Skip to main content
Log in

Rarely Pure and Never Simple: Tensions in the Theory of Truth

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Section 1 discerns ambiguity in the word “truth”, observing that the term is used most naturally in reference to truth-bearers rather than truth-makers. Focusing on truths-as-truth-bearers, then, it would appear that alethic realism conflicts with metaphysical realism as naturalistically construed. Section 2 discerns ambiguity in the purporting of truth (as in assertion), conjecturing that all expressions, not just those found in traditionally recognized opaque contexts, can be read intensionally (as well, perhaps, as extensionally). For instance, we would not generally want to say that “The Matterhorn is 4,500 m high” expresses the same truth as “The Matterhorn is 14763.7795276 feet high” (or that it is true in the same range of utterance contexts), even though the two are extensionally equivalent. The reason is that they express different intensions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. When I speak of extensional equivalences and apparent truth-conditions, I speak of the sorts of appearances that are widespread in the population of analytic philosophers. For an explanation as to why linguistic extensions and truth-conditions are not apparent to everyone, see Saka (2007).

  2. Cf. David (2005: 157) and Merricks (2007: ch 1.II).

  3. It may be objected that “awake to” is implicitly an attitude predicate, so in line (2) “the morning star” does not appear in a genuine transparent context. For (2) to evoke or imply someone’s attitude, however, does not mean that (2) denotes or expresses any attitude; the literal semantics of “awake to” does not qualify it, under orthodox theory, as an opaque context. What’s more, other examples can be found that take us even further from attitude predicates (e.g. Jennifer Saul’s “Superman left the phone booth” versus “Clark Kent left the phone booth”).

  4. “It is the mark of an educated man to look for precision,” says Aristotle, “just so far as the nature of the subject admits” (Nicomachean Ethics I.3).

  5. There is also realism about T-schemas (Alston 1996: 27, Searle 1997: 202, Merricks 2007: 175, et alia), but this terminology is unfortunate. Whereas realisms normally hinge on the mind-independent existence of something, realism about the T-schema depends on the T-schema’s validity.

  6. Terminological diagnoses and stipulations are more than intellectual masturbation. If intensionalism is correct, and possibly even if it isn’t, language influences our perceived reality and helps to frame issues. In that case, it’s worth inquiring into the terminology we have and deliberating over reforms.

  7. This paper benefitted from contributions by Amy Copland, Steven Crowell, Tim Huber, and Bert Koegler, and to them I am grateful.

References

  • Alston W (1996) A realist conception of truth. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (2004) Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (1987) Thought and reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • David M (2005) Armstrong on truthmaking. In: Beebee H, Dodd J (eds) Truthmakers. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (1991) Realism and truth. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey J, Bentley A (1948) Knowing and the known. Beacon Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin C (1997) Between the absolute and the arbitrary. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton R (2002) Realism and the correspondence theory of truth. Rowman & Littlefield, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner M (1983) The whys of a philosophical scrivener. William Morrow, New York

  • Gibbs R (1994) The poetics of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A (1999) Knowledge in a social world. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grandy R (1986) Some misconceptions about belief. In: Grandy R, Warner R (eds) Philosophical grounds of rationality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich P (1990) Truth. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Henry Holt, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kirkham R (1992) Theories of truth. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka M (2009) Approximate interpretations of number words. In: Hinrichs E & Nerbonne J (eds) Theory and evidence in semantics. CSLI, Stanford

  • Kunne W (2003) Conceptions of truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1980) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks T (2007) Truth and ontology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkola M (2008) Feminist perspectives on sex and gender. Stanford Encyclopedia Philos, Accessed 2 Feb 2009

  • Putnam H (1981) Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1998) Truth and progress: philosophical papers, vol 3. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saka P (2007) The argument from ignorance against truth-conditional semantics. American Philosophical Quarterly 44(2):157–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka P (2008) How to think about meaning. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul J (1997) Substitution and simple sentences. Analysis 57:300–308

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt F (1996) Truth: a primer. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1979) Referential and attributive. In: Expression and meaning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Searle J (1997) The construction of social reality. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers F (1997) Putnam’s born-again realism. J Philos 94:453–471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich S (1986) Are belief predicates systematically ambiguous? In: Bogdan R (ed) Belief. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tennant N (1997) The taming of the true. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Saka.

Additional information

“The truth,” says Oscar Wilde, “is rarely pure and never simple” (The Importance of Being Earnest).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Saka, P. Rarely Pure and Never Simple: Tensions in the Theory of Truth. Topoi 29, 125–135 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-009-9072-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-009-9072-5

Keywords

Navigation