Skip to main content

Deductive and Deontic Reasoning

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1256 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter offers a concise and elementary introduction to fundamental concepts in deductive and deontic reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The reader is not required to have any advanced technical background. Some basic knowledge on general philosophy, elementary set theory and propositional logic can be useful but not necessary.

  2. 2.

    More on the concept of argument in Walton, chapter 3, part I, this volume, on “Legal Reasoning and Argumentation.”

  3. 3.

    Indeed, if there is an argument from \(P_1, \dots , P_n\) into \(C_1, \dots , C_m\), it is usually the case that there are arguments for each conclusion in \(C_1, \dots , C_m\) from \(P_1, \dots , P_n\), and vice versa.

  4. 4.

    As usual, \(\varGamma , \varGamma '\) and \(\varGamma , A\) are abbreviations, respectively, for \(\varGamma \cup \varGamma '\) and \(\varGamma \cup \{ A \}\).

  5. 5.

    Sartor, Chapter 3, Part II, this volume, on “Defeasibility in Law.”

  6. 6.

    See the next section for more details.

  7. 7.

    But compare the interesting counterarguments offered by Alchourron and Martino (1990).

  8. 8.

    Sections 3.2 and 3.3 freely elaborate on parts of (Sartor 2006).

  9. 9.

    This is somehow a simplification. More on permissions in Section 4.1.1.

  10. 10.

    The example is due to Sartor 2005, p. 453.

  11. 11.

    If one knew that the action or state of affairs was not only permitted but obligatory, one would use the latter qualification, according to the Gricean principle of quantity, which requires that we provide all the relevant information we have (see Grice 1989).

  12. 12.

    In deontic logic, when it is said that any A is facultative, this is equivalent to saying that A is indifferent.

  13. 13.

    We use the expression normative proposition to mean any possible legal content: a rule, a principle, the connection between a factor and the outcome it favours, and so on.

  14. 14.

    This issue has been famously addressed by von Jhering (1924), III, 35, who distinguished the purpose of a duty (the interest it is intended to serve, according to the point of view of the legal system, or of the legal community) from its various side effects (reflex-effects, Reflexwirkungen). Jhering considers, for instance, the case of a law prohibiting the import of certain goods, which was enacted by politicians having the aim of favouring a particular domestic producer (who had lobbied for this result). He argues that the fact the individual lawmakers had this aim in mind does not imply that the law confers a right on that manufacturer: from a legal perspective the manufacturer’s advantage is rather to be viewed as a side effect of that law.

  15. 15.

    On the idea of a directed obligation, see the seminal contribution by Krogh and Herrestad (1996), though their formalisation does not fully coincide with the one here described. More details in Sartor 2005; Sergot 2013.

  16. 16.

    Notice that, as we have argued at the end of Sect. 3.3 in regard to facultativeness, also here a better way for representing directed obligations would need to extend the language with actions.

  17. 17.

    This section elaborates on parts of (Grossi and Rotolo 2011).

  18. 18.

    No crime without law, that is, everything that is not explicitly prohibited should be considered as permitted.

  19. 19.

    The problem of whether norms bear or not truth values is an old one in philosophy and was put forth in modern times by (Jørgensen 1937). The significance of the problem has recently been reemphasised in (Hansen et al. 2007), and a new approach to the problem emerged from the view of norms as “dynamic” operators—speech acts—modifying ideality orders.

  20. 20.

    A preorder can always be associated with a given Boolean algebra in the following way:

    $$\begin{aligned} a \preceq b&{\mathrm{IFF}}\,&a \sqcap b = a. \end{aligned}$$
    (35)
  21. 21.

    As is well-known, the idea that legal effects do not follow from norms by logic but, rather, by stipulation was notably defended in legal theory by Kelsen (1991).

  22. 22.

    An interesting contribution is, for instance, offered by Lindahl and Odelstad (2008).

References

  • Alchourrón, C., P. Gärdenfors, and D. Makinson. 1985. On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic 50: 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C.E. 1969. Logic of norms and logic of normative propositions. Logique et Analyse 12: 242–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C.E. 1993. Philosophical foundations of deontic logic and the logic of defeasible conditionals. In Deontic logic in computer science: Normative system specification, ed. J.J. Meyer, and R.J. Wieringa. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C.E., and Bulygin, E. 1971. Normative systems. Vienna: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, C.E., and Bulygin, E. 1984. Permission and permissive norms. In Theorie der Normen ed. W.K. et al. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourron, C.E., and A.A. Martino. 1990. Logic without truth. Ratio Juris 3 (1): 46–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. 1985. Theorie der Grundrechte. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A., and N. Belnap. 1975. Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Åqvist, L. 2001. Deontic logic. In Handbook of philosophical logic, ed. D. Gabbay, and F. Guenthner, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., M. de Rijke, and Y. Venema. 2001. Modal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchette, P. 2001. Logical consequence. In The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic, ed. L. Goble, 2001–2115. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G., Pigozzi, G., and van der Torre, L. 2009. A normative framework for norm change. In Proceedings of AAMAS 2009. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G. and van der Torre, L. 2003a. Permissions and obligations in hierarchical normative systems. In ICAIL’03, 109–118. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G. and van der Torre, L. 2003b. Permissions and undercutters. In NRAC’03, 51–57, Acapulco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G. and van der Torre, L. 2004. Regulative and constitutive norms in normative multiagent systems. In Proceedings of KR2004, ed. D. Dubois, A. Christopher, C.A. Welty, and M. Williams, 255–266. Menlo park: AAAI press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G. and van der Torre, L. 2005. Permission and authorization in normative multiagent systems. In ICAIL’05, 236–237. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. 2000. Conditional obligation and positive permission for agents in time. Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 5 (2): 83–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmo, J., and A. Jones. 2002. Deontic logic and contrary to duties. In Handbook of philosophical logic, ed. D. Gabbay, and F. Guenther, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B.F. 1980. Modal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 2000. Elements of intuitionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etchemendy, J. 1990. The concept of logical consequence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. 2002. Varieties of necessity. In Conceivability and possibility, ed. T.S. Gendler, and J. Hawthorne, 253–281. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Føllesdal, D., and R. Hilpinen. 1971. Deontic logic: An introduction, 1–35. Netherlands, Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrester, J. 1984. Gentle murder, or the adverbial samaritan. Journal of Philosophy 81: 193–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. 1985. Theoretical foundations for non-monotonic reasoning in expert systems. In Logics and models of concurrent systems—NATO ASI series, ed. K. Apt. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. 2006. Sampling labeled deductive systems. In A companion to philosophical logic, ed. D. Jacquette. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D., J. Horty, and X. Parent (eds.). 2013. Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M. 1994. What is a logical system? In What is a logical system?, ed. D.M. Gabbay, 179–216. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. 1969 [1934]. Investigations into logical deduction. In The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen, ed. M.E. Szabo, 68–213. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Governatori, G., F. Olivieri, A. Rotolo, and S. Scannapieco. 2013. Computing strong and weak permissions in defeasible logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (6): 799–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Governatori, G., and A. Rotolo. 2006. Logic of violations: A Gentzen system for reasoning with contrary-to-duty obligations. Australasian Journal of Logic 4: 193–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Governatori, G., and A. Rotolo. 2010. Changing legal systems: Legal abrogations and annulments in defeasible logic. The Logic Journal of IGPL 18 (1): 157–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossi, D. and Rotolo, A. 2011. Logic in law: A concise overview. In Logic and philosophy today—Volume 2 ed. D.M. Gabbay, 251–274. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J. 2005. Conflicting imperatives and dyadic deontic logic. Journal of Applied Logic 3 (3–4): 484–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J., G. Pigozzi, and L. van der Torre. 2007. Ten philosophical problems in deontic logic. In Normative multi-agent systems, number 07122 in DROPS proceedings, ed. G. Boella, L. van der Torre, and H. Verhagen. Germany: Internationales Begegnungs- und Forschungszentrum fuer Informatik (IBFI), Schloss Dagstuhl.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, B. 1969. An analysis of some deontic logics. Nous 3: 373–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, B. 1971. An analysis of some deontic logics, 121–147. Netherlands, Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. 1994. The concept of law. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1982. Essays on Bentham. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. 2001. Deontic logic. In The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic, ed. L. Goble. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jørgensen, J. 1937. Imperatives and logic. Erkentniss, 288–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. 1991. General theory of norms. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kment, B. 2017. Varieties of modality. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta, Spring 2017 edition. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraus, S., D. Lehmann, and M. Magidor. 1990. Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence 44: 167–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. 1959. A completeness theorem in modal logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 24: 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. 1963. Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16: 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krogh, C., and H. Herrestad. 1996. Getting personal: Some notes on the relationship between personal and impersonal obligation. In Deontic logic, agency and normative systems, ed. M. Brown, and J. Carmo, 134–153. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurucz, A., Wolter, F., Zakharyaschev, M., and Gabbay, D.M. 2003. Many-dimensional modal logics: Theory and applications, In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, Vol. 148. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindahl, L., and J. Odelstad. 2000. An algebraic analysis of normative systems. Ratio Juris 13: 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindahl, L., and J. Odelstad. 2008. Intermediaries and intervenients in normative systems. Journal of Applied Logic 6 (2): 229–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. 1999. On a fundamental problem of deontic logic. In Norms, logics and information systems. New studies in deontic logic and computer science, ed. P. McNamara, and H. Prakken, 29–54. Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., and L. van der Torre. 2000. Input-output logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4): 383–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., and L. van der Torre. 2001. Constraints for input/output logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (2): 155–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., and L. van der Torre. 2003. Permission from an input/output perspective. Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (4): 391–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarty, L.T. 1986. Permissions and obligations: An informal introduction. In Automated analysis of legal texts, ed. A.A. Martino, and F. Socci, 307–337. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendelson, E. 1987. Introduction to mathematical logic. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth & Brooks.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parent, X. 2001. Cumulativity, identity and time in deontic logic. Fundamenta informaticae 48 (2–3): 237–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H., and M.J. Sergot. 1996. Contrary-to-duty obligations. Studia Logica 57 (1): 91–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. 2006. In contradiction, a study of the transconsistent. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rotolo, A. 2010. Retroactive legal changes and revision theory in defeasible logic. In Proceedings of the 10th international conference on deontic logic in computer science (DEON 2010), ed. G. Governatori, and G. Sartor, vol. 6181 of LNAI, 116–131. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotolo, A. 2017. Logics for normative supervenience. In Supervenience and normativity, ed. B. Brozek, A. Rotolo, and J. Stelmach. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. 2005. Legal reasoning: A cognitive approach to the law. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. 2006. Fundamental legal concepts: A formal and technological characterisation. Artificial Intelligence and Law 14(1–2): 101–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1999. Development as freedom. New York, NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sergot, M. 2013. Normative positions. In Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems, ed. D. Gabbzy et al., 353–406. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. 2013. Classical logic. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta, Winter 2013 edition. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenius, E. 1963. Principles of a logic of normative systems. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16: 247–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolpe, A. 2010a. Norm-system revision: Theory and application. Artificial Intelligence and Law 18 (3): 247–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stolpe, A. 2010b. Relevance, derogation and permission. In DEON 2010, 98–115. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolpe, A. 2010c. A theory of permission based on the notion of derogation. Journal of Applied Logic 8 (1): 97–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundholm, G. 1983. Systems of deduction. In Handbook of philosophical logic: Volume I: Elements of classical logic, ed. D. Gabbay, and F. Guenthner, 133–188. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. 1983 [1936]. On the concept of logical consequence. In Logic, semantics, metamathematics, 409–420. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J., P. Dekker, J. van Eijck, M. de Rijke, and Y. Venema. 2001. Logic in action. Amsterdam: ILLC, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J., Grossi, D., and Liu, F. 2013. Priority structures in deontic logic. Theoria. 80(2): 116–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Torre, L. 1997. Reasoning about obligations: Defeasibility in preference-based deontic logic. PhD thesis, Erasmus University Rotterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Jhering, R. 1924. Geist des römischen Rechts auf den verschiedenen Stufen seiner Entwicklung, 1st ed. 1852–1865. Leipzig: Breitköpf.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. 1963. Norm and action: A logical inquiry. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G.H. 1951. Deontic logic. Mind 60: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonino Rotolo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature B.V.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Rotolo, A., Sartor, G. (2018). Deductive and Deontic Reasoning. In: Bongiovanni, G., Postema, G., Rotolo, A., Sartor, G., Valentini, C., Walton, D. (eds) Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9452-0_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics