Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T14:21:43.231Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Phenomenological Claims and the Myth of the Given

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

Over the past twenty years, Husserlian phenomenology has increasingly drawn the attention of the cognitive community, thereby leading to the emergence of what might be called a phenomenological trend within contemporary cognitive studies. What this phenomenological trend really amounts to is however a matter of debate. The reason is that it embodies, in fact, a multifaceted reflection about the relevance of Husserlian phenomenology to the current efforts towards a scientific theory of cognition, and, to a lesser degree, about the reciprocal relevance of these efforts to the fate of the Husserlian tradition. Indeed, it covers a wide array of perspectives on these questions, ranging from tentative demonstrations of the cognitively misleading character of Husserl's ideas, inasmuch as they would incarnate the same foundational errors as cognitivism (Hall and Dreyfus 1982), to diametrically opposed views arguing that the naturalist bent of contemporary cognitive science is ill-conceived, and that only the brand of transcendentalism defended by Husserl can provide it with adequate foundations (cf., for instance, Villela-Petit 1999).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, W. (1998). “Sellars and the ‘Myth of the Given”,” Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1932). “Die Physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenchaft,” Erkenntnis 3: 432465.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1967) The Logical Structure of the World. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1964/1982). “Theory of Knowledge in America.” In Chisholm, R., ed., The Foundations of Knowing. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Fales, E. (1996). A Defense of the Given. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Firth, R. (1949). “Sense Data and the Percept Theory,” Mind 58:59.Google Scholar
Hall, H., and Dreyfus, H. L. (1982). Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1995). “The Phenomenological Dimension.” In Smith, D. and Smith, B., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Husserl. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1900-1901). Logische Untersuchwzgen. Halle: Max Niemeyer. English trans. by Findlay, J. N., Logical Investigations, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1913). “Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie,” Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung. Halle. English trans. by Gibson, W. R. Boyce, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology, New York: Collier Books, 1972.Google Scholar
Jones, O. R. (1971). The Private Language Argument. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. (1929). Mind and the World-Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Neurath, O. (1932). “Protokollsatze,Erkenntnis 3: 204–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perruchet, P., and Vinter, A. (2002). “The Self-Organizing Consciousness,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25: 297388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petitot, J.P., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M., eds. (1999). Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (1998). “L'intentionnalité au carrefour de Ia phénoménologie et de la tradition sémantique.” In Rigal, E., ed., Jaakko Hintikka. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (1999). “Saving Intentional Phenomena: Intentionality, Representation and Symbol.” In Petitot, J. et al., eds., Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (2000). “La pertinence cognitive de la phénoménologie husserlienne,“ Paper delivered at the October 2000 session of the Phenomenology and Cognition Workshop. Paris.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (2000/2). “Déficit d'explication et revendication phénoménologique.“ Intellectica 31: 3583.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (2003a). “La référence phénoménologique.” In Poust, J. and Pacherie, E., eds., La philosophie cognitive. Paris: Ophrys.Google Scholar
Roy, J.-M. (2003b). “Carnap's Husserlian Reading of the Aufbau.” In Klein, C. and Awodey, S., eds., Rudolf Carnap-From Jena to L.A.: The Roots of Analytical Philosophy. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1956). “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.” In Scriven, H.F.M., ed., Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (1997). “The Mythology of the Given,The History of Philosophy Quarterly 14: 275–86.Google Scholar
Spiegelberg, H. (1994). The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, 3d ed. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J. (1996). “Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy to the Hard Problem,Journal of Consciousness Studies 3(4): 330–49.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1993). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J., Depraz, N., and Vermesch, P. (2000). “The Gesture of Awareness: An Account of its Structural Dynamics.” In Velmans, M., ed., Investigating Phenomenal Consciousness: New Methodologies and Maps. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Villela-Petit, M. (1999). “Cognitive Psychology and the Transcendental Theory of Knowledge.” In Jean Petitot et al., eds., Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Wild, J. (1940). “The Concept of the Given in Contemporary Philosophy- Its Origin and Limitations,Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 1: 7082.CrossRefGoogle Scholar