Skip to main content
Log in

What’s wrong with the minimal conception of innateness in cognitive science?

  • S.I.: Explanations in Cognitive Science: Unification vs Pluralism
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the classic debates in cognitive science is between nativism and empiricism about the development of psychological capacities. In principle, the debate is empirical. However, in practice nativist hypotheses have also been challenged for relying on an ill-defined, or even unscientific, notion of innateness as that which is “not learned”. Here this minimal conception of innateness is defended on four fronts. First, it is argued that the minimal conception is crucial to understanding the nativism-empiricism debate, when properly construed; Second, various objections to the minimal conception—that it risks overgeneralization, lacks an account of learning, frustrates genuine explanations of psychological development, and fails to unify different notions of innateness across the sciences—are rebutted. Third, it is argued that the minimal conception avoids the shortcomings of primitivism, the prominent view that innate capacities are those that are not acquired via a psychological process in development. And fourth, the minimal conception undermines some attempts to identify innateness with a natural kind. So in short, we have little reason to reject, and good reason to accept, the minimal conception of innateness in cognitive science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for example: Cowie (1999), Griffiths (2002), Linquist (2018), Mameli and Bateson (2006) and Samuels (2007).

  2. For this reason I set aside experimental work on our folk conception(s) of innateness (Griffiths et al. 2009; Knobe and Samuels 2013; Linquist et al. 2011).

  3. Note that in recognizing both kinds of learning systems are innate, I do not presume an intrinsic connection between innateness and domain-specificity (Khalidi 2001).

  4. Notably, this way of understanding the debate does not rule out the possibility that domain-specific knowledge, or concepts, may form part of the acquisition base. For discussion see Margolis and Laurence (2013, pp. 712–715).

  5. Of course, matters may also depend on the psychological domains in question. For example, one can hold that mindreading depends on domain-general statistical learning systems, and support this empiricist hypothesis by appeal to domain-specific learning mechanisms in perception (see e.g. Ruffman 2014).

  6. See for example: Ariew (1996), Mallon and Weinberg (2006) and Wimsatt (1986).

  7. Though I touch on some potential examples when discussing the next challenge for the minimal conception.

  8. In this list “conditioning” is meant to include evaluative conditioning in which a change in the preference for a conditioned stimulus is induced from being paired with a positive or negative unconditioned stimulus.

  9. One could argue that triggering involves a species of domain-specific learning that is specialized to operate in informationally-impoverished contexts. In which case, RC could be amended to refer only to domain-general learning rules. If triggering is not a clear case, then an alternative example of a process that violates RC would then be those that initiate the molecular cuing in visual development, described below.

  10. Again, as stated at the outset, my interest is not whether our folk notion of innateness is confused, as it may well be.

  11. When recruiting “neurotypical” participants this usually involves screening for comorbidity with other psychiatric conditions, such as schizophrenia or psychopathy, and also conditions that impact learning such as dyslexia (which impacts reading ability) or dyscalculia (which impacts arithmetic skills).

  12. There is substantial disagreement amongst proponents of HPC-stye approaches as to how the clustering and underlying mechanisms should be understood (Boyd 1999; Millikan 1999). Here I set these issues aside and follow Samuels’ characterization.

References

  • Ariew, A. (1996). Innateness and canalization. Philosophy of Science, 63, S19–S27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, R. C., Pietroski, P., Yankama, B., & Chomsky, N. (2011). Poverty of the stimulus revisited. Cognitive Science, 35(7), 1207–1242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilalić, M., Langner, R., Ulrich, R., & Grodd, W. (2011). Many faces of expertise: Fusiform face area in chess experts and novices. Journal of Neuroscience, 31(28), 10206–10214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61(1), 127–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Kinds, complexity and multiple realization. Philosophical Studies, 95(1), 67–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butts, D. A., Kanold, P. O., & Shatz, C. J. (2007). A burst-based “Hebbian” learning rule at retinogeniculate synapses links retinal waves to activity-dependent refinement. PLoS Biology, 5(3), e61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1975). Reflections on language. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowie, F. (1999). What’s within? Nativism reconsidered. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crain, S. (1991). Language acquisition in the absence of experience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14(4), 597–612.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crain, S., & Pietroski, P. (2001). Nature, nurture and universal grammar. Linguistics and Philosophy, 24(2), 139–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demas, J. A., Payne, H., & Cline, H. T. (2012). Vision drives correlated activity without patterned spontaneous activity in developing Xenopus retina. Developmental Neurobiology, 72(4), 537–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Representations. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, I., Skudlarski, P., Gore, J. C., & Anderson, A. W. (2000). Expertise for cars and birds recruits brain areas involved in face recognition. Nature Neuroscience, 3(2), 191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind & Language, 24(5), 605–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2002). What is innateness? The Monist, 85(1), 70–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Machery, E. (2008). Innateness, canalization, and ‘biologicizing the mind’. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 397–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, S., & Rey, G. (2012). Innateness. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. Stich (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huberman, A. D., Feller, M. B., & Chapman, B. (2008). Mechanisms underlying development of visual maps and receptive fields. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 31, 479–509.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanwisher, N., McDermott, J., & Chun, M. M. (1997). The fusiform face area: A module in human extrastriate cortex specialized for face perception. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(11), 4302–4311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanwisher, N., & Yovel, G. (2006). The fusiform face area: A cortical region specialized for the perception of faces. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 361(1476), 2109–2128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2001). Innateness and domain specificity. Philosophical Studies, 105(2), 191–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2007). Innate cognitive capacities. Mind & Language, 22(1), 92–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2013). Natural categories and human kinds: Classification in the natural and social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2016). Innateness as a natural cognitive kind. Philosophical Psychology, 29(3), 319–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Samuels, R. (2013). Thinking like a scientist: Innateness as a case study. Cognition, 126(1), 72–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2001). The poverty of the stimulus argument. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52(2), 217–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lidz, J., Waxman, S., & Freedman, J. (2003). What infants know about syntax but couldn’t have learned: Experimental evidence for syntactic structure at 18 months. Cognition, 89(3), 295–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linquist, S. (2018). The conceptual critique of innateness. Philosophy Compass, 13(5), e12492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linquist, S., Machery, E., Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2011). Exploring the folkbiological conception of human nature. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 366(1563), 444–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2006). Innateness as closed process invariance. Philosophy of Science, 73(3), 323–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M., & Bateson, P. (2006). Innateness and the sciences. Biology and Philosophy, 21(2), 155–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M., & Bateson, P. (2011). An evaluation of the concept of innateness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 366(1563), 436–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2013). In defense of nativism. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 693–718.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, G., Puce, A., Gore, J. C., & Allison, T. (1997). Face-specific processing in the human fusiform gyrus. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9(5), 605–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meredith, R. M. (2015). Sensitive and critical periods during neurotypical and aberrant neurodevelopment: A framework for neurodevelopmental disorders. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 50, 180–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1999). Historical kinds and the “special sciences”. Philosophical Studies, 95(1), 45–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, E. (2015). Relativizing innateness: Innateness as the insensitivity of the appearance of a trait with respect to specified environmental variation. Biology & Philosophy, 30(2), 211–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, G. K., & Scholz, B. C. (2002). Empirical assessment of stimulus poverty arguments. The Lnguistic Review, 18(1–2), 9–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T. (2014). To belief or not belief: Children’s theory of mind. Developmental Review, 34(3), 265–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind & Language, 17(3), 233–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2004). Innateness in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(3), 136–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2007). Is innateness a confused concept? In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind, volume 3: Foundations and the future. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. J. (2005). Innateness and (Bayesian) visual perception. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind, volume 1: Structure and contents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1975). The idea of innateness. In S. Stich (Ed.), Innate ideas. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., & Mallon, R. (2008). Living with innateness (and environmental dependence too). Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 415–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), Integrating scientific disciplines. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, R. O. L. (1999). Retinal waves and visual system development. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 22(1), 29–47.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you to Evan Westra, the anonymous referees, and the Special Issue editors, Mateusz Hohol and Marcin Miłkowski, for their helpful feedback on earlier versions of the manuscript. A special thanks is also due to Mark Engelbert. The ideas presented here grew from our many fruitful conversations about the notion of innateness. This project has received funding from the FWO and European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie Grant agreement No. 665501, via an FWO [PEGASUS]\(^2\) Marie Skłodowska-Curie fellowship (12T9217N) to the author.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Brendan Ritchie.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ritchie, J.B. What’s wrong with the minimal conception of innateness in cognitive science?. Synthese 199 (Suppl 1), 159–176 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02543-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02543-0

Keywords

Navigation