I&II). New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rukmani, T.S. (1981–89). Yogavārttika of Vijñāna Bhikṣu: Text with English Translation and Critical Notes along with Text and English Translation of the Pātañjala Yogasūtras and Vyāsabhāṣya, Vol. 1: Samādhipāda (1981); Vol. 2: Sādhanapāda (1983); Vol. 3: Vibhūtipāda (1987); Vol. 4: Kaivalyapāda (1989), New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal.

  • Taimni, I.K. (1993). The Science of Yoga: The Yoga-Sūtras of Patañjali — Text and Commentary, Adyar, Madras: The Theosophical Publishing House.

  • Woods, J.H. (1998). [1914] The Yoga-System of Patañjali or the Ancient Hindu Doctrine of Concentration of Mind, Embracing the Mnemonic Rules Called Yoga-Sūtras of Patañjali and the Comment Called Yoga-Bhāṣya Attributed to Veda-Vyāsa and the Explanation Called Tattva-Vāiśāradī of Vācaspati Miśra, Harvard Oriental Series, Reprinted in Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

Other sources

  • Berlin, I. (1969). “Two concepts of liberty”, in his four essays on liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bhattacharyya, K. (2008). Studies in philosophy volumes I&II. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

  • Carpenter, D. (2003). Practice makes perfect: The role of practice (Abhyāsa) in Pātañjala-yoga. In I. Whicher, D. Carpenter (Eds.), Yoga: The Indian tradition (pp. 25--50).

  • Chakrabarti, A. (2002). Logic, morals and meditation: tarka, dharma, yoga. http://www.infinityfoundation.com/Chakrabarti_A.pdf.

  • Chapple, C. (2008). Yoga and the luminous. Albany: State University of New York Press.

  • Descartes, R. (1911). [1641] Meditations on First Philosophy (trans: Haldane, E. S.). In The philosophical works of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://selfpace.uconn.edu/class/percep/DescartesMeditations.pdf.

  • Descartes, R. (1644). Principles of Philosophy (trans: Miller, V. R., Miller, R. P. (1983)). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Halbfass, W. (1992). India and Europe: An essay in philosophical understanding. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

  • Jagadananda, S. (2001). Upadeśa Sāhasrī — A Thousand Teachings of Sri Śaṛkarācārya (ed. and trans: Jagadananda, S.). Chennai: Sri Ramakrishna Math.

  • Krishna, D. (1989). Comparative philosophy: What is it and what it ought to be? In G. J. Larson, E. Deutsch (Eds.), Interpreting across boundaries: New essays in comparative philosophy (pp. 71--83) Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

  • Krishna, D. (2006a). Indian philosophy: A counter perspective, Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications.

  • Krishna, D. (2006b). The yoga-sūtras: The undeciphered text – anomalies, problems and paradoxes. In Indian philosophy – a counter-perspective (pp. 204--223).

  • Larson, G.J. (1979). Classical Sāmkhya: an interpretation of its history and meaning. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, G.J. (1993). The Trimūrti of Smṛti in classical indian thought. Philosophy East and West, 43.3, 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maas, P.A. (2010). On the written transmission of the Pātañjalayogaśāstra. In J. Bronkhorst, K. Preisendanz (Eds.), From Vasubandhu to Caitanya: Studies in Indian philosophy and its textual history (Papers of the 12th World Sanskrit Conference, Vol. 10.1), pp. 157–172.

  • Whicher, I. (2000). The integrity of the yoga darśana: A reconsideration of classical yoga. New Delhi: D.K. Printworld.

  • Whicher, I., & Carpenter, D. (Eds.) (2003). Yoga: The Indian tradition. London: Routledge Curzon.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Raveh.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Raveh, D. Rethinking Pātañjala Yoga Through the Concepts of Abhyāsa and Vairāgya. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 32, 319–333 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-015-0036-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-015-0036-4

Keywords

Navigation