Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-sxzjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T10:18:51.460Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why Is There Universal Macrobehavior? Renormalization Group Explanation as Noncausal Explanation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Renormalization group (RG) methods are an established strategy to explain how it is possible that microscopically different systems exhibit virtually the same macrobehavior when undergoing phase transitions. I argue—in agreement with Robert Batterman—that RG explanations are noncausal explanations. However, Batterman misidentifies the reason that RG explanations are noncausal: it is not the case that an explanation is noncausal if it ignores causal details. I propose an alternative argument, according to which RG explanations are noncausal explanations because their explanatory power is due to the application of mathematical operations, which do not serve the purpose of representing causal relations.

Type
Complex Systems
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank, in particular, Robert Batterman, Laura Franklin-Hall, Andreas Hüttemann, James Ladyman, Marc Lange, John Norton, John T. Roberts, Michael Strevens, Jessica Wilson, all of the fellows at the Center for Philosophy of Science in Pittsburgh (during the academic year 2012/13), and an audience in Cologne for discussing earlier drafts of this paper. I am also grateful to Maria Kronfeldner for a stimulating and thought-provoking discussion on renormalization group explanations.

References

Batterman, Robert. 2000. “Multiple Realizability and Universality.” British Journal for Philosophy of Science 51:115–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batterman, Robert 2002. The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction and Emergence. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert 2010. “On the Explanatory Role of Mathematics in Empirical Science.” British Journal for Philosophy of Science 61:125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bueno, Otàvio, and French, Steven. 2011. “Can Mathematics Explain Physical Phenomena?British Journal for Philosophy of Science 63:85113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butterfield, Jeremy. 2011. “Less Is Different: Emergence and Reduction Reconciled.” Foundations of Physics 41:1065–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1989. Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Craver, Carl. 2007. Explaining the Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, Michael. 1982. “Scaling, University and Renormalization Group Theory.” In Critical Phenomena, ed. Hahne, F., 1139. Lecture Notes in Physics 186. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1997. “Special Sciences. Still Autonomous after All These Years.” Philosophical Perspectives 11:149–63.Google Scholar
Franklin-Hall, Laura. 2014. “The Causal Economy Account of Scientific Explanation.” Unpublished manuscript, New York University.Google Scholar
Hüttemann, Andreas, Kühn, Reimer, and Terzidis, Orestis. Forthcoming. “Stability, Emergence and Part-Whole Reduction.” In Why More Is Different: Philosophical Issues in Condensed Matter Physics and Complex Systems, ed. Brigitte Falkenburg and Margaret Morrison. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Ladyman, James, and Ross, Don. 2007. Every Thing Must Go. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2013. “What Makes a Scientific Explanation Distinctively Mathematical?British Journal for Philosophy of Science 64:485511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, Margaret. 2012. “Emergent Physics and Micro-Ontology.” Philosophy of Science 79:141–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, John. 2007. “Causation as Folk Science.” In Price and Corry 2007, 1144.Google Scholar
Norton, John 2012. “Approximation and Idealization: Why the Difference Matters.” Philosophy of Science 79:207–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, Huw, and Corry, Richard, eds. 2007. Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Reutlinger, Alexander. Forthcoming. “Are Causal Facts Really Explanatorily Emergent? Ladyman and Ross on Higer-Level Causal Facts and Renormalization Group Explanation.” Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0530-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shimony, Abner. 1993. Search for a Naturalistic World View: Natural Science and Metaphysics. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2003. Bigger than Chaos. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael 2008. Depth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica. 2010. “Non-reductive Physicalism and Degrees of Freedom.” British Journal for Philosophy of Science 61:279311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James. 2003. Making Things Happen. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James 2010. “Causation in Biology: Stability, Specificity, and the Choice of Levels of Explanation.” Biology and Philosophy 25:287318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar