Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Planning Facts Through Law: Legal Reasonableness as Creative Indexicality and Trans-categorical Re-configuration

  • Published:
International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue internationale de Sémiotique juridique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Legal reasonableness and its theoretical analysis are often gauged on judicial activity. However, the judicial exercise of reasonableness is always a post-factum activity. People produce facts, and then courts are called to ascertain and qualify their conduct to determine its legal consequences. The use of reasonableness appears, in this way, almost inherently grafted onto a pre-existing divide between facts and legal rules. Reasonableness would appear to be mainly engaged in the balancing of the semantic spectrums of law’s provisions and their underlying axiological legitimations. To put it diversely, reasonableness seems to be confined within the semantic fluctuations of a major premise of syllogism and only indirectly focused on its minor premise and the translation of facts in legal terms. I think this traditional approach is defective. Its defectiveness is due, in my view, to a lack of semiotic awareness in the assumptions made by judges about what facts are and the resulting tendency to produce ossified understandings. If, instead, legal interpreters were to consider facts as epitomes of signical chains that are thus open to a narrative unwinding, the categorization of facts and the creative remolding of the semantic spectrum of legal enunciations would reveal their interpenetration. Narrations make visible the implicit deictic dimension inherent in the symbolic representation of facts and actions, as well as the signical webs in which such empirical ‘data’ are embedded. These expanded landscapes of multifarious properties and connotations—if traversed far and wide by the interpreters—tend to proffer new and unexpected axes of semantic/legal qualification. This is because the newly emerging properties are often pertinent to various phrastic parts of different legal enunciations (and the lexemes they comprise, as well), thereby urging a renewed assessment of their categorical borders and criteria of trans-categorical relevance. In this sense, reasonableness can function as a chisel to proactively mold the world of experience rather than as a rhetorical device that is only applied to previously defined rules and empirical categories. Indeed, this is exactly what occurs, even more intensively, when legal practitioners provide legal assistance to their clients before and outside the courts. In many cases, when clients are informed about the legal consequences of their actions, they undertake—even if unawares—a semiotic/indexical re-assessment of their potential conduct; they re-plan the factual/behavioral chains designed to pursue their interests and achieve their ends. In this way, they become able to produce facts through law. If taken together, legal education, a semiotic understanding of facts, and a widespread use of pre-litigation legal assistance might cast new light on the potentialities of legal experience, if not its own socio-political and even cognitive significance. From this angle, therefore, improving the semiotic analysis of the life of law is a crucial step on the path toward new ways of rethinking the relationships between legal discourse and the making of the social world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this regard, it is to be observed from the outset that rationality and reasonableness are sometimes declined, respectively in the legal domain and in moral theory, with different, if not even opposite, meanings. In moral theory—see, for example, [29, 30, 83] rationality is intended as a means/ends (individualistic) standard for efficient action; reasonableness, conversely, as an inclusive strategy to carry out one’s own conduct. In law—see, for example, [1]—rationality pertains to general scheme of action meanwhile reasonableness is related, usually, to the solution of specific cases, even if such solutions are then considered according to a comprehensive horizon of values/ends. This is due to the assumption that legal provisions must embody generality that results from previous axiological and teleological balancing between individual goals and preferences. Reasonableness coincides, instead, with the derogation and/or the exception with respect to the general schemes included in legal provisions and logical inferences that any judge could/should draw from them to make a decision on the case.

  2. The idea that any act of communication entails, at least, an implicit translation goes back to St. Augustine, and pervasively imbues Peirce’s semiotics. It is also the leitmotiv of comparative literary theory as seen in Steiner’s After Babel [84], just to recall a few examples.

  3. It would be very interesting to compare this hypothetical benefit with the moral philosophical positions that assume, in their analysis of rational and/or reasonable conduct, the agent’s self-centered ‘consideration’ as a normative standpoint. See, in this regard, [16, 31, 77, 88]. For a criticism of these positions, sometimes dubbed as ‘reason’s fundamentalism,’ [22, 79] or ‘fundamentalist justificationism’ [24] see [22, 42, 43, 78,79,80].

  4. As for the distinction between ‘phrastic’ and ‘neustic’ in deontic propositions, see [33].

  5. Even the overall debate on the figure of ‘reasonable man’—see, for example, [49]—is developed by assuming the judicial point of view. Things completely change, however, when the agent’s perspective is taken into account as such—namely outside a judicial context—as a standpoint for moral philosophical analysis: see, for example, [12,13,14, 28,29,30].

  6. Space limitations do not allow for an adequate treatment of the complexities of the relations between various languages and the issue of self-referentiality within a semiotic universe here. However, a more extensive examination from a semio-legal point of view can be found in [73] and there for further bibliographical references.

  7. I addressed this issue in elsewhere [73] from a semiotic legal point of view [32]. In the specific domain of legal theory, as regards the terms of the issues concerning the constitutiveness of legal language with respect to the ‘fact’ and the relationships between legal language and natural/common language, as well as legal truth and natural truth, see [41, 50: p. 49 ff., 89, 90: p. 131 ff., 56, 57]. These authors, despite the different nuances of their arguments, see ‘facts’ under the lens of law as legal or institutional facts constitutively semanticized by legal discourse. At the other extreme, there are those who consider legal judgment to be a declaratory activity/function and consider it much like an empirical ascertainment [3], or a social fact [75] to be considered from a ‘realistic’ sociological point of view. As will emerge below, I take neither one position nor the other precisely because of my approach, inspired by both Peircean semiotics and Deweyian cognitive instrumentalism (among other philosophies and linguistic theories as enactivism, language embodiment, cognitive grammar) concerning ‘what facts are’ and how they are ‘made meaningful’ by human beings (and their action).

  8. Hereinafter I will refer to the factual element taken as a pre-condition (e.g.: someone did action X) of legal qualification (e.g. a contract, a murderer) included in the legal rules whenever I discuss the applicability of the so-called truth-values or truth-value semantics to legal reasoning, judgments, argumentation and justification.

  9. For a recent analysis of the strengths and weaknesses of ‘common sense’ see [18]; as for the legal uses of this paradigm [54]. An interesting investigation in the close intertwining of intuition, instinct and common sense in Peirce’s idea of cognition/investigation can be found in [11].

  10. ‘Sinsemics’ and ‘sinsemia’ refer to conceptual cartographies or maps and their use in supporting reasoning, conceptualization, learning, planning, and so on. See [60] and https://synsemia.org. On average, conceptual maps are drawn according to a hierarchical logic, often projected on a two-dimensional plane and depicted as a kind of web featuring a center-periphery representation and operational order. By contrast, I imagine sinsemic relationships as characterized by mobile geographies such that the center can move continually according to an index of salience suggested by the emersion of trans-categorical relationships. This approach translates in legal terms the logical and figurative dynamics adopted, for example, by Al-Jāḥiẓ [2, 72] and Klee [69].

  11. I am fully aware that preventive legal advice can also be aimed to supply interpretations or solutions capable of eluding legal control. Nonetheless, any resort to a literal interpretation of legal rules so as to avert this misuse of the preventive legal advice runs the risk of proving worse than the original problem. This is precisely because a literal interpretation/combination of rules is the main device used to construe and underpin solutions arranged in order to formalistically bypass, and/or immunize themselves from, legal control and bans [51]; in many cases, paradoxically, this is in sharp contrast with the values/ends underlying and legitimating the same rules involved in supplying the elusive advice. To a certain extent, however, purposiveness in legal interpretation cannot be avoided or neutralized [90: p. 265 ff., 9]. Sometimes, as for intercultural issues, that purposiveness can even be (paradoxically) ‘unaware,’ but not for this reason is it less partisan, discriminating and substantially illegal and/or illegitimate. All depends on the role played by, and the use of, the principles and values/ends at the legal system’s apex in translating people’s needs and interests in legal terms. As for the analysis of this topic, space requirements, however, compel me to refer to other works [67, 71].

  12. I prefer to use here the expression ‘what to do’ rather than the more typical, at least in legal discourse, ‘what is to be done’ or ‘what should be done’ precisely to emphasize the planning prospection inherent in the preventive use of law. It would be very interesting to compare this approach with a philosophic moral analysis of rationality and reasonableness focused on the ‘planning moment’ of rational choices. See, for example, [12,13,14]: pointing out, however, that the overall inspiration of my approach is not exactly in tune with his theoretical view. This distance increases further with regard to the so-called ‘Planning Theory of Law’ elaborated by [82] (somehow an adherent of Bratman’s proposal), which is as far from my approach because of the semantic/normative (or even vaguely authoritarian) rigidity of his approach to ends and the realted denial of any means/ends dialectics applicable to the meaning of legal statements

  13. In this regard, it is enough to check what scholars who are engaged in a multiculturalist approach to legal experience mean when using the expression ‘culture matters for justice.’ See, for example, [62, 63].

  14. The Qur’an verses about the ‘veil’ are consequentially translated (with specific regard to the ‘hijab’) as if they impel Muslim women, as a matter of fact, to wear pieces of cloth on their heads. In this way, however, all the semantic, psychological, social, etc. implications related to the ‘hijab’ are completely ‘made invisible’ (and not only ‘lost’) in translation. Contrastively, I would like to raise the following question: ‘What if on a day the hijabs were placed in the showcases of (western) dress shops among other garments and other kinds of headgear?’ What should be, in that case, their significance? What about this ‘categorical migration’ and its socio-legal consequences?

  15. As for the veil, see SAS v. France, 2014-III Eur. Ct. H.R. 341; Dakir v. Belgium, App. No. 4619/12 (Eur. Ct. H.R. July 11, 2017); Belcacemi and Oussar v. Belgium, App. No. 37798/13 (Eur. Ct. H.R. July 11, 2017): even if the decisions were based on the ban of the niqab (which also covers the face), they engendered many social consequences on the possibility to wear the hijab, at least in some countries. As for the kirpan, I refer to [71]. On hijab in workplaces judged as a religious symbols in contrast with a ‘legitimate’ ban on the wearing of political, philosophical or religious sign/symbols, see Court of Justice of the European Union—No 30/17 Luxembourg, 14 March 2017. In this regard, for more information, see https://webcache.googleusercontent.com/search?q=cache:eUaC6j7m9BkJ, https://ec.europa.eu/newsroom/just/document.cfm%3Faction%3Ddisplay%26doc_id%3D48810+&cd=5&hl=it&ct=clnk&gl=it.

  16. It would be very interesting, but also tremendously instructive, to compare the above considerations about the legal categorization of the kirpan with the observations about the categorization of ‘a knife’ and the legal interpretive problems related to the use of discretion and/or reasonableness proposed by Hart many years ago [35: p. 654 ff.].

  17. It could be very constructive here to recall what two scholars observed some years ago about the application of analytical legal logic to case-law experience [24: p. 275]: ‘Precisely because of their ‘formal inclination’, logicians concern themselves in principle only with the truth of the premises of an argument insofar as this truth depends on the form of the statements in which the premises are expressed. Logicians regard an argument form as valid only if no substitution instance of this argument form with true premises ever produces an untrue conclusion. This, however, does not mean that they are interested in truth values as such, let alone that they support the ideal model of knowledge referred to by Toulmin as ‘the Eternal City of well-founded truths.’’ See, also [79: p. 519 ff.].

  18. This almost paradoxical consequence—namely a plurality of (aspiring) self-centered universalisms—can be instructively paralleled to the implications of a pluralistic ‘reasons fundamentalism’ [22] gushing out as a reaction to the ‘pure formalization of logic’ [79: pp. 519 ff; esp. 523–524] that the history of ‘Western Reason’ produced in the last century.

  19. For an intercultural translational-transactional solution to the ‘kirpan’ case, as such also available for the ‘hijab’ case, see [67, 71]. I would like, also, to mark the distance between this cognitive transformative/transactional approach [20, 21] and the neo-Kantian one underlying the arguments developed in [83].

  20. Even if before the courts or dealing with other state institutions all the relationships between people from different cultures, as well as those between individuals and state institutions and even the infra-cultural/infra-communitarian ones, become, at least potentially, intercultural. [67].

  21. As for the intercultural and universalizing use of human and/or fundamental rights that can exploit for inclusive purposes their semantic vagueness and the plasticity inherent in the ends they encapsulate see [65, 66, 68, 70, 71]. More specifically as regards the danger of an excluding use of human and/or fundamental rights by passing off identity with universality see [65, 68].

  22. I draw this from an ethnographical-legal survey carried out in the field on a sample of Italian notaries [74] spread over the whole national territory.

  23. I developed—as scientific coordinator—a project pioneering a legal-pedagogical action in collaboration with the Italian National Bar Association (CNF) and MIUR (Italian Department of Education and Science) with the legislative framework of the so-called ‘Work-Related Learning.’ The project draft can be found at https://www.consiglionazionaleforense.it/web/cnf/scuola-lavoro?p_p_id=101_INSTANCE_CdMynPmsVwKI.

  24. As if to say that only the formation of the experiential datum constitutes categories as a priori with respect to the unfolding of knowledge, so establishing their inherent co-implication.

  25. Divina Commedia: Paradiso, Canto XXII, vv. 133–138; 151–154. English translation ‘I turned my gaze back through each and every one of the seven spheres, and saw this globe, so that I smiled at its pitiful semblance, and I approve that wisdom greatest which considers it least: since he whose thoughts are directed elsewhere may be called truly noble.

    […] The threshing-floor that makes us so fierce, appeared to me from mountains to river-mouth, as I revolved with the eternal Twins: then I turned my eyes to the lovely eyes again. The complete translation of the Chant can be found at https://www.poetryintranslation.com/PITBR/Italian/DantPar22to28.php#anchor_Toc64099969.

  26. My italics: so as to emphasize the comprehensive self-reflexiveness of the sentence and, in spite of appearances, its projection into the future. In this regard, for some cues [81].

References

  1. Aarnio, Aulis. 1987. The Rational as Reasonable: A Treatise on Legal Justification. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Al-Jāḥiẓ (Abu Uthman Amr ibn Bahr al-Kinani al-Basr). 2012. Kitab al-Hayawan. 2/VII vol. Beirut: Dar Al Kitab Al Arabi (partial French transtlation: Al- Jāḥiẓ. 2003. Le livre des animaux. Fayard: Paris).

  3. Alchourrón, Carlos, and E. Emilio Bulygin. 2015. Limits of Law and Legal Reasoning (1992). In Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. Emilio Bulygin, 252–271. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Alexy, Robert. 2002. A Theory of Constitutional Rights. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Alexy, Robert. 2009. The Reasonableness of the Law. In Reasonableness and Law, ed. Bongiovanni Giorgio, Sartor Giovanni, and Valentini Chiara, 3–15. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Alexy, Robert. 2009. A Theory of Legal Argumentation: The Theory of Rational Discourse as Theory of Legal Justification. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Aroso Linhares, José M. 2017. O Binómio casos fáceis/casos difíceis e a categoria de inteligibilidade sistema jurídico: Um contraponto indispensável no mapa do discurso jurídico contemporâneo?. Coimbra: Coimbra University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Atienza, Miguel. 1990. On The Reasonable in Law. Ratio Juris 3(1): 148–161.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Barak, Aharon. 2005. Purposive Interpretation in Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Bertea, Stefano. 2004. Certainty, Reasonableness and Argumentation in Law. Arguments 18: 465–478. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-004-5890-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Boyd, Kenneth, and Diana Heney. 2017. Peirce on Intuition, Instinct, and Common Sense. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Bratman, Michael E. 1999. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge, MA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bratman, Michael E. 2013. Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Bratman, Michael E. 2018. Planning, Time, and Self-Governance: Essays in Practical Rationality. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cosgrove, Denis E. 2001. Apollo’s Eye: A Cartographic Genealogy Genealogy of the Earth in the Western Imagination. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Dancy, Jonathan. 2006. Ethics Without Principles. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Danesi, Marcel. 2012. The Languages of the Law: An integrated View from Vico and Conceptual Metaphor Theory. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 25: 95. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9250-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Delaney, Tim. 2019. Common Sense as a Paradigm of Thought: An Analysis of Social Interaction. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Dewey, John. 1938. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Dewey, John, and Arthur F. Bentley. 1949. Knowing and the Known. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Di Paolo, Ezequiel, Hanne De Jaegher, and Elena C. Cuffaro. 2018. Linguistic Bodies: The Continuity Between Life and Language. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Dreier, Jamie. 2014. Can Reasons Fundamentalism Answer the Normative Question? In Motivational Internalism, ed. G. Björnsson et al., 167–181. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Dworkin, Ronald. 1975. Hard Cases. Harvard Law Review 88(6): 1057–1109.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Eemeren, Frans H. van, and Grootendorst Rob. 1988. Rationale For a Pragma-Dialectical Perspective. Argumentation 2: 271–291.

  25. Engisch, Karl. 1963. Logische Studien zur Gesetzesanwendung. Heidelberg: Carl Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Esser, Josef. 1972. Vorverständnis und Methodenwahl in der Rechtsfindung. Rationalitätsgrundlagen richterlicher Entscheidungspraxis. Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 2013. Truth and Method. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Gewirth, Alan. 1980. Reason and Morality. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Gewirth, Alan. 1983. The Rationality of Reasonableness. Synthese 57: 225–247. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf01064003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Gewirth, Alan. 1991. Can any Final Ends be Rational? Ethics 102(1): 66–95.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Gibbard, Allan. 1992. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Greimas, A. J. 1983. Du Sens II—Essais semiotiques. Paris: Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Hare, Richard M. 1963. The Language of Morals. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hart, Herbert L. A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Hart, Herbert L. A. 2013. Discretion. Harvard Law Review 127: 652–665.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Hassemer, Winfried. 1968. Tatbestand und Typus. Untersuchungen zur strafrechtlichen Hermeneutik. Köln-Berlin-Bonn-München: Carl Heymanns.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Hevia, Martin. 2012. Reasonableness and Responsibility: A Theory of Contract Law. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Howes, David. 2003. Sensual Relations: Engaging the Senses in Culture and Social Theory. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Howes, David, and Classen Constance. 2014. Ways of Sensing: Understanding the Senses in Society. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Kaufmann, Arthur. 1982. Analogie und “Natur der Sache”. Zugleich ein Beitrag zur Lehre vom Typus. Heidelberg: Decker & Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Kelsen, Hans. 2009. Pure Theory of Law. Clark, NJ: Lawbook Exchange.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Kiesewetter, Benjamin. 2017. The Normativity of Rationality. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Kiesewetter, Benjamin. 2018. What Kind of Perspectivism? Journal of Moral Philosophy 15(4): 415–443.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kriele, Martin. 1976. Theorie der Rechtsgewinnung, entwickelt am Problem der Verfassungsinterpretation. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Lakoff, George P. 1987. Women, Fire and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Larenz, Karl. 1991. Methodenlehre der Rechtswissenschaft. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Liszt, Franz von. 2002. Der Zweckgedanke im Strafrecht (1882/83). Baden-Baden: Nomos.

  48. MacCormick, Neil. 1984. On Reasonableness. In Les notions à contenu variable en droit, ed. C. Perelman and R. Vanderelst, 131–156. Bruxelles: Bruylant.

    Google Scholar 

  49. MacCormick, Neil. 1999. Reasonableness and Objectivity. Notre Dame Law Review 74(5): 1575–1603.

    Google Scholar 

  50. MacCormick, Neil, and Weinberger Ota. 1986. An Institutional Theory of Law. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  51. McBarnet, Doreen, and Whelan Cristopher. 1991. The Elusive Spirit of the Law: Formalism and the Struggle for Legal Control. The Modern Law Review 54(6): 848–873.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Miller, Jeannie. 2013. More Than the Sum of its Parts: Animal Categories and Accretive Logic in Volume One of Al- Jāḥiẓ’s Kitāb al-Ḥayawān. Ph.D. Dissertation, Department of Middle Eastern and Islamic Studies, New York University.

  53. Modood, Tariq. 2019. Essays on Secularism and Multiculturalism. London: Rowman & Littlefeld.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Moran, Mayo. 2003. Rethinking the Reasonable Person: An Egalitarian Reconstruction of the Objective Standard. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Nyström, Maria, and Karin Dahlberg. 2001. Pre-understanding and Openness—A Relationship Without Hope? Scandinavian Journal of Caring Sciences 15(4): 339–346.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Peczenik, Aleksander. 1968. Norms and Reality. Theoria 34(2): 117–133.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Peczenik, Aleksander. 1989. On Law and Reason. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Peirce, Charles S. 1998. Pragmatism. In The Essential Peirce, ed. Peirce Edition Project. Vol. II, Id. 398–433. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  59. Perelman, C. 1979. The Rational and the Reasonable. In The New Rhetoric and the Humanities. Essays on Rhetoric and its Applications, Id., ed. Jaakko Hintikka, 117–123. Dordrecht: Springer.

  60. Perondi, Luciano. 2012. Sinsemie. Scrittura nello spazio. Rome: Stampa Alternativa.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Porcello, Thomas. 2010. The Reorganization of the Sensory World. Annual Review of Anthropology 39: 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Renteln, Alison D. 2004. The Cultural Defense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Renteln, Alison D. 2010. Making Room for Culture in the Court. The Judges Journal 49(2): 7–15.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Renteln, Alison D., and Foblets Marie-Claire (eds.). 2009. Multicultural Jurisprudence: Comparative Perspectives on the Cultural Defense. Oxford: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ricca, Mario. 2008. Oltre Babele. Codici per una democrazia interculturale. Bari: Dedalo.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ricca, Mario. 2013. Culture interdette. Modernità, migrazioni, diritto interculturale. Torino: Bollati boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ricca, Mario. 2014. Intercultural Law, Interdisciplinary Outlines: Lawyering and Anthropological Expertise in Migration Cases Before the Courts. In E/C Rivista Telematica dell‟Associazione Italiana di Studi Semiotici. 1–53. http://www.ec-aiss.it/index_d.php?recordID=709. Accessed March 3, 2020.

  68. Ricca, Mario. 2016. The Intercultural Use of Human Rights and Legal Chorology. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2807424 or https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2807424. Accessed January 14, 2020.

  69. Ricca, Mario. 2016. Klee’s Cognitive Legacy and Human Rights As Intercultural Transducers: Modern Art, Legal Translation, and Micro-Spaces of Coexistence. In CalumetIntercultural Law and Humanities Review. 1–40. http://www.windogem.it/calumet/upload/pdf2/mat_51.pdf. Accessed January 13, 2020.

  70. Ricca, Mario. 2018. Cultures in Orbit, or Justi-fying Differences in Cosmic Space: On Categorization, Territorialization and Rights Recognition. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 31: 829–875. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-018-9578-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  71. Ricca, Mario. 2018. Ignorantia Facti Excusat: Legal Liability and the Intercultural Significance of Greimas’ “Contrat de Véridition”. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 31: 101–126. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-017-9529-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Ricca, Mario. 2019. Signs across Races: Al-Jahiz’s Cosmo-semiosis and His Trans-racial Mapping of the “Human”. In Calumet—Intercultural Law and Humanities Review, 21 Aug 2019. http://www.windogem.it/calumet/upload/pdf2/mat_82.pdf. Accessed January 12, 2020.

  73. Ricca, Mario. 2020. Perpetually Astride Eden’s Boundaries: The Limits to the ‘Limits of Law’ and the Semiotic Inconsistency of ‘Legal Enclosures’. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law (forthcoming).

  74. Ricca, Mario, and Tommaso, Sbriccoli. 2015. Notariato e diritto interculturale. Un viaggio giuridico-antropologico tra i notai d’Italia. In CalumetIntercultural Law and Humanities Review. 1–49. http://www.windogem.it/calumet/upload/pdf/mat_35.pdf. Accessed January 12, 2020.

  75. Ross, Alf. 2019. On Law and Justice. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Sartor, Giovanni. 2009. A Sufficientist Approach to Reasonableness in Legal Decision-Making and Judicial Review. In Reasonableness and Law, eds. Giorgio, B., Sartor, G., and C. Valentini, 17–68. New York: Springer

  77. Scanlon, Thomas M. 2013. Being Realistic about Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Schafer, Karl. 2017. Rational as the Capacity for Understanding. Nous 53(3): 639–663. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Schafer, Karl. 2018. A Brief History of Rationality: Reason, Reasonableness, Rationality, and Reasons. Manuscrito: Revista International de Filosofia (Campinas) 41(4): 501–529. https://doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2018.v41n4.ks.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Schafer, Karl. 2018. Constitutivism about Reason: Autonomy and Understanding. In The Many Moral Rationalisms, ed. Karen Jones and François Schroeter, 70–90. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Seligman, Martin, E. Railton, P. Baumeister, F. Roy, and Chandra Sripada. 2016. Homo Prospectus. New York: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Shapiro, Scott J. 2011. Legality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  83. Sibley, W. M. 1953. The Rational Versus the Reasonable. Philosophical Review 62(4): 554–560.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Steiner, George. 1998. After Babel: Aspects of Language and Translation. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Sweet, Alec Stone and Jud, Matthews. 2009. Proportionality, Judicial Review, and Global Constitutionalism. In Reasonableness and Law, eds. Giorgio, B., Sartor, G., and C. Valentini, 171–214. New York: Springer

  86. Vico, Giambattista. 1720/21. De universi iuris (English Translation 2000: The Universal Right. Amsterdam, Atlanta: Rodopi).

  87. Weber, Max. 2002. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Wedgwood, Ralph. 2019. The Value of Rationality. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Wróbleswsky, Jerzy. 1983. Meaning and Truth in Judicial Decision. Helsinki: A-Tieto Oy.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Wróblewski, Jerzy. 1992. The Judicial Application of Law. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Zorzetto, Silvia. 2015. Reasonableness. The Italian Law Journal 1: 107–139.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Ricca.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ricca, M. Planning Facts Through Law: Legal Reasonableness as Creative Indexicality and Trans-categorical Re-configuration. Int J Semiot Law 33, 1089–1123 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09702-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-020-09702-z

Keywords

Navigation