Skip to main content
Log in

If materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

If you’re a materialist, you probably think that rabbits are conscious. And you ought to think that. After all, rabbits are a lot like us, biologically and neurophysiologically. If you’re a materialist, you probably also think that conscious experience would be present in a wide range of naturally-evolved alien beings behaviorally very similar to us even if they are physiologically very different. And you ought to think that. After all, to deny it seems insupportable Earthly chauvinism. But a materialist who accepts consciousness in weirdly formed aliens ought also to accept consciousness in spatially distributed group entities. If she then also accepts rabbit consciousness, she ought to accept the possibility of consciousness even in rather dumb group entities. Finally, the United States would seem to be a rather dumb group entity of the relevant sort. If we set aside our morphological prejudices against spatially distributed group entities, we can see that the United States has all the types of properties that materialists tend to regard as characteristic of conscious beings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For purposes of this essay, I’m going to assume that we know, at least roughly, what “material stuff” is. I recognize that this assumption might be problematic. Discussions include Montero (1999), Chomsky (2009), Stoljar (2010).

  2. The empirical literature on folk opinion about group consciousness is more equivocal than I would have thought, however. See Knobe and Prinz (2008), Sytsma and Machery (2010), Arico (2010), Huebner et al. (2010), Phelan et al. (2013).

    Few scholars have clearly endorsed the possibility of literal group consciousness. On group minds without literal consciousness see Bosanquet (1899/1923), McDougall (1920), Wilson (2004); and the recent literature on collective intentionality (e.g., Gilbert 1989; Clark 1994; Bratman 1999; Rupert 2005; Tuomela 2007; Searle 2010; List and Pettit 2011; Huebner 2014).

    For more radical views of group minds see Espinas (1877/1924), Schäffle (1896); maybe Wundt (1897/1897); maybe Strawson (1959) (none of whom were materialists). Perhaps the best developed group consciousness view—with some affinities to the present view, though again not materialist—is that of Teilhard de Chardin (1955/1965). See also Lewis and Viharo’s “Google Consciousness”, TEDxCardiff (June 9, 2011); Vernor Vinge’s science fiction portrayal of group minds in Vinge (1992, 2011); Averroës (Ibn Rushd) on the active intellect, (12th c./2009), Edelman (2008, p. 432), Koch (2012, pp. 131–134).

  3. I develop this idea farther in Schwitzgebel in draft. Some others who doubt common sense as a guide to metaphysics are Churchland (1981), Stich (1983), Gopnik and Schwitzgebel (1998), Kornblith (1998), Dennett (2005), Ladyman and Ross (2007), Mandik and Weisberg (2008). Hume (1740/1978) and Kant (1781/1787/1998) are also interesting on this issue, of course.

  4. On the last, see Bettencourt et al. (1992).

  5. See, for example, the essays collected in Wittenbrink and Schwarz, eds., (2007), Petty et al. (2009). Philosophical discussions include Gendler (2008a, b), Haslanger (2008), Schwitzgebel (2010), Saul (2013).

  6. Especially if the entity’s parts move on diverse trajectories. See, for example, Campbell (1958), Spelke et al. (1992), Scholl (2007), Carey (2009). See Barnett (2008) and Madden (2012) for philosophical arguments that we do not intuitively attribute consciousness to scattered objects.

  7. See discussions in Korman (2011), Elder (2011).

  8. These last thoughts are inspired by Parfit (1984), Churchland (1981), Egan (1992).

  9. See, for example, Greene (2011).

  10. See also Barnett (2008, 2010), Madden (2012); and for comparison Godfrey-Smith (2013) on the “exclusion principle” regarding biological organisms. Barnett, like Putnam, seems to rely simply on an intuitive sense of absurdity (2010, p. 162). In an earlier work, Tononi (2010, note 9) discusses an anti-nesting principle without endorsing it. There he states that such a principle is “in line with the intuitions that each of us has a single, sharply demarcated consciousness”. In his more recent article, Tononi does not repeat his appeal to that intuition.

  11. For a review of “type materialism” see McLaughlin (2007). For more detail how some of the options described in this paragraph might play out, see Lewis (1980), Bechtel and Mundale (1999), Polger (2004), Hill (2009). Block (2002/2007) illustrates the skeptical consequences of embracing type identity without committing to some possibility of broadly this sort.

  12. See Stock (1993) for a similar perspective presented in lively detail. On Godfrey-Smith’s (2013) three-dimensional taxonomy of “Darwinian individuals”, the United States would appear to be an intermediate case, comparable to a sponge.

  13. For a hypothetical case that might help buttress the ideas of this section, see my blog post “Group Minds on Ringworld” (Schwitzgebel 2012a).

  14. E.g., Hurley (1998), Noë (2004), Wilson (2004), Rockwell (2005).

  15. E.g., Putnam (1975), Burge (1979), Millikan (1984), Davidson (1987), Dretske (1988, 1995), Wilson (2004).

  16. See also Moravec (1997), Kurzweil (2005), Hilbert and López (2011). It is probably too simplistic to conceptualize the connectivity of the brain as though all that mattered were neuron-to-neuron connections; but those who favor complex models of the internal interactivity of the brain should, I think, for similar reasons, be drawn to appreciate complex models of the interactivity of citizens and residents of the United States.

  17. See e.g., Davidson (1987), Dretske (1995), Millikan (2010).

  18. In this respect, the case of the United States is importantly different from more artificial cases discussed in Lycan (1981) and Brooks (1986).

  19. Notable exceptions include Lycan (1981), Brooks (1986), Wilson (2004) and Bryce Huebner (2014). Huebner, Brooks, and Lycan endorse hypothetical group consciousness under certain counterfactual conditions (e.g., Brooks’s “Brain City” in which people mimic the full neuronal structure of a brain), while refraining from stating that their arguments concerning literal group consciousness extend to any group entities that actually exist. Wilson I am inclined to read as rejecting group consciousness on the grounds that it has been advocated only sparsely and confusedly, with no advocate meeting a reasonable burden of proof. Edelman (2008) and Koch (2012) make passing but favorable remarks about group consciousness, at least hypothetically. Tononi and Putnam I discuss in Sect. 2.

  20. For a review of higher-order theories, see Carruthers (2001/2011).

  21. The theories I chose were Dretske’s, Dennett’s, Humphrey’s, and Tononi’s pre-2012 view. You can see some of my preliminary efforts in blog posts Schwitzgebel (2012b, c, d, e, f) (compare also Koch’s sympathetic 2012 treatment of Tononi). On the most natural interpretations of these four test-case views, I thought that readers sympathetic with any of these authors’ general approaches ought to accept that the United States is conscious. And I confess I still do think that, despite protests from Dretske, Dennett, Humphrey, and Tononi themselves in personal communication. See the comments section of Schwitzgebel (2012d) for Humphrey’s reaction, the remainder of the present section for Dretske and Dennett, and Sect. 2 for Tononi.

  22. In his 1995 book, Dretske says that a representational is natural if it is not “derived from the intentions and purposes of its designers, builders, and users” (p. 7) rather than the more general criterion, above, of independency from “others”. In light of our correspondence on group consciousness, he says that he has modified this aspect of his view.

  23. Although Chalmers is not a materialist, for the issues at hand his view invites similar treatment. See especially his (1996) and (forthcoming).

  24. P.M.Churchland (1984/1988), P.S.Churchland (2002), Stich (2009). Contrast skepticism about loaded versions of “consciousness” or “qualia” in Churchland (1983), Dennett (1991), Frankish (2012).

  25. Churchland characterizes as a living being “any semiclosed system that exploits the order it already possesses, and the energy flux through it, in such a way as to maintain and/or increase its internal order” (1984/1988, p. 173). By this definition, Churchland suggests, beehives, cities, and the entire biosphere all qualify as living beings (ibid.). Consciousness and intelligence, Churchland further suggests, are simply sophistications of this basic pattern—cases in which the semiclosed system exploits energy to increase the information it contains, including information about its own internal states and processes (1984/1988, pp. 173 and 178).

  26. On the homunculi, see e.g., Fodor (1968). Leibniz imagines entering into an enlarged brain as into a mill in his (1714/1989).

  27. Hutchins (1995) vividly portrays distributed cognition in a military vessel. I don’t know whether he would extend his conclusions to phenomenal consciousness, however.

References

  • Allen, C. (1995/2010). Animal consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 edition).

  • Arico, A. (2010). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 371–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Averroës (Ibn Rushd). (12th c./2009). Long commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle (trans: Taylor, R.C.). New Haven: Yale.

  • Baars, B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balduzzi, D., & Tononi, G. (2009). Qualia: The geometry of integrated information. PLoS Computational Biology, 5, 8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, D. (2008). The simplicity intuition and its hidden influence on philosophy of mind. Noûs, 42, 308–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, D. (2010). You are simple. In R. C. Koons & G. Bealer (Eds.), The waning of materialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Mundale, J. (1999).  Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states.  Philosophy of Science, 66, 175–207.

  • Bettencourt, B. A., Brewer, M. B., Croak, M. R., & Miller, N. (1992). Cooperation and the reduction of intergroup bias: The role of reward structure and social orientation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 28, 301–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1978/2007). Troubles with functionalism. In Block, N. (Ed.), Consciousness, function, and representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

  • Block, N. (2002/2007). The harder problem of consciousness. In Block, N. (Ed.), Consciousness, function, and representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

  • Bosanquet, B. (1899/1923). The philosophical theory of the state (4th ed.). London: Macmillan.

  • Bratman, M. (1999). Faces of intention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, D. H. M. (1986). Group minds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 456–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1958). Common fate, similarity, and other indices of the status of aggregates of persons as social entities. Behavioral Science, 3, 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Canetti, E. (1960/1962). Crowds and power (trans: Stewart, C.). New York: Viking.

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2001/2011). Higher-order theories of consciousness. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 edition).

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (forthcoming). The combination problem for panpsychism. http://consc.net/papers/combination.pdf.

  • Chomsky, N. (2009). The mysteries of nature: How deeply hidden? Journal of Philosophy, 106, 167–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1983). Consciousness: The transmutation of a concept. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 80–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1984/1988). Matter and consciousness (rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT.

  • Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1994). Beliefs and desires incorporated. Journal of Philosophy, 91, 404–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2009). Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head. Mind, 118, 963–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuda, T. (1985). Against neural chauvinism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 111–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 61, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and workspace framework. Cognition, 79, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2005). Sweet dreams. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, S. (2008). Computing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, G. (1992). Closer. In Eidelon (Vol. 8). http://www.eidolon.net/old_site/issue_09/09_closr.htm.

  • Elder, C. (2011). Familiar objects and their shadows. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Espinas, A. (1877/1924). Des sociétés animales (3rd ed.). Paris: Félix Alcan.

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968). The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 627–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankish, K. (2012). Quining diet qualia. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 667–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008a). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 634–663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008b). Alief in action, and reaction. Mind and Language, 23, 552–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. Darwinian individuals. In Bouchard, F. & Huneman, P. (Eds.). (2013). From groups to individuals. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

  • Gopnik, A., & Schwitzgebel, E. (1998). Whose concepts are they, anyway? The role of philosophical intuition in empirical psychology. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. (2011). The hidden reality. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2008). Changing the ideology and culture of philosophy: Not by reason (alone). Hypatia, 23, 210–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, M., & López, P. (2011). The world’s technological capacity to store, communicate, and compute information. Science, 332, 60–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. S. (2009). Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. (2014). Macrocognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Huebner, B., Bruno, M., & Sarkissian, H. (2010). What does the nation of China think about phenomenal states? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 225–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740/1978). In Selby-Bigge, L.A. & Nidditch, P.H. (Eds.), A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/1787/1998). Critique of pure reason (ed. and trans: Guyer, P. & Wood, A. W.). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2012). Consciousness: Confessions of a romantic reductionist. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korman, D. (2011). Ordinary objects. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 edition).

  • Kornblith, H. (1998). The role of intuition in philosophical inquiry: An account with no unnatural ingredients. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil, R. (2005). The singularity is near. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bon, G. (1895/1995). In Nye, R. A. (Ed.), The crowd. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1714/1989). The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology. In Philosophical Essays (ed. and trans: Ariew, R. & Garber, D.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Lewis, D. K. (1980). Mad pain and Martian pain. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in philosophy of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1981). Form, function, and feel. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 24–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madden, R. (2012). The naive topology of the conscious subject. Noûs..

  • Mandik, P., & Weisberg, J. (2008). Type Q materialism. In C. B. Wrenn (Ed.), Naturalism, reference, and ontology. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Szathmáry, E. (1995). The major transitions in evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDougall, W. (1920). The group mind. New York: Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (2007). Type materialism for phenomenal consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (2010). On knowing the meaning: With a coda on Swampman. Mind, 119, 43–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (1999). The body problem. Noûs, 33, 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravec, H. (1997). When will computer hardware match the human brain? http://www.transhumanist.com/volume1/moravec.htm. Accessed 1 June 2012.

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., Fazio, R. H., & Briñol, Pablo (Eds.). (2009). Attitudes: Insights from the new implicit measures. New York: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelan, M., Arico, A., & Nichols, S. (2013). Thinking things and feeling things: On an alleged discontinuity in folk metaphysics of mind. Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences, 12, 703–725.

  • Polger, T. W. (2004). Natural minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1965). Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion. Liverpool: University of Pittsburgh Press/C. Tinling.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language and reality. London: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rockwell, T. (2005). Neither brain nor ghost. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2005). Minding one’s own cognitive system: When is a group of minds a single cognitive unit? Episteme, 1, 177–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2013). Implicit bias, stereotype threat and women in philosophy. In K. Hutichson & F. Jenkins (Eds.), Women in philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schäffle, A. E. F. (1896). Bau und Leben des socialen Körpers (2nd ed.). Tübingen: Laupp’schen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. (2007). Object persistence in philosophy and psychology. Mind and Language, 22, 563–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012a). Group minds on Ringworld. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com). October 24 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012b). Why Dennett should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com). February 9 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012c). Why Dretske should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com). February 17 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012d). Why Humphrey should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com). March 8 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012e). Why Tononi should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com). March 23 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012f). Why Tononi should allow that conscious entities can have conscious parts. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com) June 6 2012.

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (forthcoming). The crazyist metaphysics of mind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. http://faculty.ucr.edu/~eschwitz.

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1984). Minds, brains, and science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2010). Making the social world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J., & Jacobson, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge. Psychological Review, 99, 605–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (2009). Five answers. In Grim, S. (Ed.), Mind and consciousness. Automatic Press.

  • Stock, G. (1993). Metaman. Toronto: Doubleday Canada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2010). Physicalism. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Consciousness and its place in nature. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. M., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151, 299–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarrow, S. G. (1994/2011). Power in movement (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Teilhard de Chardin, P. (1955/1965). The phenomenon of man (rev. English ed.) (trans: Wall, B.). New York: Harper & Row.

  • Tononi, G. (2004). An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neuroscience, 5, 42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2008). Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto. Biological Bulletin, 215, 216–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2010). Information integration: Its relevance to brain function and consciousness. Archives Italiennes de Biologie, 148, 299–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2012a). The integrated information theory of consciousness: An updated account. Archives Italiennes de Biologie, 150, 290–326.

  • Tononi, G. (2012b). Phi. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007). The philosophy of sociality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vinge, V. (1992). A fire upon the deep. New York: Tor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinge, V. (2011). Children of the sky. New York: Tor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1968). Reasoning about a rule. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 20, 273–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittenbrink, B., & Schwarz, N. (Eds.). (2007). Implicit measures of attitudes. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1897/1897). Outlines of psychology (trans: Judd, C. H.). Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful discussion of these issues in the course of writing, thanks to Rachel Achs, Santiago Arango, Scott Bakker, Zachary Barnett, Mark Biswas, Ned Block, Dave Chalmers, David Daedalus, Dan Dennett, Fred Dretske, Louie Favela, Kirk Gable, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Chris Hill, Linus Huang, Nick Humphrey, Enoch Lambert, Janet Levin, Bill Lycan, Pete Mandik, Tori McGeer, Luke Roelofs, Giulio Tononi, Till Vierkant, Vernor Vinge, and Rob Wilson; to audiences at University of Cincinnati, Princeton University, Tufts University, University of Basque Country, Consciousness Online, University of Edinburgh, and Bob Richardson’s seminar on extended cognition; and to the many readers who posted comments on relevant posts on my blog, The Splintered Mind.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Schwitzgebel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schwitzgebel, E. If materialism is true, the United States is probably conscious. Philos Stud 172, 1697–1721 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0387-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0387-8

Keywords

Navigation