Skip to main content
Log in

Dreaming of a stable world: vision and action in sleep

  • S.I. : Between Vision and Action
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Our eyes, bodies, and perspectives are constantly shifting as we observe the world. Despite this, we are very good at distinguishing between self-caused visual changes and changes in the environment: the world appears mostly stable despite our visual field moving around. This, it seems, also occurs when we are dreaming. As we visually investigate the dream environment, we track moving objects with our dream eyes, examine objects, and shift focus. These movements, research suggests, are reflected in the rapid movements or saccades of our sleeping eyes. Do we really see the dream world in the same way that we see the real world? If we do, how could dreaming, usually assumed to be mind-generated hallucinations, replicate such an experience? This problem would be deflated if dreams are not hallucinations at all, but rather imagination, illusion or simply unrealistic. I argue that imagination and illusion views do not satisfactorily explain away the problem of vision and action in sleep. The imagination model is not a complete description of dreaming that is consistent with empirical research, and it is unlikely that the visual dream world is an illusion. Given that the dreaming visual experience is most likely active, hallucinatory, and at times a realistic world simulation, there are important implications for our understanding of visual perception and its relationship to movement. Evidence suggests that our dream eyes investigate the dream world as our waking eyes investigate the waking world. If changes to the unconsciously generated dream environment are perceived as external and unintentional while dream body movements are perceived as self-generated and intentional, current theory of visual perception may have to be expanded to account for how the dreaming mind generates a stable world in which we track and visually explore mind-generated objects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is debate about whether hallucinations are perceptual, however, my discussion concerns whether dreams can be convincingly life-like in the absence of mind-independent objects. If the distinction between perception and imagination is merely that the experience is caused by an external stimulus, this is theoretically problematic (Siegel 2005) and would arbitrarily discount dreams as perceptual experience. Whether hallucinations should be termed ‘quasi-perceptual’ (Nanay 2016) or otherwise need not be debated here. For simplicity, I refer to hallucinations as perceptual.

  2. There are other uses of the term “imagining” such as to make-believe, but for Ichikawa’s discussion of dream phenomenology, the relevant type is the bringing about of an image or sensation to one’s imagination.

  3. Some might argue that inner speech is a different phenomenon all together from imagining speech, for example, “sub vocalisations”, which may account for some auditory verbal hallucinations (for an in-depth discussion, see Wilkinson 2014), but imagination seems the most accurate description in these cases.

  4. Known as “propositional imagination” (Ichikawa 2016, p. 124).

  5. Liao and Szabó Gendler (2011) characterise delusions as “belief- like mental representations that manifest an unusual degree of disconnectedness from reality [and] seem to exhibit features of both belief and imagination” (p. 87). Although they note that delusions can involve elements of imagination, this does not necessarily support the imagination model, as dreaming can involve both imagination and hallucination, consistent with the pluralistic model of dreams (Rosen 2018b).

  6. Taken from Sleepanddreamdatabase.org, a publicly accessible database storing tens of thousands of dream reports. Dream Text: Most Recent Dream - Q15), 41 words, harris_2013s:001465 [Answer Date Unknown].

  7. Although saccades are defined as voluntary, if there are cases of, for example, involuntary REM saccades generated by PGO activity, these would be exceptions to their voluntariness. For my purposes, I use ‘saccades’ to refer to all eye movements that are rapid and remain neutral on whether they are voluntary.

  8. An alternative interpretation is that the tACS was ineffective at modulating frontal lobe activity in 23% of cases, thus lucidity should not be expected. It is unclear whether the EEG monitoring performed during these experiments can disambiguate. Thanks to a reviewer for this point. However, it is also important to note that in Voss et al. (2014) work, “lucidity was assumed when subjects reported elevated ratings (> mean + 2 s.e.) on either or both of the LuCiD scale factors insight and dissociation” (p. 813) where “dissociation” refers to taking on a 3rd person perspective. The definition of lucidity relevant to my discussion, the realization that one was dreaming, is more specific than this scale, and thus the percentage of dreamers who realized that they were dreaming may be less than the 77% noted here. The potential for increased cognitive ability to occur without explicit awareness that one is dreaming supports the view that dreams can at times stand up to rational scrutiny.

  9. Note that there is some debate about what age this development is completed (Sándor et al. 2015).

  10. Thanks to a reviewer for suggestions in this section.

References

  • Anderson, D. (1988). The delusion of inanimate doubles. Implications for understanding the Capgras phenomenon. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 153(5), 694–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Appel, K., Pipa, G., & Dresler, M. (2017). Investigating consciousness in the sleep laboratory—An interdisciplinary perspective on lucid dreaming. Interdisciplinary Science Reviews, 43, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1080/03080188.2017.1380468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnulf, I. (2011). The ‘scanning hypothesis’ of rapid eye movements during REM sleep: A review of the evidence. Archives Italiennes de Biologie, 149(4), 367–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aspy, D. J., Delfabbro, P., Proeve, M., & Mohr, P. (2017). Reality testing and the mnemonic induction of lucid dreams: Findings from the national Australian lucid dream induction study. Dreaming, 27(3), 206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M., & Petitmengin, C. (2017). Neurophenomenology and the microphenomenological interview. In S. Schneider, & M. Velmans (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (2nd Edn., pp. 726–739). Wiley.

  • Blumberg, M. S. (2010). Beyond dreams: Do sleep-related movements contribute to brain development? Frontiers in Neurology, 1, 140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S., Coleman, C. M., Gerth, A. I., & McMurray, B. (2013). Spatiotemporal structure of REM sleep twitching reveals developmental origins of motor synergies. Current Biology, 23(21), 2100–2109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, S. A., & Stark, L. W. (1997). Spontaneous eye movements during visual imagery reflect the content of the visual scene. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9(1), 27–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brasić, J. R. (1998). Hallucinations. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 86(3), 851–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bray, N. (2014). Sleep: Inducing lucid dreams. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 15(7), 428–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breen, N., Caine, D., Coltheart, M., Hendy, J., & Roberts, C. (2000). Towards an understanding of delusions of misidentification: Four case studies. Mind and Language, 15(1), 74–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgeman, B. (2007). Efference copy and its limitations. Computers in Biology and Medicine, 37(7), 924–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgeman, B. (2012). Eye movements. Encyclopedia of Human Behavior, 2, 160–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgeman, B., Van der Heijden, A. H. C., & Velichkovsky, B. M. (1994). A theory of visual stability across saccadic eye movements. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17(2), 247–258. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00034361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Busby, K. A., Mercier, L., & Pivik, R. (1994). Ontogenetic variations in auditory arousal threshold during sleep. Psychophysiology, 31(2), 182–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buzzi, G. (2011). False awakenings in light of the dream protoconsciousness theory: A study in lucid dreamers. International Journal of Dream Research, 4(2), 110–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). Why pretend? In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction (pp. 89–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cavallero, C., Cicogna, P., Natale, V., Occhionero, M., & Zito, A. (1992). Slow wave sleep dreaming. Sleep, 15(6), 562–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A. (2004). Borderlands of consciousness: Between dream world and wake world. Toward a Science of Consciousness, 8, 319–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colace, C. (2010). Children’s dreams: From Freud’s observations to modern dream research. London: Karnac Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colace, C. (2012). Dream bizarreness and the controversy between the neurobiological approach and the disguise-censorship model: The contribution of children’s dreams. Neuropsychoanalysis, 14(2), 165–174. https://doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2012.10773700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. (2005). Conscious experience and delusional belief. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 12(2), 153–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, P. R., Taylor, J. R., Wang, X. J., Fletcher, P. C., & Krystal, J. H. (2010). Toward a neurobiology of delusions. Progress in Neurobiology, 92(3), 345–369. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pneurobio.2010.06.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T., & French, C. (2017). The problem of perception. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/perception-problem/.

  • David, A. (2010). Why we need more debate on whether psychotic symptoms lie on a continuum with normality. Psychological Medicine, 40(12), 1935–1942.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., Coltheart, M., Langdon, R., & Breen, N. (2001). Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 8(2), 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dement, W., & Kleitman, N. (1957a). Cyclic variations in EEG during sleep and their relation to eye movements, body motility, and dreaming. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 9(4), 673–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dement, W., & Kleitman, N. (1957b). The relation of eye movements during sleep to dream activity: An objective method for the study of dreaming. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 53(5), 339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dement, W., & Wolpert, E. A. (1958). The relation of eye movements, body motility, and external stimuli to dream content. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 55(6), 543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1976). Are dreams experiences? The Philosophical Review, 85(2), 151–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deubel, H. (2004). Localization of targets across saccades: Role of landmark objects. Visual Cognition, 11(2–3), 173–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. W. (2003). The scientific study of dreams: Neural networks, cognitive development, and content (1st ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Domhoff, G. W. (2007). Realistic simulation and bizarreness in dream content: Past findings and suggestions for future research. In D. Barrett & P. McNamara (Eds.), The new science of dreaming (pp. 1–28). Westport: Praeger Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doricchi, F., Iaria, G., Silvetti, M., Figliozzi, F., & Siegler, I. (2007). The “ways” we look at dreams: Evidence from unilateral spatial neglect (with an evolutionary account of dream bizarreness). Experimental Brain Research, 178(4), 450–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dresler, M., Eibl, L., Fischer, C. F., Wehrle, R., Spoormaker, V. I., Steiger, A., et al. (2014). Volitional components of consciousness vary across wakefulness, dreaming and lucid dreaming. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dresler, M., Erlacher, D., Czisch, M., & Spoormaker, V. I. (2016). Lucid dreaming. In M. Kryger, T. Roth, & W. Dement (Eds.), Principles and practice ofsleep medicine. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erlacher, D., Stumbrys, T., & Schredl, M. (2015). The lucid dreaming athlete. In: Proceedings of the 14th European congress of sport psychology - theories and applications for performance, health and humanity, 14–19 July 2015. Bern, Switzerland.

  • Ermis, U., Krakow, K., & Voss, U. (2010). Arousal thresholds during human tonic and phasic REM sleep. Journal of Sleep Research, 19(3), 400–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farah, M. J. (1984). The neurological basis of mental imagery: A componential analysis. Cognition, 18(1–3), 245–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foulkes, D. (1982). Children’s dreams: Longitudinal studies. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulkes, D. (1996). Dream research: 1953–1993. Sleep, 19(8), 609–624. https://doi.org/10.1093/sleep/19.8.609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foulkes, D. (1999). Children’s dreaming and the development of consciousness. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulkes, D., & Fleisher, S. (1975). Mental activity in relaxed wakefulness. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 84(1), 66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D. (2014). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. London: Psychology Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., & Done, D. J. (1989). Experiences of alien control in schizophrenia reflect a disorder in the central monitoring of action. Psychological Medicine, 19(2), 359–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauntlett-Gilbert, J., & Kuipers, E. (2003). Phenomenology of visual hallucinations in psychiatric conditions. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 191(3), 203–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, C. E. (1968). Lucid dreams (Vol. 1). Oxford: Institute of Psychophysical Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, C. E., & McCreery, C. (1994). Lucid dreaming: The paradox of consciousness during sleep (Vol. 6). London: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haarmeier, T., Thier, P., Repnow, M., & Petersen, D. (1997). False perception of motion in a patient who cannot compensate for eye movements. Nature, 389(6653), 849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, M., Martarelli, C. S., Mast, F. W., & Stocker, K. (2014). Eye movements during mental time travel follow a diagonal line. Consciousness and Cognition, 30, 201–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (1988). The dreaming brain. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (1999). Dreaming. In R. A. Wilson & F. C. Keil (Eds.), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (2002). Dreaming: An introduction to the science of sleep. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A. (2005). In bed with mark solms? What a nightmare! A reply to Domhoff (2005). Dreaming, 15(1), 21–29. https://doi.org/10.1037/1053-0797.15.1.21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., & McCarley, R. W. (1977). The brain as a dream state generator: An activation-synthesis hypothesis of the dream process. American Journal of Psychiatry, 134(12), 1335–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., Pace-Schott, E. F., & Stickgold, R. (2000). Dreaming and the brain: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 793–842. (discussion 904-1121).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, J. A., Pace-Schott, E. F., & Stickgold, R. (2003). Dreaming and the brain: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of conscious states. In E. F. Pace-Schott, M. Solms, M. Blagrove, & S. Harnad (Eds.), Sleep and dreaming: Scientific advances and reconsiderations (Vol. 23, pp. 793–842). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodoba, D., Hrabrić, K., Krmpotić, P., Brečić, P., Kujundžić-Tilja, M., & Majdančić, Ž. (2008). Dream recall after night awakenings from tonic/phasic REM sleep. Collegium Antropologicum, 32(1), 69–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hong, C. C. H., Harris, J. C., Pearlson, G. D., Kim, J. S., Calhoun, V. D., Fallon, J. H., et al. (2009). fMRI evidence for multisensory recruitment associated with rapid eye movements during sleep. Human Brain Mapping, 30(5), 1705–1722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horikawa, T., Tamaki, M., Miyawaki, Y., & Kamitani, Y. (2013). Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep. Science, 340(6132), 639–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • https://www.statsbiblioteket.dk/au/#/search?query=recordID%3A%22ebog_ssj0001499942%22.

  • Hurley, S. L. (1998). Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. (2008). Skepticism and the imagination model of dreaming. Philosophical Quarterly, 58(232), 519–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. (2009). Dreaming and imagination. Mind and Language, 24(1), 103–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. (2016). Imagination, dreaming, and hallucination. In A. Kind (Ed.), Routledge handbook of the philosophy of imagination (pp. 149–162). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. K. (1992). MEM: Mechanisms of recollection. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 4(3), 268–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, T. L., & Claudatos, S. (2016). Phenomenological features of dreams: Results from dream log studies using the subjective experiences rating scale (SERS). Consciousness and Cognition, 41, 159–176. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2016.02.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, T. L., & LaBerge, S. (1994). Lucid dreaming as metacognition: Implications for cognitive science. Consciousness and Cognition, 3(2), 246–264. https://doi.org/10.1006/ccog.1994.1014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, T. L., & LaBerge, S. (1996). Cognition and metacognition in dreaming and waking: Comparisons of first and third-person ratings. Dreaming, 6, 235–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom, J. F. (2004). Joseph Jastrow and his duck-or is it a rabbit. Trends in the Cognitive Sciences (TICS), Last Visited, 31(07), 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2016). Introduction: Exploring imagination (pp. 1–11). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kubota, Y., Takasu, N. N., Horita, S., Kondo, M., Shimizu, M., Okada, T., et al. (2011). Dorsolateral prefrontal cortical oxygenation during REM sleep in humans. Brain Research, 1389, 83–92. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.brainres.2011.02.061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S. (2000). Lucid dreaming: Evidence and methodology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 962–964.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S., & DeGracia, D. J. (2000). Varieties of lucid dreaming experience. Individual Differences in Conscious Experience, 20, 269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S., & Levitan, L. (1995). Validity established of DreamLight cues for eliciting lucid dreaming. Dreaming, 5(3), 159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaBerge, S., Levitan, L., & Dement, W. C. (1986). Lucid dreaming: Physiological correlates of consciousness during REM sleep. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 7, 251–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laeng, B., & Teodorescu, D.-S. (2002). Eye scanpaths during visual imagery reenact those of perception of the same visual scene. Cognitive Science, 26(2), 207–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langdon, R., Jones, S., Connaughton, E., & Fernyhough, C. (2009). The phenomenology of inner speech: Comparison of schizophrenia patients with auditory verbal hallucinations and healthy controls. Psychological Medicine, 39(4), 655–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larøi, F. (2006). The phenomenological diversity of hallucinations: Some theoretical and clinical implications. Psychologica Belgica, 46(1–2), 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, K., & Ogilvie, R. (1996). Vestibular dreams: The effect of rocking on dream mentation. Dreaming, 6(1), 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitan, L. (1994). A fool’s guide to lucid dreaming. Nightlight, 6(2), 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. Y., & Szabó Gendler, T. (2011). Pretense and imagination. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2(1), 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mack, A., & Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional blindness (Vol. 33). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mahowald, M. W., Schenck, C. H., & Bornemann, M. A. C. (2005). Sleep-related violence. Current Neurology and Neuroscience Reports, 5(2), 153–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, N. (1967). Dreaming: (4. impr.).. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S. L., & Hubel, D. H. (2004). The role of fixational eye movements in visual perception. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5(3), 229–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather, G. (2016). Foundations of sensation and perception. London: Psychology Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. B. (1981). On being immoral in a dream. Philosophy, 56(215), 47–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). The content of perceptual experience. The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 44(175), 190–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003). Phenomenal transparency and cognitive self-reference. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2(4), 353–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2009). The ego tunnel: The science of the mind and the myth of the self. New York: Basic Books (AZ).

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2013). Why are dreams interesting for philosophers? The example of minimal phenomenal selfhood, plus an agenda for future research. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyauchi, S., Misaki, M., Kan, S., Fukunaga, T., & Koike, T. (2009). Human brain activity time-locked to rapid eye movements during REM sleep. Experimental Brain Research, 192(4), 657–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2016). Imagination and perception. In A. Kind (Ed.), Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A. (1993). Changes in the kinesthetic content of dreams following somatosensory stimulation of leg muscles during REM sleep. Dreaming, 3(2), 99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, T. A., Ouellet, L., & Zadra, A. (1995). Pressure stimulation during REM sleep alters dream limb activity and body bizarreness. Sleep Research, 24, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2006). Experience without the head. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 411–433). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2007). Magic realism and the limits of intelligibility: What makes us conscious. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2012). Varieties of presence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A., Pessoa, L., & Thompson, E. (2000). Beyond the grand illusion: What change blindness really teaches us about vision. Visual Cognition, 7(1–3), 93–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noreika, V., Windt, J. M., Lenggenhager, B., & Karim, A. A. (2010). New perspectives for the study of lucid dreaming: From brain stimulation to philosophical theories of self-consciousness. International Journal of Dream Research, 3, 36–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogawa, K., Nittono, H., & Hori, T. (2005). Brain potentials before and after rapid eye movements: An electrophysiological approach to dreaming in REM sleep. Sleep, 28(9), 1077–1082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, M., & Mogensen, J. (2017). An integrative view on consciousness and introspection. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(1), 129–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, A. (2017). Current research on lucid dreaming and shared lucidity states. In Book of abstracts of the 41st SPR international annual conference (Vol. 35, pp. 11–13). Horsely Estate, UK, 1–3 Sept 2017.

  • Peigneux, P., Laureys, S., Fuchs, S., Delbeuck, X., Degueldre, C., Aerts, J., et al. (2001). Generation of rapid eye movements during paradoxical sleep in humans. Neuroimage, 14(3), 701–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rechtschaffen, A., & Buchignani, C. (1992). The visual appearance of dreams. In J. S. Antrobus & M. Bertini (Eds.), The Neuropsychology of sleep and dreaming (pp. 143–155). Erlbaum.

  • Revonsuo, A., & Salmivalli, C. (1995). A content analysis of bizarre elements in dreams. Dreaming, 5(3), 169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A., & Tarkko, K. (2002). Binding in dreams-the bizarreness of dream images and the unity of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(7), 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. G. (2013). What I make up when I wake up: Anti-experience views and narrative fabrication of dreams. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 514. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. G. (2015). I’m thinking your thoughts while I sleep: Sense of agency and ownership over dream thought. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 2(3), 326–339. https://doi.org/10.1037/cns0000064.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. G. (2018a). Enactive or inactive? Cranially envatted dream experience and the extended conscious mind. Philosphical Investigations, 21(2), 295–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. G. (2018b). How Bizarre? A pluralist approach to dream content. Consciousness and Cognition, 62, 148–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. G. (2018c). Your dream-body: All an illusion? Commentary on windt’s account of the dream-body in dreaming. Journal of Consciousness Studies (forthcoming).

  • Rosen, M. G., & Sutton, J. (2013). Self-representation and perspectives in dreams. Philosophy Compass, 8(11), 1041–1053. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sándor, P., Szakadát, S., Kertész, K., & Bódizs, R. (2015). Content analysis of 4 to 8 year-old children’s dream reports. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 534. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schädlich, M., Erlacher, D., & Schredl, M. (2017). Improvement of darts performance following lucid dream practice depends on the number of distractions while rehearsing within the dream—A sleep laboratory pilot study. Journal of Sports Sciences, 35(23), 2365–2372. https://doi.org/10.1080/02640414.2016.1267387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schönhammer, R. (2005). ‘Typical dreams’: Reflections of arousal. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12, 18–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S., Dang-Vu, T. T., Ponz, A., Duhoux, S., & Maquet, P. (2005). Dreaming: A neuropsychological view. Schweizer Archiv für Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 156, 426–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S., & Maquet, P. (2002). Sleep imaging and the neuro-psychological assessment of dreams. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(1), 23–30. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01818-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). Why did we think we dreamed in black and white? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 33(4), 649–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selterman, D. F., Apetroaia, A. I., Riela, S., & Aron, A. (2014). Dreaming of you: Behavior and emotion in dreams of significant others predict subsequent relational behavior. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 5(1), 111–118. https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550613486678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2005). The contents of perception. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/entries/perception-contents/.

  • Snyder, F., Karacan, I., Tharp, V., & Scott, J. (1968). Phenomenology of REM dreaming. Psychophysiology, 4, 375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solms, M. (2000). Dreaming and REM sleep are controlled by different brain mechanisms. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(6), 843–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2005). Dreams and philosophy. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79(2), 7–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E., & Ichikawa, J. (2009). Dreaming, philosophical issues. In T. Bayne, P. Wilken, & A. Cleeremans (Eds.), Oxford companion to consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger, A., Lappe-Osthege, M., Talamo, S., Gais, S., Kimmig, H., & Helmchen, C. (2010). Eye movements during REM sleep and imagination of visual scenes. NeuroReport, 21(1), 45–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, J. K., Emerson, R. C., Gerstein, G. L., Kallos, T., Neufeld, G. R., Nichols, C. W., et al. (1976). Paralysis of the awake human: Visual perceptions. Vision Research, 16(1), 93–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stickgold, R., Hobson, J. A., Fosse, R., & Fosse, M. (2001). Sleep, learning, and dreams: Off-line memory reprocessing. Science, 294(5544), 1052–1057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stumbrys, T., Erlacher, D., Johnson, M., & Schredl, M. (2014). The phenomenology of lucid dreaming: An online survey. The American Journal of Psychology, 127(2), 191–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stumbrys, T., Erlacher, D., Schädlich, M., & Schredl, M. (2012). Induction of lucid dreams: A systematic review of evidence. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(3), 1456–1475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (1997). Mental time travel and the evolution of the human mind. Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs, 123(2), 133–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Théoret, H., & Pascual-Leone, A. (2002). Language acquisition: Do as you hear. Current Biology, 12(21), R736–R737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uzzaman, S., & Joordens, S. (2011). The eyes know what you are thinking: Eye movements as an objective measure of mind wandering. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 1882–1886. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2011.09.010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R. (2007). What if phenomenal consciousness admits of degrees? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5–6), 528–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Helmholtz, H., & Southall, J. P. C. (2005). Treatise on physiological optics (Vol. 3). Chelmsford: Courier Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voss, U., & Hobson, J. A. (2014). What is the State-of-the-Art on lucid dreaming?-Recent advances and questions for future research Open MIND: Open MIND. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voss, U., Holzmann, R., Hobson, J. A., Paulus, W., Koppehele-Gossel, J., Klimke, A., et al. (2014). Induction of self awareness in dreams through frontal low current stimulation of gamma activity. Nature Neuroscience, 17(6), 810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voss, U., Holzmann, R., Tuin, I., & Hobson, A. J. (2009). Lucid dreaming: A state of consciousness with features of both waking and non-lucid dreaming. Sleep, 32(9), 1191–1200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, S. (2014). Accounting for the phenomenology and varieties of auditory verbal hallucination within a predictive processing framework. Consciousness and Cognition, 30, 142–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windt, J. M. (2015). Dreaming: A conceptual framework for philosophy of mind and empirical research. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Windt, J. M. (2017). Predictive brains, dreaming selves, sleeping bodies: How the analysis of dream movement can inform a theory of self-and world-simulation in dreams. Synthese, 195, 1–49.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank John Sutton, Peter Menzies and three anonymous reviewers for their invaluable comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Funding

Funded by the Carlsberg Foundation distinguished postdoctoral Grant No. CF16-0804.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Melanie Rosen.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosen, M. Dreaming of a stable world: vision and action in sleep. Synthese 198 (Suppl 17), 4107–4142 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02149-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02149-1

Keywords

Navigation