Skip to main content
Log in

Arguing about representation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The question of whether cognition requires representations has engendered heated discussion during the last two decades. I shall argue that the question is, in all likelihood, a spurious one. There may or may not be a fact of the matter concerning whether a given item qualifies as a representation. However, even if there is, attempts to establish whether cognition requires representation have neither practical nor theoretical utility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That is, actually, two tacit quantifiers.

  2. Clark and Toribio (1994) provide a good example of this position.

  3. And don’t get me started on cognition. For my attempts to identify a workable mark of the cognitive, see my (2009). A more developed version can be found in my (2010). But even these provide only sufficient conditions for cognition. Necessary conditions are much harder to identify.

  4. And how we understand the relation of representation will, in turn, have implications for a third sub-question: (3) What are the objects of representation? This third question, though important, plays only a minor part in this paper.

  5. A point well made, in conversation, by Shaun Gallagher. Gallagher’s own focus on decouplability is very evident in his (2008), for example.

  6. See Strawson (2006) for lucid discussion.

  7. This point is well made by Fodor (1990). Most of my thoughts about, say, Paris (i.e. thoughts that, let us suppose, involve the activation and deployment of the PARIS representation), are not caused by Paris, but by other things. This point also provides—and this is the way Fodor uses it—an objection to crude informational accounts of representation (which Fodor regards as a species of causal account).

  8. The inspiration is obviously Kripke (1972). But Kripke does not endorse a crude causal theory either.

  9. Locus classicus, Dretske (1981).

  10. See Fodor (1990) for a good discussion of the discussion problem in the context of informational accounts of representation. With regard to the more sophisticated variations, among the more familiar options from which we will have to choose are Dretske (1985, 1988), the Stalnaker (1984) optimal conditions account, various forms of adverbial theories, and perhaps most sophisticated of all, Fodor (1990) asymmetric dependence theory.

  11. See Millikan (1984, 1993). One big choice we will have to make, of course, will be whether to go with a Millikan-style consumer-based version of teleosemantics or a Dretske-style producer-based alternative. See Dretske (1985) and Dretske (1988).

  12. See Loewer (1997) for useful discussion.

  13. If, for example, one wants to shout ‘Inscrutability of reference!’ at any point in discussion, then one may well be on to something. For my attempts to deal with these sorts of technical problems, see Rowlands (1997).

  14. All these accounts are far more at home dealing with what they regard as ‘simple’ or ‘basic’ cases of representation, which are usually regarded as demonstrative in character: ‘Fly, there!’ and things of that ilk. When the context becomes more complicated, involving declarative rather than demonstrative thought for example, then you are often likely to be told, as Fodor (1990) notes, that the theory is “out to lunch”.

  15. The renewal of interest in concepts (e.g. Fodor (2008))—even if this interest is largely hostile [e.g. Millikan (2000, 2013)]—among those engaged in the project naturalizing semantics is a reflection of the idea that the project will have to try to say something about the idea of a mode of presentation, even if only to disparage it. The general drift is predictable: either a radical externalist theory of concepts or a deflation. That a view is predictable is, of course, no indication that it is incorrect.

  16. More precisely, it would be relevant only to the extent this etiology impacted on the information the state carries or the causal relations into which it enters. Taken on its own, or in itself, etiology would be irrelevant.

  17. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for allowing me to clarify this point.

  18. (Haugeland (1991), p. 62).

  19. For an earlier, less developed, version of this idea, see Rowlands (2006, 2012).

  20. This, in effect, is what the development of progressively more sophisticated attempts to naturalize representation was all about. See Sect. 4.

  21. Both examples due to Clark and Toribio (1994). These sorts of cases are examples of what they call ‘representation-hungry domains’.

  22. See Rowlands (2006) for some of these.

  23. See, for example, Byrne (2005).

  24. See Cleeremans (1993) and Clark and Toribio (1994).

  25. See Gelder (1990).

  26. See Ramsey et al. (1991) for a good overview.

  27. For example: ‘When we examine very simple level intelligence, we find that explicit representations and models of the world simply get in the way. It turns out to be better to use the world as its own model\(\ldots \) Representation is the wrong unit of abstraction in building the bulkiest parts of intelligent systems.’ Rodney (Brooks (1991), p. 140).

  28. See condition 3 of his account of representation above.

  29. I am not claiming, of course, that this is the only condition that must be met for BEACH BAR to constitute a sign, merely that it is one of those conditions.

  30. The positive answer, for example, seems to rule out, by diktat, the possibility of pictorial representation—a staple of much cognitive-scientific practice. For my two pennor’th on why the negative answer should be preferred, see my (2006).

  31. See Rowlands (2013) for an argument to this effect.

  32. This is stronger than Haugeland’s notion of ‘standing in’, since there was nothing in that, taken in itself, that required standing in to take place through awareness of the representational item. It may, of course, be that this is what Haugeland had in mind.

  33. See Fodor (1987), chapter 1, for a classic statement of this view.

  34. And, of course, the various forms of instantiation regress suggest strongly that they are not.

  35. This, in essence, is the fallacy underlying higher-order thought (HOT) accounts of consciousness. Or, at least so I argue in my (2001a) and (2001b).

  36. I wish to thank a reviewer for Synthese for making this point.

  37. Blackburn (1984). See also (Rowlands (1995), pp. 68–73).

  38. I do not, of course, think of this list as exhaustive, but merely as a sampling of the sorts of things that would constitute a fact of the matter about representation.

  39. I would like to thank a reviewer for Synthese for raising this point.

  40. I would like to thank a reviewer for allowing me to clarify this point.

  41. I would like to thank a reviewer for allowing me to clarify this point.

References

  • Blackburn, S. (1984). Spreading the word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2005). Intentionality. In: J. Pfeifer and S. Sarkar (Eds.), Philosophy of science: An encyclopedia. New York: Routledge.

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing. Synthese, 101, 401–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleeremans, A. (1993). Mechanisms of implicit learning: Connectionist models of sequence processing. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1985). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990a). A theory of content and others essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Are minimal representations still representations? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16(3), 351–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational genera. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61–90). New Jersey: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990b). Information and representation. In P. Hanson (Ed.), Information, language and cognition, Vancouver studies in cognitive science (Vol. 1). Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2008). LOT2: The language of thought revisited. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (1997). A guide to naturalizing semantics. In C. Wright & B. Hale (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Millikan, R. (2000). On clear and confused ideas. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2013). Dispensing with concepts (unpublished ms).

  • Ramsey, W., Stich, S., & Rumelhart, D. (Eds.). (1991). Philosophy and connectionist theory. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.

  • Rowlands, M. (1995). Supervenience and materialism. Aldershot: Avebury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1997). Teleological semantics. Mind, 106(422), 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2001a). The nature of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2001b). Consciousness and higher-order thoughts. Mind and Language, 16(3), 290–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2006). Body language: Representation in action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2012). Representing without representations. Avant, 1(2012), 133–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2013). Enactivism, intentionality and content. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(3), 303–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956/1997). In R. Brandom (Ed.), Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1990). Compositionality: A connectionist variation on a classical theme. Cognitive Science, 14, 335–384.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank two reviewers for Synthese for some very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Rowlands.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rowlands, M. Arguing about representation. Synthese 194, 4215–4232 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0646-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0646-4

Keywords

Navigation