Skip to main content
Log in

Psychopaths and Filthy Desks

Are Emotions Necessary and Sufficient for Moral Judgment?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophical and empirical moral psychologists claim that emotions are both necessary and sufficient for moral judgment. The aim of this paper is to assess the evidence in favor of both claims and to show how a moderate rationalist position about moral judgment can be defended nonetheless. The experimental evidence for both the necessity- and the sufficiency-thesis concerning the connection between emotional reactions and moral judgment is presented. I argue that a rationalist about moral judgment can be happy to accept the necessity-thesis. My argument draws on the idea that emotions play the same role for moral judgment that perceptions play for ordinary judgments about the external world. I develop a rationalist interpretation of the sufficiency-thesis and show that it can successfully account for the available empirical evidence. The general idea is that the rationalist can accept the claim that emotional reactions are sufficient for moral judgment just in case a subject’s emotional reaction towards an action in question causes the judgment in a way that can be reflectively endorsed under conditions of full information and rationality. This idea is spelled out in some detail and it is argued that a moral agent is entitled to her endorsement if the way she arrives at her judgment reliably leads to correct moral beliefs, and that this reliability can be established if the subject’s emotional reaction picks up on the morally relevant aspects of the situation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The most obvious and straigthforward way for the rationalist about moral judgment to incorporate the necessity-thesis seems to be to argue for a cognitivist position in the theory of emotion. If emotions just are cognitive states (evaluative judgments), then the fact that emotions are necessary for moral judgment does not have to intimidate the rationalist the slightest bit. For an overview over this position, see Deigh 1994. For a defense of cognitivism about emotions, see Solomon 1976; de Sousa 1987; Greenspan 1988; Helm 2001; Stocker and Hegeman 1996; Nussbaum 2001. I do not argue for emotional cognitivism in this paper, because I want to avoid the problems the cognitivist has with offering a psychologically realistic picture of the emotions without overintellectualizing them (a point that Peter Goldie (2000) insists on).

  2. In what follows, I shall argue that emotions are sufficient for moral judgments only if they cause them in a justification-conveying way. On a dispositional view of the emotions, there seems to be a problem with unmanifested dispositions. If there can be such dispositions, and it seems that there can, one might ask how these can convey any justificatory force to the judgments which are based on them. In the theory of moral judgment, the motivation to use a dispositional concept of emotions is to allow for cases in which the respective emotion is not occurrent. The content of the judgment has been committed to memory. This is impossible, however, if the disposition to have a certain emotional reaction that judgment is based on has never been manifested. Thus, the problem of unmanifested dispositions will, though metaphysically possible, typically not be a problem in the case of emotional dispositions.

  3. This, in a nutshell, is Prinz’ “constructive sentimentalism”, cf. Prinz 2007.

  4. The concept of reliability employed here may strike some as odd, because reliability doesn’t seem to be about getting it right in a range of circumstances, but about getting it right on most occasions. In this sense, my use of the concept of reliability is stipulative to a certain extent. Roughly, what I have in mind is that a method of judgment-formation is reliable if it satisfies a sensitivity-condition (a judgment that p is sensitive iff ∼p → ∼Bx(p) and p → Bx(p), cf. Nozick 1981, 176). Both conditions are important because, given the empirical evidence, disgust reponses that pick up on extraneous features are ruled out by the first conjunct, cases of artifical mood induction that prevents people from picking up on morally relevant features are ruled out by the second conjunct. For an overview over the concept of reliability in general epistemology, see Pritchard 2005.

  5. Neo-Sentimentalist accounts of moral judgment analyze moral judgments similarly, namely in terms of conditions of appropriateness for emotional reactions: on that view, to make a moral judgment is to think it appropriate to have an emotional reponse (of guilt, resentment etc.) towards an action, person, or event (see, for example, Wiggins 1998; Gibbard 1990; McDowell 1998). I have argued elsewhere (Sauer 2011) that this account is not successful, particularly because it does not offer a satisfactory response to the so-called “conflation problem” (D’Arms and Jacobson 2000; Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen 2004; Olson 2004).

References

  • Appiah KA (2008) Experiments in ethics. Harvard UP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly N (2003) Unprincipled virtue. An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJR (1995) A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair J, Mitchell D, Blair K (2005) The psychopath. Emotion and the brain. Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady MS (2008) The irrationality of recalcitrant emotions. Philos Stud 145(3):413–430

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman HA, Kim DA, Susskind JM, Anderson AK (2009) In bad taste: evidence for the oral origins of moral disgust. Science 323:1222–1226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cima M, Tonnaer F et al (2010) Psychopaths know right from wrong but don’t care. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci 5:59–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio A (1994) Descartes’ error. Emotion, reason, and the human brain. Gossett/Putnam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Damm L (2010) Emotions and moral agency. Philos Explor 13(3):275–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms J (2005) Two arguments for sentimentalism. Philos Issues 15:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms J, Jacobson D (2000) Sentiment and value. Ethics 110:722–748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deigh J (1994) Cognitivism in the theory of emotions. Ethics 104(4):824–854

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna JA (2006) Emotion, perception and perspective. Dialectica 60(1):29–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa R (1987) The rationality of emotion. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa R (2001) Moral emotions. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 4(2):109–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Döring S (2007) Seeing what to do: affective perception and rational motivation. Dialectica 61(3):363–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerrans P, Kennett J (2010) Neurosentimentalism and moral agency. Mind 119(475):585–614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1990) Wise choices, apt feelings. A theory of normative judgment. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2000) The emotions. A philosophical exploration. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2004a) Emotion, reason, and virtue. In: Evans D, Cruse P (eds) Emotion, evolution, and rationality. Oxford UP, Oxford, pp 249–267

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2004b) Emotion, feeling, and knowledge of the world. In: Solomon R (ed) Thinking about feeling: contemporary philosophers on emotion. Oxford UP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie P (2007) Seeing what is the kind of thing to do. Perception and emotion in morality. Dialectica 61(3):347–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD, Sommerville RB, Nystrom LE, Darley JM, Cohen JD (2001) An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293:2105–2108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan PS (1988) Emotions and reasons: an inquiry into emotional justification. Routledge, Chapman and Hall, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunther Y (2003) In: Gunther Y (ed) Emotions and force. Essays on nonconceptual content. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 279–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108(4):814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J, Rozin P, McCauley C, Imada S (1997) Body, psyche, and culture: the relationship between disgust and morality. Psychol Dev Soc 9(1):107–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare RD (1999) Without conscience. The disturbing world of the psychopaths among us. Guilford, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (2007) Ethics and observation. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Ethical theory. An anthology. Blackwell, Malden, pp 36–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Helm BW (2001) Emotional reason. Deliberation, motivation and the nature of value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson D (2008) Does social intuitionism flatter morality or challenge it? In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology vol. 2: the cognitive science of morality: intuition and diversity. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 219–233

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones K (2006) Metaethics and emotions research. A response to Prinz. Philos Explor 9(1):45–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2007) The evolution of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (2009) Will the real moral judgment please stand up? The implications of social intuitionist models of cognition for meta-ethics and moral psychology. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 12:77–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J, Fine C (2008) Internalism and the evidence from psychopaths and “acquired sociopaths”. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology vol. 3: the neuroscience of morality: emotion, brain disorders, and development. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 173–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe J, Nichols S (2008) Experimental philosophy. Oxford UP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs M, Young L, Adolphs R, Tranel D, Cushman F, Hauser M, Damasio A (2007) Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgments. Nature 446:908–911

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1985) Values and secondary qualities. In: Honderich T (ed) Morality and objectivity. Routledge, London, pp 110–129

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1994) Mind and world. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1998) Projection and truth in ethics. In: McDowell J (ed) Mind, value and reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 151–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S (2004) Sentimental rules. On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford UP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1981) Philosophical explanations. Belknap, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nucci L (1985) Children’s conceptions of morality, social conventions and religious prescription. In: Harding C (ed) Moral dilemmas: philosophical and psychological reconsiderations of moral reasoning. Precedent, Chicago, pp 137–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum M (2001) Upheavals of thought. The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson J (2004) Buck-passing and the wrong kind of reasons. Philos Q 54:295–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2006) The emotional basis of moral judgment. Philos Explor 9(1):29–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2007) The emotional construction of morals. Oxford UP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard D (2005) Epistemic luck. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz W, Rønnow-Rasmussen T (2004) The strike of the demon: on fitting pro-attitudes and value. Ethics 114:391–424

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roskies A (2003) Are ethical judgments intrinsically motivational? Lessons from “acquired sociopathy”. Philos Psychol 16(1):51–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauer H (2011) The appropriateness of emotions. Moral judgment, moral emotions, and the conflation problem. Ethical Perspectives 18(1):107–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Saver JL, Damasio AR (1991) Preserved access and processing of social knowledge in a patient with acquired sociopathy due to ventromedial frontal damage. Neuropsychologia 29(12):1241–1249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnall S, Haidt J, Clore GL, Jordan A (2008) Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 34:1096–1109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz N, Clore GL (1983) Mood, misattribution, and judgments of well-being: informative and directive functions of affective states. J Pers Soc Psychol 45(3):513–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote M (2004) Moral sentimentalism. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 7:3–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1994) The moral problem. Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon RC (1976) The passions. Emotions and the meaning of life. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Stocker M, Hegeman E (1996) Valuing emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet C (2011) Emotions, perceptions, and emotional illusions. In: Calabi C (ed) The crooked oar, the moon’s size and the Kanisza triangle. Essays on perceptual illusions. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel E (1983) The development of social knowledge: morality and convention. Cambridge UP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Valdesolo P, DeSteno D (2006) Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychol Sci 17(6):476–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley T, Haidt J (2005) Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychol Sci 16(10):780–784

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1998) A sensible subjectivism? In: Wiggins D (ed) Needs, values, and truth. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 185–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1981) Persons, character and morality. In: Williams B (ed) Moral luck. Cambridge UP, Cambridge, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson TD, Brekke N (1994) Mental contamination and mental correction: unwanted influences on judgments and evaluations. Psychol Bull 116:117–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Tom Bates, Pauline Kleingeld and Markus Schlosser for their very helpful comments to an earlier version of this paper. I am also indebted to the organizers and participants of the workshop Philosophical Implications of Empirically Informed Ethics at the University of Zürich, March 2010, especially to Anne Burkard, Markus Christen, Jan Gertken, Bert Musschenga, Hichem Naar and Shaun Nichols. Two anonymous referees from Ethical Theory and Moral Practice have made very useful suggestions, for which I would like to thank them as well.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hanno Sauer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sauer, H. Psychopaths and Filthy Desks. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 15, 95–115 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9274-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9274-y

Keywords

Navigation