Skip to main content
Log in

Optogenetics and the mechanism of false memory

  • S.I.: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Constructivists about memory argue that memory is a capacity for building representations of past events from a generalized information store (e.g., De Brigard, in Synthese 191:155–185, 2014a; Michaelian, in Philos Psychol 24:323–342, 2012). The view is motivated by the memory errors discovered in cognitive psychology. Little has been known about the neural mechanisms by which false memories are produced. Recently, using a method I call the Optogenetic False Memory Technique (O-FaMe), neuroscientists have created false memories in mice (e.g., Ramirez et al., in Science 341:388–391, 2013). In this paper, I examine how Constructivism fares in light of O-FaMe results. My aims are two-fold. First, I argue that errors found in O-FaMe and cognitive psychology are similar behaviorally. Second, Constructivists should be able to explain the former since they purport to explain the latter, but they cannot. I conclude that O-FaMe studies reveal details about the mechanism by which false memories are produced that are incompatible with the explanatory approach to false memories favored by Constructivism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I resist labeling these memories of particular past events as episodic so as to avoid debates over whether episodic memory must involve a rich phenomenal character and whether non-human animals are capable of episodic remembering. I prefer the more neutral category event memory, for reasons elaborated on in Sect. 4.1.

  2. The genealogy of non-human animal models of false memory extends back further, of course. I discuss the recent history of this research in Sect. 3.

  3. Gallo (2006) offers a thorough review of the DRM and its various permutations.

  4. It is worth noting that these results reflect performance tendencies across large groups of participants. Not everyone who engages in such tasks produces false memories, nor does everyone produce the same rates of error or fall prone to the same manipulations. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing this point.

  5. This does not mean that all experimentalists who conduct studies of these memory errors endorse Constructivism, although of course some do (e.g., Loftus 2003). My focus is on contemporary philosophical versions of Constructivism, which take such evidence as motivation for their views.

  6. There are many variants of Constructivism; where individual accounts disagree, my exposition below follows the commitments of De Brigard.

  7. Versions of Constructivism can be distinguished by the specific distributed architecture endorsed. For a discussion of these variations, see Robins (forthcoming).

  8. The claim that memory responds accurately most of the time may strike the reader as difficult to reconcile with De Brigard’s other claim, quoted in Sect. 2.1, that memory “regularly and systematically malfunctions” (2014a, p. 159). Proponents of Constructivism must maintain a fine balance here, between claiming that memory follows certain patterns that are generally reliable and that the possibilities for error are pervasive enough to motivate this alternative account of memory. This is an interesting tension in the view, and I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting it, but I do not explore it further in this paper.

  9. For the purposes of this paper, the terms “engram” and “memory trace” are being used interchangeably.

  10. It is an interesting to ask whether, in the neuroscience of memory, commitment to the existence of discrete memory traces is a pretheoretical commitment or empirical discovery. For a discussion of this issue, see De Brigard (2014b).

  11. Although, of course, philosophers of neuroscience disagree about the explanatory lessons to be drawn from consideration of this example. Bickle (2003) uses memory formation as an example of “ruthless” reduction, whereas Craver (2007) advocates multi-level mechanisms. For concerns about the explananda, see Sullivan (2010).

  12. Freezing is an adaptive response to fear, as predators are often sensitive to motion, and is found in most rodents.

  13. For a thorough review of optogenetic techniques, see Deisseroth (2011).

  14. This is not to say that the method is without its limitations (Häusser 2014). Some even recommend more focus on alternative molecular interventions, such as designer receptors exclusively activated by designer drugs (DREADDs), and the relative experimental advantages and disadvantages of each (Bickle forthcoming).

  15. The transgenic population used by the Tonegawa laboratory for the O-FaMe studies discussed below are c-fos/tTA/Dox-off mice. In addition to the features discussed in the text, these mice are also engineered to have: (1) A tetracycline-responsive element (TRE), which provides a binding site for the protein that allows expression of the engineered opsin gene), and (2) Monomeric fluorescent protein gene (mCherry), which expresses a protein that appears red under standard light microscopy, allowing the engram cells to be detected by researchers. Many thanks to John Bickle for helping me understand the details of this mechanism.

  16. The lineage of O-FaMe, and inquiries into the possibility of animal models of false memory, can be traced back further, to studies that manipulate which neurons are involved in the engram by interventions into the CREB transcription factor (Han et al. 2007).

  17. Another portion of the Redondo et al. study involved a comparison of encoding-related changes in the amygdala versus the dentate gyrus. This portion of the results confirms that it is the neural changes in the dentate gyrus, not the amygdala, that are responsible for engram formation.

  18. The rates of false recognition were lower, however. Only 25 % of participants “recognized” the photo without the misleading question on the questionnaire, whereas 60 % “recognized” it when the misleading question was included.

  19. I am grateful to Jacqueline Sullivan for raising this issue.

  20. To make this point more forcefully, O-FaMe studies should include a fourth condition, where the mouse is taken to a familiar, neutral context. If the mouse treats the environment as familiar, but does not freeze, then it would be clear that the misinformation has not spread to all remembered contexts. To my knowledge, no O-FaMe study has yet included such a condition.

References

  • Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Drodrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2005). Molecular neuroscience to my rescue (again): Reply to Looren de Jong and Schouten. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 487–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (forthcoming). Revolutions in neuroscience: Tool development. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience.

  • Boyden, E. S. (2011). A history of optogenetics: The development of tools for controlling brain circuits with light. F1000 Biological Reports, 3, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyden, E. S., Zhang, F., Bamberg, E., Nagel, G., & Deisseroth, K. (2005). Millisecond-timescale, genetically targeted optical control of neural activity. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1263–1268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (forthcoming). Thinking about interventions: optogenetics and makers knowledge of the brain. In K. Waters (Ed.), Causation in biology and philosophy. Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Crick, F. (1999). The impact of molecular biology on neuroscience. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series B, 354, 2021–2025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F. (2014a). Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of episodic hypothetical thinking. Synthese, 191, 155–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F. (2014b). The nature of memory traces. Philosophy Compass, 9, 402–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F., Addis, D., Ford, J. H., Schacter, D. L., & Giovanello, K. S. (2013). Remembering what could have happened: Neural correlates of episodic counterfactual thinking. Neuropsychologia, 51, 2401–2414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deisseroth, K. (2011). Optogenetics. Nature Methods, 8, 26–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Draaisma, D. (2000). Metaphors of memory: A history of ideas about the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenno, L., Yizhar, O., & Deisseroth, K. (2011). The development and application of optogenetics. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 32, 389–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallo, D. A. (2006). Associative illusions of memory: False memory research in DRM and related tasks. New York, NY: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Han, J., Kushner, S. A., Yiu, A. P., Cole, C. J., Matynia, A., Brown, R. A., et al. (2007). Neuronal competition and selection during memory formation. Science, 316, 457–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasselmo, M. E. (2012). How we remember: Brain mechanisms of episodic memory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häusser, M. (2014). Optogenetics: The age of light. Nature Methods, 11, 1012–1014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. (2013). The temporal orientation of memory: It’s time for a change of direction. Journal of Research in Applied Memory and Cognition, 2, 222–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lashley, K. (1950). In search of the engram. Symposium on explorations of biology, No. 4. (pp. 454–482). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Liu, X., Ramirez, S., Pang, P., Puryear, C., Govindarajan, A., Deisseroth, K., et al. (2012). Optogenetic stimulation of a hippocampal engram activates fear memory recall. Nature, 484, 381–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, X., Ramirez, S., & Tonegawa, S. (2014). Inception of a false memory by optogenetic manipulation of a hippocampal memory engram. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 369, 2013–2042.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F. (2003). Our changeable memories: Legal and practical implications. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 4, 231–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lofuts, E. F., Miller, D. G., & Burns, H. J. (1978). Semantic integration of verbal information into a visual memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 4, 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F., & Palmer, J. C. (1974). Reconstruction of auto-mobile destruction: An example of the interaction between language and memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 13, 585–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F., & Pickrell, J. E. (1995). The formation of false memories. Psychiatric Annals, 25, 720–725.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Looren de Jong, H., & Schouten, M. K. D. (2005). Ruthless reductionism: A review essay of John Bickle’s “Philosophy and Neuroscience”. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 473–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2012). Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology, 24, 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U., & Harsch, N. (1992). Phantom flashbulbs: False recollections of hearing the news about challenger. In E. Winograd & U. Neisser (Eds.), Affect and accuracy in recall: Studies of flashbulb memories (pp. 9–31). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paradis, C. M., Solomon, L. Z., Florer, F., & Thompson, T. (2004). Flashbulb memories of personal events of 9/11 and the day after for a sample of New York City residents. Psychological Reports, 95, 304–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramirez, S., Liu, X., Lin, P., Suh, J., Pignatelli, M., Redondo, R. L., et al. (2013). Creating a false memory in the hippocampus. Science, 341, 388–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramirez, S., Tonegawa, S., & Liu, X. (2014). Identification and optogenetic manipulation of memory engrams in the hippocampus. Frontiers of Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redondo, R. L., Kim, J., Arons, A. L., Ramirez, S., Liu, X., & Tonegawa, S. (2014). Bidirectional switch of the valence associated with a hippocampal contextual memory engram. Nature, 513, 426–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, S. K. (forthcoming). Misremembering. Philosophical Psychology.

  • Roediger, H. L., & McDermott, K. B. (1995). Creating false memories: Remembering words that were not presented in lists. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 21, 803–814.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D. C., & Umanath, S. (2015). Event memory: A theory of memory for laboratory, autobiographical, and fictional events. Psychological Review, 122, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Semon, R. (1921). The mneme. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silva, A. J., Landreth, A., & Bickle, J. (2014). Engineering the next revolution in neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Squire, L. R., & Zola, S. M. (1996). Structure and function of declarative and nondeclarative memory systems. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93, 13515–13522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, J. (2010). Reconsidering spatial memory and the Morris water maze. Synthese, 177, 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (1998). Philosophy and memory traces: Descartes to connectionism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., & Windhorst, C. (2009). Extended and constructive remembering: Two notes on Martin and Deutscher. Crossroads: An Interdisciplinary Journal for the Study of History, Philosophy, Religion, and Classics, 4, 79–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Templer, V. L., & Hampton, R. R. (2013). Episodic memory in nonhuman animals. Current Biology, 23, R801–R806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, R. F. (2005). In search of memory traces. Annual Review of Psychology, 56, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2005). The missing link in cognition. In H. S. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? (pp. 3–56). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to audiences at the University of Colorado’s 2014 HPS Conference, the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology meeting in New Orleans, and the Society for Philosophy and Psychology meeting at Duke University. I am especially grateful to John Bickle, Paul Davies, Corey Maley, Joseph McCaffrey, and Jacqueline Sullivan, as well as two anonymous reviewers, for their detailed and thoughtful feedback. Completion of this manuscript was supported by the University of Kansas General Research Fund allocation #2301035.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sarah K. Robins.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Robins, S.K. Optogenetics and the mechanism of false memory. Synthese 193, 1561–1583 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1045-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1045-9

Keywords

Navigation