Skip to main content
Log in

Phenomenal evidence and factive evidence

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Perceptions guide our actions and provide us with evidence of the world around us. Illusions and hallucinations can mislead us: they may prompt as to act in ways that do not mesh with the world around us and they may lead us to form false beliefs about that world. The capacity view provides an account of evidence that does justice to these two facts. It shows in virtue of what illusions and hallucinations mislead us and prompt us to act. Moreover, it shows in virtue of what we are in a better epistemic position when we perceive than when we hallucination. In this paper, I develop the capacity view, that is, the view that perceptual experience has epistemic force in virtue of the epistemic and metaphysical primacy of the perceptual capacities employed in perception. By grounding the epistemic force of experience in facts about the metaphysical structure of experience, the capacity view is not only an externalist view, but moreover a naturalistic view of the epistemology of perceptual experience. So it is an externalist and naturalistic alternative to reliabilism. I discuss the repercussions of this view for the justification of beliefs and the epistemic transparency of mental states, as well as, familiar problem cases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Naturally, there are big differences between these different views but what they all have in common is that they treat conscious mental states as explanatory basic.

  2. One could make the case that insofar as on some of the views categorized as capacity views it is essential that the capacities in play are reliable, those views should better be classified as reliabilist views.

  3. Williamson (2000) famously holds that knowledge cannot be analyzed. But one can accept the insights of his account of justification as derivative from knowledge while rejecting his view that knowledge cannot be analyzed.

  4. Williamson’s notion of method can be understood as a kind of capacity.

  5. See my (2013a). For critical discussion, see (Byrne 2014).

  6. For the contrast between analyzing sensory character in terms of awareness relations to peculiar entities, such as strange particulars or abstract entities, on the one hand, and understanding sensory character in terms of a mental activity, such as employing perceptual capacities, see my (2011a).

  7. For a detailed development of such a color realist view, see Byrne and Hilbert (2003).

  8. According to Williamson, we have only evidence provided by an appearance proposition in the bad case. For discussion of the problems with this, see my (2013a).

  9. For a discussion of the relationship between evidence and justification, see McGrath and Fantl (2002, 2009).

  10. An alternative would be to think of the quality of the epistemic position as an aspect of knowledge distinct from justification. On this way of thinking, one would say that the perceiver and the hallucinator are equally justified, but the perceiver is still in a better epistemic position in virtue of having knowledge, where this difference in epistemic position makes the difference between knowledge and ignorance.

  11. An interesting question is what the connection is between the strength of the evidence we have for a proposition and our confidence in that proposition. For a discussion of the relationship between having evidence for p and having confidence in p, see Neta (2003, 2008) and Silins (2005).

  12. I am taking for granted here that being in a mental state is closed under constitution: what is constituted by the mental is itself mental. For an argument for the thesis that the evidence one has is a matter of what mental state one is in, see Williamson (2000).

  13. See Williamson (2000: 11) for both principles. For a critical discussion of both principles, see Smithies (2012).

  14. For a recent discussion of related issues, see Greco (2014).

  15. Some internalists have understood the accessibility of evidence as an essential part of the very nature of evidence. Indeed, it has been argued that denying the accessibility of evidence amounts to changing the subject (Cohen 1984: 284). It will lead too far astray to address this issue here.

  16. For a more general discussion of the limits and unreliability of introspection, see Pereboom (1994), Goldberg (2000), Bar-On (2004), Schwitzgebel (2008), Fumerton (2009) and Gertler (2011).

  17. To keep issues of personal identity out of the picture, I will focus on inanimate objects. Putting aside issues specific to personal identity, everything said about inanimate objects carries over to persons.

  18. Thanks to Dan Greco for helpful discussions on these issues.

  19. For a defense of such a view, see my (2011b) and (2014b). See also Dretske (1995), Tye (1995), Byrne (2001), Chalmers (2006) and Pautz (2010).

  20. For a discussion of such an approach, see McGrath (2013).

  21. For a defense of such a weak representationalist view, see Schellenberg (2010, 2013b).

  22. This case differs from BonJour’s (1980) Norman case, since there is no assumption that Vernon comes at her hallucination by way of a reliable process. By contrast clairvoyant Norman comes to his beliefs by way of a reliable process that however is not based on any evidence or reasons.

  23. Given that one has factive evidence, one already has (at least some) safety. One has safety since singular content entails its truth. So arguably adding a safety requirement on knowledge would not be an option for the capacity view. One might argue however that there is a safety condition on the content type. If that is right, then the capacity view is compatible with a safety requirement on knowledge. We can remain neutral on this issue here.

References

  • Bar-On, D. (2004). Externalism and self-knowledge: Content, use, and expression. Nous, 38, 430–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 503–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism defended. The Philosophical Review, 110, 199–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2014). Perception and evidence. Philosophical Studies.

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Perception and the fall from eden. In Gendler, & Hawthorne (Eds.).

  • Chisholm, R. (1942). The problem of the speckled hen. Mind, 51, 363–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth. Philosophical Studies, 46, 279–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 15–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2009). Luminous enough for a cognitive home. Philosophical Studies, 142, 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. (2011). Self-knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2000). Externalism and authoritative knowledge of content: a new incompatibilist strategy. Philosophical Studies, 100, 51–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Knowledge and justification. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1993). Epistemic folkways and scientific epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 3, 271–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. (2011). Epistemic entitlement. New Jersey: Nous.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2001). Virtues and rules in epistemology. In Fairweather, & Zagzebski (Eds.).

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, D. (2014). Could KK be OK?. Journal of Philosophy, 111, 169–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2007). Compassionate phenomenal conservatism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 30–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives & afterthoughts. In J. Almog, J. Perry & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lehrer, K., & Cohen, S. (1983). Justification, truth, and coherence. Synthese, 55, 191–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (2009). Perception and basic beliefs: Zombies, modules and the problem of the external world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1982). Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge. Proceedings of the British Academy, 68, 455–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2013). Dogmatism, underminers and skepticism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 533–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M., & Fantl, J. (2002). Evidence, pragmatics, and justification. The Philosophical Review, 111, 67–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M., & Fantl, J. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2008). Perceptual-recognitional abilities and perceptual knowledge. In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action, knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2013). Knowledge as a mental state. Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 4, 273–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R. (2003). Contextualism and the problem of the external world. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R. (2008). What evidence do you have? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 89–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2010). Why ezplain visual experience in terms of content? In B. Nanay (Ed.), Perceiving the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (1994). Bats, brain scientists, and the limitations of introspection. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 315–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1974). Experience and justification. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34, 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2010). The particularity and phenomenology of perceptual experience. Philosophical Studies, 149, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2011a). Ontological minimalism about phenomenology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2011b). Perceptual Content defended. Noûs, 45, 714–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2013a). Experience and evidence. Mind, 122, 699–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2013b). Externalism and the gappy content of hallucination. In F. E. Macpherson & D. Platchias (Eds.), Hallucination (pp. 291–311). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2014a). The epistemic force of perceptual experience. With a response by Alex Byrne, Philosophical Studies.

  • Schellenberg, S. (2014b). The relational and representational character of perceptual experience. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content?. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of introspection. Philosophical Review, 117, 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silins, N. (2005). Deception and evidence. Philosophical Perspective, 19, 375–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2012). Mentalism and epistemic transparency. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 723–741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2006). Internal foundations or external virtues? Philosophical Studies, 131, 733–769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to James Genone and Dan Greco for comments on a draft of this paper as well as audiences at the Evidence workshop in Philadelphia and The Epistemology of Perception workshop at SMU.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Susanna Schellenberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schellenberg, S. Phenomenal evidence and factive evidence. Philos Stud 173, 875–896 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0528-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0528-8

Keywords

Navigation