Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x5gtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-30T18:50:37.800Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Charles Lyell and the Philosophers of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Michael Ruse
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, The University of Guelph, Ontario, CanadaN1G 2W1.

Extract

Two of the most influential evaluations of Charles Lyell's geological ideas were those of the philosophers of science, John F. W. Herschel and William Whewell. In this paper I shall argue that the great difference between these evaluations—whereas Herschel was fundamentally sympathetic to Lyell's geologizing, Whewell was fundamentally opposed—is a function of the fact that Herschel was an empiricist and Whewell a rationalist. For convenience, I shall structure the discussion around the three key elements in Lyell's approach to geology. First, he was an actualist: he wanted to explain past geological phenomena in terms of causes of the kind that are operating at present. Second, he was a uniformitarian: he wanted to explain only in terms of causes of the degree operating at present; that is, he wanted to avoid ‘catastrophes’. Third, as a geologist he saw the earth as being in a steady-state, in which all periods are essentially similar to one another. Because they will prove important, I draw attention also to two major features of Lyell's programme. First, there is his theory of climate, which suggests, ‘without help from a comet’, that earthly temperature fluctuations are primarily a function of the constantly changing distribution of land and sea. Clearly this theory is actualistic, for it is based on such present phenomena as the Gulf Stream; it is also uniformitarian and supports a steady-state world picture. Second, there is Lyell's denial that the fossil record is progressive, his criticism of Lamarckian evolutionism, ostensibly on the grounds that modern evidence is against it (i.e. it fails actualistically), and his rather veiled claim that the origins of species will nevertheless prove in some way natural, that is, subject to causes falling beneath lawlike regularities in principle discernible by us.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British Society for the History of Science 1976

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

1Lyell, C., Principles of geology, being an attempt to explain the former changes of the earth's surface, by reference to causes now in operation (3 vols., London, 18301833).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2 I draw heavily here on Rudwick, M. J. S., ‘The strategy of Lyell's Principles of geology’, Isis, Ixi (1969), 533,Google Scholar
and The meaning of fossils (New York and London, 1972).Google Scholar
3 [Mrs] Lyell, K. M. (ed.), Life, letters and journals of Sir Charles Lyell, Bart. (2 vols., London, 1881), i. 262.Google Scholar
4 The important paper, Bartholomew, Michael, ‘Lyell and evolution: an account of Lyell's response to the prospect of an evolutionary ancestry for man’, The British journal for the history of science, vi (19721973), 261303,Google Scholar
suggests that Lyell must have invoked miracles for organic origins. I have given my reasons for thinking otherwise in my paper, ‘The relationship between science and religion in Britain, 1830–70’, Church history, xliv (1975), 505–22.Google Scholar
5Herschel, J. F. W., A preliminary discourse on the study of natural philosophy (London, 1831).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6 Herschel, of course, had only the first volume of the Principles when he wrote his Discourse.Google Scholar
7Cannon, W. F., ‘The impact of uniformitarianism: two letters from John Herschel to Charles Lyell, 1836–1837’, Proceedings of the American philosophical society, cv (1961), 301–14, especially p. 305.Google Scholar
8Herschel, , Discourse, op. cit. (5), pp. 287–8.Google Scholar
9Herschel, , p. 144.Google Scholar
10Herschel, , p. 149.Google Scholar
See also Kavaloski, V., ‘The “vera causa” principle: an historico-philosophical study of a metatheoretical concept from Newton through Darwin’ (University of Chicago Ph.D. thesis, 1974);Google Scholar
Wilson, D., ‘Herschel and Whewell's version of Newtonianism’, Journal of the history of ideas, xxxv (1974), 7997.Google Scholar
11Lyell, , op. cit. (3), ii. 3.Google Scholar
12Herschel, , Discourse, op. cit. (5), p. 285.Google Scholar
13Cannon, , op. cit. (7), pp. 307–8.Google Scholar
14Herschel, , Discourse, op. cit. (5), p. 285.Google Scholar
15Herschel, , p. 285.Google Scholar
16Herschel, , pp. 146–7.Google Scholar
17Herschel, J. F. W., ‘On the astronomical causes which may influence geological phenomena’, Transactions of the Geological Society of London, iii (1832), 293–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18Herschel, , Discourse, op. cit. (5), p. 283.Google Scholar
19Herschel, , pp. 281–2.Google Scholar
20Herschel, , pp. 282–3.Google Scholar
21Cannon, , op. cit. (7), p. 307.Google Scholar
22Cannon, , p. 307.Google Scholar
23Whewell, W., History of the inductive sciences (3 vols., London, 1837), ii. 127.Google Scholar
24Whewell, W., iii. 481–9.Google Scholar
25Whewell, W., iii. 549.Google Scholar
26Whewell, W., iii. 548.Google Scholar
27Whewell, W., iii. 575–6.Google Scholar
28Whewell, W., Philosophy of the inductive sciences (2 vols., London, 1840), ii. 124.Google Scholar
29 At one point Whewell actually allowed that in the inorganic world ‘all the facts of geological observation are of the same kind as those which occur in the common history of the world’; see [Whewell, W.], ‘Principles of Geology by Charles Lyell, vol. 2’, Quarterly review, xlvii (1832), 108–32, especially p. 126 (his italics). But the context makes it clear that, at most, he was arguing that the causes in the inorganic world are all natural.Google Scholar
30Lyell, , op. cit. (3), ii. 5.Google Scholar
31Lyell, , ii., 6.Google Scholar
32Whewell, , History, op. cit. (23), iii. 617.Google Scholar
33Whewell, , iii. 618.Google Scholar
34Whewell, , Philosophy, op. cit. (28), ii. 441 (his italics).Google Scholar
35Whewell, , ii. 441–2.Google Scholar
36Whewell, , ii. 446.Google Scholar
37 Herschel was aware of, and lauded, consiliences in science, particularly in the context of the wave theory of light, but they were not for him the central constituent of verae causae.Google Scholar
38Whewell, , History, op. cit. (23), iii. 588–9.Google Scholar
39Whewell, , iii. 574.Google Scholar
40Whewell, Google Scholar
41 See Ruse, op. cit. (4).Google Scholar
42Whewell, , Philosophy, op. cit. (28), ii. 126.Google Scholar
43Whewell, , History, op. cit. (23), iii. 616.Google Scholar
44Whewell, , Philosophy, op. cit. (28), ii. 127.Google Scholar
45Whewell, , ii. 118.Google Scholar
46Whewell, , ii. 130.Google Scholar
47Whewell, , History, op. cit. (23), iii. 618–19.Google Scholar
48 [Whewell, ], op. cit. (29), p. 117.Google Scholar