Skip to main content
Log in

Structuralism with and without causation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the status of causation in structuralist metaphysics of physics. What role (if any) does causation play in understanding ‘structure’ in ontological structural realism? I address this question by examining, in a structuralist setting, arguments for and against the idea that fundamental physics deals, perhaps exclusively, with causal properties. I will argue (against Esfeld, Dorato and others) that a structuralist interpretation of fundamental physics should diverge from ‘causal structuralism’. Nevertheless, causation outside fundamental physics, and the basic motivation for causal structuralism outside fundamental physics, can be captured with an appropriate conception of causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See French (2014) for a cutting edge exploration.

  2. Many more can be identified in the history of philosophy. See, for example, Marmodoro (2009).

  3. The idea that objective reality should be identified with invariances originates from Klein’s ‘Erlangen Programme’ (1872). See Ihmig (1999) for an account of its influence on the development of early structuralist philosophy of physics.

  4. Cf. Shoemaker (1980):

    [W]hat makes a property the property it is, what determines its identity, is its potential for contributing to the causal powers of the things that have it. (p. 256)

  5. Cf. Shoemaker (1980):

    My reasons for holding this theory of properties are, broadly speaking, epistemological. Only if some causal theory of properties is true, I believe, can it be explained how properties are capable of engaging our knowledge, and our language, in the way they do. (p. 257)

  6. Cf. Esfeld (2009), for example:

    I maintain that ontic structural realism, as a position in the metaphysics of science that is a form of scientific realism, is committed to causal structures. (p. 180).

  7. Cf. French and Ladyman (2003a):

    [O]ur understanding of structural realism is also informed by the need to provide an ontology that can dissolve some of the metaphysical conundrums of modern physics ...(p. 33).

  8. Different discussions of OSR have focused on different symmetries, ranging from permutation invariance in quantum mechanics [e.g. French and Rickles (2003)], to general covariance of general relativity [e.g. Saunders (2003)], to gauge (Lyre 2004), to the role of symmetry groups in particle physics [e.g. Roberts (2011)].

  9. Cf. French and Ladyman (2003a):

    Charge, typically understood as an intrinsic property ...features in the relevant laws of physics and ...what we have here is a reversal of the classical relationship between the concepts of object and law. (p. 39)

  10. French and Ladyman (2003b) also appeal to causation to this effect, claiming that ‘causal relations constitute a fundamental feature of the structure of the world’. (p. 75) In their respective later developments of OSR both French (2014) and Ladyman [in Ladyman and Ross (2007)] have come to deny that causation plays a fundamental role in OSR.

  11. See e.g. (Van Fraassen (1989), p. 243ff) on the connection between invariance and symmetry.

  12. North’s main exemplar is her study of the relationship between Lagrangian and Hamiltonian mechanics. In these two formulations of classical mechanics different mathematical structures are used to represent the objective features of the physics, and North has argued that Lagrangian mechanics posits ‘excess structure’, and that Hamiltonian mechanics is for that reason more fundamental, revealing the ‘real structure’. This claim has been criticised by Curiel (2014) and Barrett (2013), for example.

  13. Cf. Ney (2009):

    [According to causal foundationalism] causation is fundamentally a microphysical phenomenon, which can be discovered by looking directly at our fundamental physical theories. The obtaining of [all] causal facts depends on the obtaining of facts about physical causation. (p. 741)

  14. See Field (2003) and Ney (2009) for further details and discussion.

  15. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Electric_charge

  16. Full details can be found in any gauge/quantum field theory textbook, e.g. Ryder (1985).

  17. Continuous symmetry is one specified by parameters that can be varied continuously starting from arbitrarily close to the ‘identity transformation’ (which does not transform the system at all). Lagrangian is a function that completely encodes the dynamics of a system in the sense that it yields the correct equations of motion by substitution into the Euler-Lagrance equation.

  18. External symmetries involve spatiotemporal variables: translations, time displacements, rotations.

  19. In the local transformation the rotation \(\Lambda \) (in the internal variable space) is a function of spatiotemporal location \(x\).

  20. See also Livanios (2010) for a convincing criticism of dispositional essentialism from a perspective that is closely related to mine.

  21. For just one example, consider Steven Weinberg: “Symmetries are fundamental, and possibly all that one needs to learn about the physical world beyond quantum mechanics itself.” (Feynman and Weinberg 1987, p. 79)

  22. Cf. Esfeld (2009)

    One can avoid these [quidditistic] commitments by taking the essence of the properties to be tied to the causal and nomological relations in which they stand (Shoemaker 1980). (p. 183)

    We can delete ‘causal’ in the above without affecting the central idea.

  23. See also Dorato and Esfeld (2010).

  24. Cf. (Esfeld 2009, p .188), who talks about such dispositions being ‘irreducible’:

    This disposition is irreducible: it is not grounded on non-dispositional, categorical properties. It belongs to the ontological ground floor. It is a real and actual property, not a mere potentiality. It is therefore appropriate to talk in terms of a power for spontaneous localization, this disposition being a causal property that brings about spontaneous localizations. This disposition does not need external manifestation conditions: that is why GRW conceive the disposition in question as one for spontaneous localization.

  25. Esfeld et al. (2013) only focuses on the ontology of Bohmian mechanics and is not at all concerned with structuralism. I’m reading it in the context of Esfeld’s wider campaign for a Causal Structuralist construal of OSR.

  26. See e.g. Ladyman and Ross (2007) for a structuralist critique of this kind of metaphysics.

References

  • Barrett, T. W. (2013). On the structure of classical mechanics. Preprint (Foundations of Physics 2013 conference), http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9603/

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Dispositions, laws, and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curiel, E. (2014). Classical mechanics is Lagrangian; it is not Hamiltonian. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(2), 269–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M., & Esfeld, M. (2010). GRW as an ontology of dispositions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B, 41(1), 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. & Lam, V. (2008). Moderate structural realism aboutspace-time. Synthese, 160, 27–46.

  • Esfeld, M. (2009). The modal nature of structures in ontic structural realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23(2), 179–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2010). Physics and causation. Foundations of Physics, 40(9–10), 1597–1610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., Hubert, M., Lazarovici, D., & Drr, D. (2013). The ontology of Bohmian mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. Advance access

  • Esfeld, M., & Lam, V. (2011). Ontic structuralism as a metaphysics of objects. In A. Bokulich & P. Bokulich (Eds.), Scientific structuralism (pp. 143–159). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Feynman, R. P., & Weinberg S. (1987). Elementary particles and the laws of physics: The 1986 Dirac memorial lectures. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Field, H. (2003). Causation in a physical world. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 435–460). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: From representation to reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003a). Remodelling structural realism: Quantum physics and the metaphysics of structure. Synthese, 136(1), 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003b). The dissolution of objects: Between platonism and phenomenalism. Synthese, 136(1), 73–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Rickles, D. (2003). Understanding permutation symmetry. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections (pp. 212–238). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, E. Hall, & L. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Hawthorne, J. (2001). Causal structuralism. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 361–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihmig, K.-N. (1999). Ernst Cassirer and the structural conception of objects in modern science: The importance of the ‘Erlanger programme’. Science in Context, 12, 513–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29A, 409–424.

  • Ladyman, J. (2013). Structural realism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Summer 2013 Edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/structural-realism/

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Livanios, V. (2010). Symmetries, dispositions and essences. Philosophical Studies, 148(2), 295–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2004). Holism and structuralismin U(1) gauge theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35, 597–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmodoro, A. (2009). Do powers need powers to make them powerful? From pandispositionalism to Aristotle. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 26(4), 337–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2009). Physical causation and difference-making. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 737–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, J. (2009). The “structure” of physics: A case study. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 57–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H., & Corry, R. (2007). Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rickles, D. (2008). Who’s afraid of background independence? Philosophy and Foundations of Physics, 4, 133–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, B. W. (2011). Group structural realism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 47–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, L. (1985). Quantum field theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Saunders, S. (2003). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Identity, cause and mind (Second expanded edition, 2003 ed.)., Chapter causality and properties (pp. 206–33). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Suppes, P. (1967). What is a Scientific Theory? In S. Morgenbesser (Ed.), Philosophy of science today (pp. 55–67). New York: Basic Books.

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2007). Causation with a human face. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited (pp. 66–105). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica 43, 99–124. Reprinted in D. Papineau (Ed.) The Philosophy of science (pp. 139–165). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at University of Leeds and University of Cologne. I would like to thank audiences at these talks. Special thanks to Michael Esfeld, Steven French, Andreas Hüttemann, and Jakob Sprickerhof. I would also like to acknowledge that this paper was partly written during my visiting Fellowship at Durham Institute of Advanced Studies (IAS).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juha Saatsi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Saatsi, J. Structuralism with and without causation. Synthese 194, 2255–2271 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0595-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0595-y

Keywords

Navigation