Skip to main content
Log in

A New Way of Thinking about Social Location in Science

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Durkheimian concept of the density of social relationships may prove more fruitful than the historical materialist notion of a social hierarchy for thinking about the social location of epistemic agents in science. To define a scientist’s social location in terms of the density of her professional relationships with other scientists permits us to give a more precise characterization of marginalization and thus to formulate more testable hypotheses about marginalized groups in science. The notion of social density helps to explain not only how some individual scientists are more likely than others to get a hearing for their ideas, but also how scientific inquiry flourishes more in some societies than in others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The way she explained it in an earlier paper appears to subsume the other conditions under one’s location in a hierarchy: ‘What counts as a “social location” is structurally defined. What individuals experience and understand is shaped by their location in a hierarchically structured system of power relations: by the material conditions of their lives, by the relations of production and reproduction that structure their social interactions, and by the conceptual resources they have to represent and interpret these relations’ (Wylie 2003, p. 31).

  2. By ‘framework assumptions’, Wylie appears to mean assumptions regarding a social framework of power relationships and not a conceptual framework. The paragraph from which this quotation is taken deals with social structure and social hierarchy.

  3. Donna Haraway (1991, pp. 183–201) makes a somewhat different but related point in her essay ‘Situated Knowledges’, emphasizing how our sense experiences are embodied.

  4. Longino (2002a, p. 146) quotes Nelson as saying, ‘I know only what we know for some we’.

  5. It is not at all clear that if everyone in some culture has the same categories, that they will therefore have the same beliefs. I take up this question in the last section. See also: Schmaus (2007).

  6. Just what Longino’s ‘non-monism’ or pluralism amounts to is not at all clear. See, for example, Kitcher (2002). However, this ambiguity does not affect her defense of non-individualism and non-relativism.

  7. Critics such as Miriam Solomon and Alan Richardson (2005, p. 215) question whether there is any empirical support from the history of science for Longino’s position that the growth of scientific knowledge depends on this fourth condition. It should be kept in mind, of course, that Longino’s four conditions are ideals and are not meant to be descriptive of any particular scientific community at any period in history.

References

  • Ben-David J, Aran L (1991) Socialization and career patterns as determinants of productivity of medical researchers. In: Freudenthal G (ed) Scientific growth: essays on the social organization and ethos of science. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, pp 321–342

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane D (1972) Invisible colleges: diffusion of knowledge in scientific communities. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim E (1893) De la division du travail social: étude sur l’organisation des sociétés supérieures. Alcan, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim E (1895) Les Règles de la méthode sociologique. Alcan, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim E (1955) Pragmatisme et sociologie. Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim E (1983) Pragmatism and sociology, translation of Durkheim 1955 by J. C. Whitehouse. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaines LJ (1998) The roots of a woman. In: Pattatuci A (ed) Women in science. Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks, CA, pp 73–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway D (1991) Simians, cyborgs, and women: the reinvention of nature. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding S (1986) The science question in feminism. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding S (1991) Whose science? Whose knowledge? Thinking from women’s lives. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (2001) Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (2002) The third way: reflections on Longino’s The fate of knowledge. Philos Sci 69:549–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L (1981) Science and hypothesis. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon K (2003) Naturalising and interpretive turns in epistemology. Int J Philos Stud 11:245–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennon K (2004) Feminist epistemology. In: Niiniluoto I, Sintonen M, Wolenski J (eds) Handbook of epistemology. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 1013–1026

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (2002a) The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (2002b) Reply to Philip Kitcher. Philos Sci 69:573–577

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton RK (1965) On the shoulders of giants: a Shandean postscript. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick C (1994) Feminist epistemology: implication for philosophy of science. Philos Sci 61:646–657

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rollin K (2002) Gender and trust in science. Hypatia 17:95–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmaus W (2007) Categories and classification in the social sciences. In: Turner SP, Risjord MW (eds) Philosophy of anthropology and sociology, handbook of the philosophy of science, vol 8. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 429–458

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scott JW (1991) The evidence of experience. Crit Inq 17:773–797

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon M, Richardson A (2005) A critical context for Longino’s critical contextual empiricism’ (essay review). Stud Hist Philos Sci 36:211–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnert G, Holton G (1995) Gender differences in science careers. The project access study. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson JD (1969) The double helix. Atheneum, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2002) The epistemic significance of collaborative research. Philos Sci 69:150–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray KB (2007) Evaluating scientists: examining the effects of sexism and nepotism. In: Kincaid H, Dupré J, Wylie A (eds) Value-free science? ideals and illusions. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 87–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie A (2003) Why standpoint matters. In: Figueroa R, Harding S (eds) Science and other cultures: issues in philosophies of science and technology. Routledge, New York, pp 26–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie A (2007) The feminism question in science: what does it mean to “Do social science as a feminist”? In: Hesse-Biber S (ed) Handbook of feminist research. Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA, pp 567–577

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Warren Schmaus.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schmaus, W. A New Way of Thinking about Social Location in Science. Sci & Educ 17, 1127–1137 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9129-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9129-z

Keywords

Navigation