Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T07:54:36.382Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bayesianism and Scientific Reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2022

Jonah N. Schupbach
Affiliation:
University of Utah

Summary

This Element explores the Bayesian approach to the logic and epistemology of scientific reasoning. Section 1 introduces the probability calculus as an appealing generalization of classical logic for uncertain reasoning. Section 2 explores some of the vast terrain of Bayesian epistemology. Three epistemological postulates suggested by Thomas Bayes in his seminal work guide the exploration. This section discusses modern developments and defenses of these postulates as well as some important criticisms and complications that lie in wait for the Bayesian epistemologist. Section 3 applies the formal tools and principles of the first two sections to a handful of topics in the epistemology of scientific reasoning: confirmation, explanatory reasoning, evidential diversity and robustness analysis, hypothesis competition, and Ockham's Razor.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781108657563
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 31 March 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alvarez, L. W., Alvarez, W., Asaro, F., and Michel, H. V (1980). Extraterrestrial cause for the Cretaceous-Tertiary extinction. Science, 208(4448):10951108.Google Scholar
Archibald, J. D. et al., (2010). Cretaceous extinctions: multiple causes. Science, 328(5981):973.Google Scholar
Bacchus, F. (1990). Representing and Reasoning with Probabilistic Knowledge: A Logical Approach to Probabilities. Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Y. and Carnap, R. (1953). Semantic information. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4(14):147157.Google Scholar
Barnes, J., ed. (1984). The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 6th edition.Google Scholar
Bayes, T. (1763). An essay towards solving a problem in the doctrine of chances. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 53:370418.Google Scholar
Belot, G. (2013). Bayesian orgulity. Philosophy of Science, 80(4):483503.Google Scholar
Bertrand, J. (1889). Calcul des Probabilités. Gauthier-Villars, Paris.Google Scholar
Birnbaum, A. (1962). On the foundations of statistical inference. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 57(298):269306.Google Scholar
Blackwell, D. and Dubins, L. (1962). Merging of opinions with increasing information. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 33(3):882886.Google Scholar
Bolzano, B. (1837). Theory of Science. Blackwell, Oxford, 1972 edition. Translated by Rolf George.Google Scholar
Boole, G. (1854). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought: on Which Are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Macmillan and Co., London.Google Scholar
Bovens, L. and Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian Epistemology. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
Bradley, S. and Steele, K. (2014). Uncertainty, learning, and the “problem” of dilation. Erkenntnis, 79(6):12871303.Google Scholar
Brössel, P. (2015). On the role of explanatory and systematic power in scientific reasoning. Synthese, 192(12):38773913.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R. (1828). A brief account of microscopical observations on the particles contained in the pollen of plants; and on the general existence of active molecules in organic and inorganic bodies. Edinburgh New Philosophical Journal, 5:358371. Page references are to Brown’s unpublished report.Google Scholar
Buchak, L. (2013). Belief, credence, and norms. Philosophical Studies, 169(2):285311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calcott, B. (2011). Wimsatt and the robustness family: review of Wimsatt’s Re-engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Biology & Philosophy, 26(2):281293.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1947). On the application of inductive logic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 8(1):133148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. (1955). Statistical and Inductive Probability. The Galois Institute of Mathematics and Art, Brooklyn, New York, pages 279287.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1962). Logical Foundations of Probability. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2nd edition.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1991). Replicability, reproducibility, and robustness: comments on Harry Collins. History of Political Economy, 23(1):143155.Google Scholar
Chesterton, G. K. (1908). Orthodoxy. John Lane Company, New York.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. (1996). Dutch-book arguments depragmatized: epistemic consistency for partial believers. The Journal of Philosophy, 93(9):450479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3):551582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, M. P. (2015). On Schupbach and Sprenger’s measures of explanatory power. Philosophy of Science, 82(1):97109.Google Scholar
Cohen, M. P. (2016). On three measures of explanatory power with axiomatic representations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67(4):10771089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2004). The philosophical significance of Cox’s theorem. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 37(1):7185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2008). Is probability the only coherent approach to uncertainty? Risk Analysis, 28(3):645652.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Colyvan, M. (2013). Idealisations in normative models. Synthese, 190(8): 13371350.Google Scholar
Courtillot, V. and Fluteau, F. (2010). Cretaceous extinctions: the volcanic hypothesis. Science, 328(5981):973974.Google Scholar
Cox, R. T. (1946). Probability, frequency and reasonable expectation. American Journal of Physics, 14(1):113.Google Scholar
Cox, R. T. (1961). The Algebra of Probable Inference. The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD.Google Scholar
Crupi, V., Fitelson, B., and Tentori, K. (2008). Probability, confirmation, and the conjunction fallacy. Thinking and Reasoning, 14(2):182199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crupi, V and Tentori, K. (2012). A second look at the logic of explanatory power (with two novel representation theorems). Philosophy of Science, 79(3):365385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crupi, V., Tentori, K., and Gonzalez, M. (2007). On Bayesian measures of evidential support: theoretical and empirical issues. Philosophy of Science, 74(2):229252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Culp, S. (1994). Defending robustness: the bacterial mesosome as a test case. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1: Contributed Papers:4657.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1872). The Origin of Species. John Murray, London, 6th edition. Page references are to the Modern Library edition, 1998.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. (2017). Theory of Probability: A Critical Introductory Treatment. Wiley Series in Probability and Statistics. John Wiley & Sons, New York.Google Scholar
Douven, I. (2013). Inference to the Best Explanation, Dutch Books, and inaccuracy minimisation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 63(252):428444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douven, I. (2020). The ecological rationality of explanatory reasoning. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 79(Feb.):114.Google Scholar
Duns Scotus, J. (1998). Questions of the Metaphysics of Aristotle, Text Series, no. 19, vol. 2. Franciscan Institute Publishers, St. Bonaventure, NY.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory. Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Easwaran, K. (2016). Conditional probability. In Hájek, A. and Hitchcock, C., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy, chapter 9, pages 167182. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Easwaran, K. (2019). Conditional probabilities. In Pettigrew, R. and Weisberg, J., eds., The Open Handbook of Formal Epistemology, pages 131198. PhilPapers Foundation. ISBN 978–1–9991763–0-3Google Scholar
Edwards, A. W. F. (1992). Likelihood: An Account of the Statistical Concept of Likelihood and Its Application to Scientific Inference. The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, expanded edition. First edition published 1972.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. and Infeld, L. (1938). The Evolution of Physics: From Early Concepts to Relativity and Quanta. Simon & Schuster, New York.Google Scholar
Feldman, M. (1991). On the generic nonconvergence of Bayesian actions and beliefs. Economic Theory, 1(4):301321.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (1996). Wayne, Horwich, and evidential diversity. Philosophy of Science, 63(4):652660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B. (1999). The plurality of Bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity. Philosophy of Science, 66(Supp.):S362-S378.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2001a). A Bayesian account of independent evidence with applications. Philosophy of Science, 68(3):S123-S140.Google Scholar
Fitelson, B. (2001b). Studies in Bayesian Confirmation Theory. PhD thesis, University of Wisconsin – Madison.Google Scholar
Forster, M. R. and Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45:135.Google Scholar
Gaifman, H. and Snir, M. (1982). Probabilities over rich languages, testing and randomness. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47(3):495548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, D. (1983). Old evidence and logical omniscience in Bayesian confirmation theory. In Earman, J., ed., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. X, pages 99131. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.Google Scholar
Garwood, C. (2008). Flat Earth: The History of an Infamous Idea. Thomas Dunne Books, New York.Google Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2012). Inference to the Best Explanation: does it track truth? Synthese, 185:411427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2016). Science, God and Ockham’s razor. Philosophical Studies, 174(5):11451161Google Scholar
Glass, D. H. (2021). Information and explanatory goodness. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and Evidence. Princeton University Press, Princeton.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1960). Weight of evidence, corroboration, explanatory power, information and the utility of experiments. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B (Methodological), 22(2):319331.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1966). A derivation of the probabilistic explication of information. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society: Series B (Methodological), 28(3):578581.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1968). Corroboration, explanation, evolving probability, simplicity and a sharpened razor. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19(2):123143.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1965). Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. (2006). The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of the Early Ideas About Probability, Induction, and Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2nd edition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haenni, R., Romeijn, J.-W., Wheeler, G., and Williamson, J. (2010). Probabilistic Logic and Probabilistic Networks. The Synthese Library. Springer, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2003). What conditional probability could not be. Synthese, 137:273323.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2009). What conditional probability also could not be: reply to Kenny Easwaran. Unpublished.Google Scholar
Halpern, J. Y. (1999a). A counterexample to theorems of Cox and Fine. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 10(1):6785.Google Scholar
Halpern, J. Y. (1999b). Cox’s theorem revisited. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 11:429435.Google Scholar
Harman, G. H. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74(1):8895.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1945). Studies in the logic of confirmation II. Mind, 54(214):97121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. In Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, pages 331496. Free Press, New York.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2):135175.Google Scholar
Hildebrand et al, A. R. (1991). Chicxulub crater: a possible Cretaceous/Tertiary boundary impact crater on the Yucatan Peninsula, Mexico. Geology, 19:867871.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. (2017). Troubles for Bayesian formal epistemology. Res Philosophica, 94(2):233255.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. (1982). Probability and Evidence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (2000). Hume’s Problem: Induction and the Justification of Belief. Clarendon Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (2011). Bayesianism as a pure logic of inference. In Bandyopad-hyay, P. S. and Forster, M. R., (eds.), Philosophy of Statistics, volume 7 of Handbook of Philosophy of Science, pages 441471. Elsevier, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. Open Court, Peru, IL, 3rd edition.Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. (1957). Information theory and statistical mechanics. Physical Review, 106(4):620630.Google Scholar
Jaynes, E. T. (2003). Probability Theory: The Logic of Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (2004). Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. (1983a). Bayesianism with a human face. In Earman, J., (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories, volume X, pages 133156. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. (1983b). The Logic of Decision. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2nd edition.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, H. (1939). Theory of Probability. Clarendon Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. (1998). A nonpragmatic vindication of Probabilism. Philosophy of Science, 65(4):575603.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. (2009). Accuracy and Coherence: Prospects for an Alethic Epistemology of Partial Belief. In Huber, F. and Schmidt-Petri, C., (eds.), Degrees of Belief, vol. 342 of Synthese Library, pages 263297. Springer, New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. M. (2010). A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1):281323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, G., Adatte, T., Pardo, A. et al. (2010). Cretaceous extinctions: evidence overlooked. Science, 328(5981):974975.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. T. (2011). Simplicity, truth, and probability. In Bandyopadhyay, P. S. and Forster, M. R., (eds.), Philosophy of Statistics, vol. 7 of Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, pages 9831024. North-Holland, Amsterdam.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, K. T., Schulte, O., and Juhl, C. (1997). Learning theory and the philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 64(2):245267.Google Scholar
Keynes, J. M. (1921). A Treatise on Probability. Macmillan, London.Google Scholar
Kimhi, I. (2018). Thinking and Being. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933). Foundations of the Theory of Probability. Chelsea Publishing Company, New York.Google Scholar
Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., and Marchionni, C. (2010). Economic modelling as robustness analysis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(3):541567.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (1961). Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief. Wesleyan University Press, Middletown, CT.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (1976). Chance. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5(3):355393.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (1977). Randomness and the right reference class. The Journal of Philosophy, 74(9):501521.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (1980). Conditionalization. The Journal of Philosophy, 77(2):98114.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (1983). Levi, Petersen, and direct inference. Philosophy of Science, 50(4):630634.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. (2003). Don’t take unnecessary chances! In Kyburg, H. E. and Thalos, M., (eds.), Probability Is the Very Guide of Life: The Philosophical Uses of Chance, pages 277294. Open Court, La Salle, IL.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. E. and Teng, C. M. (2001). Uncertain Inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Laplace, P.-S. (1814). A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities. Chapman & Hall, Limited, London.Google Scholar
Leitgeb, H. (2013). Reducing belief simpliciter to degrees of belief. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 164(12):13381389.Google Scholar
Leitgeb, H. and Pettigrew, R. (2010a). An objective justification of Bayesianism I: measuring inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2):201235.Google Scholar
Leitgeb, H. and Pettigrew, R. (2010b). An objective justification of Bayesianism II: the consequences of minimizing inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2):236272.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1977). Direct inference. The Journal of Philosophy, 74(1):529.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1978). Confirmational conditionalization. The Journal of Philosophy, 75(12):730737.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1980). The Enterprise of Knowledge: An Essay on Knowledge, Credal Probability, and Chance. Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1981). Direct inference and confirmational conditionalization. Philosophy of Science, 48(4):532552.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1987). The demons of decision. The Monist, 70(2):193211.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (2004). The logic of consistency and the logic of truth. Dialectica, 58(4, Special issue: Ramsey):461482.Google Scholar
Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54(4):421431.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review, 85(3):297315.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Jeffrey, R. C., (ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, pages 263293. University of California Press, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Lindberg, D. C. (2007). The Beginnings of Western Science: The European Scientific Tradition in Philosophical, Religious, and Institutional Context, Prehistory to A.D. 1450. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2nd edition.Google Scholar
Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the Best Explanation. Routledge, New York, 2nd edition.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. A. (2009). Varieties of support and confirmation of climate models. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 83:213232.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. A. (2010). Confirmation and robustness of climate models. Philosophy of Science, 77(5):971984.Google Scholar
Maher, P. (1993). Betting on Theories. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (1996). Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
McGrew, L. (2010). Probability kinematics and probability dynamics. Journal of Philosophical Research, 35:89105.Google Scholar
McGrew, L. (2014). Jeffrey conditioning, rigidity, and the defeasible red jelly bean. Philosophical Studies, 168:569582.Google Scholar
McGrew, L. (2016). Evidential diversity and the negation of H: a probabilistic account of the value of varied evidence. Ergo, 3(10):263292.Google Scholar
McGrew, T. (2003). Confirmation, heuristics, and explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54(4):553567.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. (1992). The Inference That Makes Science. Marquette University Press, Milwaukee, WI.Google Scholar
of Ockham, W. (1986). Tractatus de Corpore Christi, volume X of Opera Theologica. Franciscan Institute Publishers, St. Bonaventure, NY.Google Scholar
Parker, W. S. (2011). When climate models agree: the significance of robust model predictions. Philosophy of Science, 78(4):579600.Google Scholar
Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference. Morgan Kaufman, San Francisco.Google Scholar
Pedersen, A. P. and Wheeler, G. (2014). Demystifying dilation. Erkenntnis, 79(6):13051342.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1878). Deduction, induction, and hypothesis. Popular Science Monthly, 13(Aug.):470482.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1883). A theory of probable inference. In Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins University, pages 126181. Little, Brown, and Company, Boston, MA.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1893). Reply to the necessitarians: rejoinder to Dr Carus. The Monist, 3(4):526570.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1931–5). The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. I-VI. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1958). The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. VII-VIII. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Perrin, J. (1913). Les Atomes. Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, CT. Translated by D. Ll. Hammick.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2019). Epistemic utility arguments for Probabilism. In Zalta, E. N., editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, winter 2019 edition.Google Scholar
Pettigrew, R. and Titelbaum, M. G. (2014). Deference done right. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(35):119.Google Scholar
Plutynski, A. (2006). Strategies of model building in population genetics. Philosophy of Science, 73(5):755764.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. L. (1987). Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science, 11(4):481518.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. L. (1990). Nomic Probability and the Foundations of Induction. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson, London.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (1979). The logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1):219241.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2002). Inconsistency and the empirical sciences. In Meheus, J. (ed.), Inconsistency in Science, pages 119128. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2006). Doubt Truth to Be a Liar. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and Probability. In Mellor, D. H. (ed.), Philosophical Papers, pages 5294. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Edited collection published in 1990.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1949). The Theory of Probability. University of California Press, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Renne, P. R., Sprain, C. J., Richards, M. A. et al. (2015). State shift in Deccan volcanism at the Cretaceous-Paleogene boundary, possibly induced by impact. Science, 350(6256):7678.Google Scholar
Rosenkrantz, R. D. (1981). Foundations and Applications of Inductive Probability. Ridgeview Press, Atascadero, CA.Google Scholar
Royall, R. (1997). Statistical Evidence: A Likelihood Paradigm. Chapman & Hall, Boca Raton, FL.Google Scholar
Russell, J. B. (1991). Inventing the Flat Earth: Columbus and Modern Historians. Praeger, Westport, CT.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York. Page references are to the 1972 Dover edition.Google Scholar
Schulte et al., P. (2010). The Chicxulub asteroid impact and mass extinction at the Cretaceous-Paleogene boundary. Science, 327(5970):12141218.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2011a). Comparing probabilistic measures of explanatory power. Philosophy of Science, 78(5):813829.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2011b). Studies in the Logic of Explanatory Power. PhD thesis, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2015). Robustness, diversity of evidence, and probabilistic independence. In Mäki, U., Votsis, I., Ruphy, S., and Schurz, G. (ed.) Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Science: EPSA13 Helsinki, pages 305316. Springer, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2016). Competing explanations and explaining-away arguments. Theology and Science, 14(3):256267.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2017). Inference to the Best Explanation, cleaned up and made respectable. In McCain, K. and Poston, T. (eds.), Best Explanations: New Essays on Inference to the Best Explanation, pages 3961. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. (2018). Robustness analysis as explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(1):275300.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. and Glass, D. H. (2017). Hypothesis competition beyond mutual exclusivity. Philosophy of Science, 84(5):810824.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. and Sprenger, J. (2011). The logic of explanatory power. Philosophy of Science, 78(1):105127.Google Scholar
Schupbach, J. N. and Sprenger, J. (2014). Explanatory power and explanatory justice. Unpublished. Available online at http://jonahschupbach.com/documents/EPandEJ.pdf.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. (1979). Why I am not an objective Bayesian: some reflections prompted by Rosenkrantz. Theory and Decision, 11:413440.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. (1986). Entropy and uncertainty. Philosophy of Science, 53(4):467491.Google Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. and Wasserman, L. (1993). Dilation for sets of probabilities. The Annals of Statistics, 21(3):11391154.Google Scholar
Shannon, C. E. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27(July):379423, 623–656.Google Scholar
Shimony, A. (1985). The status of the principle of maximum entropy. Synthese, 63(1):3553.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1985). Maximum entropy inference as a special case of condition-alization. Synthese, 63(1):5574.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2009). Parsimony arguments in science and philosophy - a test case for naturalism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 83(2):117155.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2015). Ockham’s Razors: A User’s Manual. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2019). The Design Argument. Elements in the Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Sprenger, J. and Hartmann, S. (2019). Bayesian Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Stegenga, J. (2009). Robustness, discordance, and relevance. Philosophy of Science, 76(5):650661.Google Scholar
Stegenga, J. and Menon, T. (2017). Robustness and independent evidence. Philosophy of Science, 84(3):414435.Google Scholar
Stolarz-Fantino, S., Fantino, E., Zizzo, D. J., and Wen, J. (2003). The conjunction effect: new evidence for robustness. The American Journal of Psychology, 116(1):1534.Google Scholar
Tentori, K., Crupi, V, Bonini, N., and Osherson, D. (2007). Comparison of confirmation measures. Cognition, 103(1):107119.Google Scholar
Thorn, P. D. (2012). Two problems of direct inference. Erkenntnis, 76(3):299318.Google Scholar
Titelbaum, M. G. (2013). Quitting Certainties: A Bayesian Framework Modeling Degrees of Belief. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. (1984). Belief and the will. The Journal of Philosophy, 81(5):235256.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
Vineberg, S. (2016). Dutch book arguments. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, spring 2016 edition.Google Scholar
Weisberg, M. and Reisman, K. (2008). The robust Volterra principle. Philosophy of Science, 75(1):106131.Google Scholar
Wheeler, G. and Williamson, J. (2011). Evidential probability and objective Bayesian epistemology. In Bandyopadhyay, P. S. and Forster, M. R. (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, vol. 7: Philosophy of Statistics, pages 307331. Elsevier Science & Technology.Google Scholar
Williamson, J. (2007). Motivating Objective Bayesianism: From Empirical Constraints to Objective Probabilities. In Harper, W. and Wheeler, G. (eds.), Probability and Inference: Essays in Honour of Henry E. Kyburg Jr., pages 151179. College Publications, London.Google Scholar
Williamson, J. (2010). In Defence of Objective Bayesianism. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Williamson, J. (2011). Objective Bayesianism, Bayesian conditionalisation, and voluntarism. Synthese, 178(1):6785.Google Scholar
Williamson, J. (2017). Lectures on Inductive Logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1981). Robustness, reliability, and overdetermination. In Brewer, M. B. and Collins, B. E. (eds.), Scientific Inquiry and the Social Sciences, pages 125163. Jossey-Bass. Page references are to the version reprinted in (Wimsatt, 2007).Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24(sup1):207274. Page references are to the version reprinted in (Wimsatt, 2007).Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (2011). Robust re-engineering: a philosophical account? Biology & Philosophy, 26(2):295303.Google Scholar
Winsberg, E. (2018). Philosophy and Climate Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Routledge, Abingdon, 1974 edition. Translated by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuiness.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (2006). Some varieties of robustness. Journal of Economic Methodology, 13(2):219240.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Bayesianism and Scientific Reasoning
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Bayesianism and Scientific Reasoning
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Bayesianism and Scientific Reasoning
Available formats
×