Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-12T10:59:54.028Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Statistical Evidence and the Problem of Specification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 November 2021

Frederick Schauer*
Affiliation:
University of Virginia, Charlottesville, VA, USA

Abstract

Philosophical debates over statistical evidence have long been framed and dominated by L. Jonathan Cohen's Paradox of the Gatecrasher and a related hypothetical example commonly called Prison Yard. These examples, however, raise an issue not discussed in the large and growing literature on statistical evidence – the question of what statistical evidence is supposed to be evidence of. In actual practice, the legal system does not start with a defendant and then attempt to determine if that defendant has committed some unspecified or under-specified act, as these examples appear to suppose. Rather, both criminal and civil litigation start with a sufficiently specified act and then attempt to determine if the defendant has committed it. And when we start with a more fully specified act, the statistics look very different, and these prominent examples no longer present the paradox they are claimed to support. Examining the issue of specification, however, does more than simply undercut the prominent examples in a long and extensive literature. The examination also raises normative issues challenging the legal system's traditional reluctance to base liability on the conjunction of probabilities.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Backes, M. (2020). ‘Epistemology and the Law: Why There is no Epistemic Mileage in Legal Cases.’ Philosophical Studies 177, 2759–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blome-Tillman, M. (2020). ‘Statistical Evidence, Normalcy, and the Gatecrasher Paradox.’ Mind 129, 563–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Capra, D. and Richter, L.L. (2018). ‘Character Assassination: Amending Federal Rule of Evidence 404(B) to Protect Criminal Defendants.’ Columbia Law Review 118, 769832.Google Scholar
Clermont, K.M. (2012). ‘Aggregation of Probabilities and Illogic.’ Georgia Law Review 47, 165–80.Google Scholar
Cohen, L.J. (1977). The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1969). ‘The Individuation of Events.’ In Rescher, N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, pp. 216–34. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Bello, M. (2019). ‘Trial by Statistics: Is a High Probability of Guilt Enough to Convict?’ Mind 128, 1045–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. and Fisher, T. (2015). ‘Sense and Sensitivity: Epistemic and Instrumental Approaches to Statistical Evidence.’ Stanford Law Review 67, 557611.Google Scholar
Enoch, D., Fisher, T. and Spectre, L. (2012). ‘Statistical Evidence, Sensitivity, and the Legal Value of Knowledge.’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 40, 197224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fennell, L.A. (2018). ‘Accidents and Aggregates.’ William & Mary Law Review 59, 2371–445.Google Scholar
Finkelstein, M.O. and Fairley, W.B. (1970). ‘A Bayesian Approach to Identification Evidence.’ Harvard Law Review 83, 489517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finkelstein, M.O. and Fairley, W.B. (1971). ‘The Continuing Debate over Mathematics in the Law of Evidence.’ Harvard Law Review 84, 1801–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardiner, G. (2017). ‘In Defence of Reasonable Doubt.’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 34, 221–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harel, A. and Porat, A. (2009). ‘Aggregating Probabilities Across Cases: Criminal Responsibility for Unspecified Offenses.’ Minnesota Law Review 94, 261310.Google Scholar
Littlejohn, C. (2017). ‘Truth, Knowledge, and the Standard of Proof in Criminal Law.’ Synthese. http:doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1608-4.Google Scholar
Margalit, A. (1980). ‘Comments.’ In Cohen, L.J. and Hesse, M. (eds), Applications of Inductive Logic, p. 195. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moss, S. (2018). Probabilistic Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nesson, C. (1979). ‘Reasonable Doubt and Permissive Inferences: The Value of Complexity.’ Harvard Law Review 92, 1187–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pundik, A. (2015). ‘Should Criminals be Convicted of Unspecified Offenses? On Efficiency, Condemnation, and Cognitive Psychology.’ Criminal Law and Philosophy 9, 207–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redmayne, M. (2008). ‘Exploring the Proof Paradoxes.’ Legal Theory 14, 281309.10.1017/S1352325208080117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, L.D. (2020). ‘Recent Work on the Proof Paradox.’ Philosophy Compass 15. doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12667.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, F. (2003). Profiles, Probabilities, and Stereotypes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. and Spellman, B.A. (2020). ‘Probabilistic Causation in the Law.’ Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 176, 417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaviro, D. (1989). ‘Statistical-probability Evidence and the Appearance of Justice.’ Harvard Law Review 103, 530–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sindell v. Abbott Laboratories (1980). 26 Cal. 3d 588, 607 P.2d 924.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (2018). ‘When does evidence suffice to convict?’ Mind 127, 1193–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith v. Rapid Transit Co. (1945). 317 Mass, 469, 58 N.E.2d 754.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J. (1977). Acts and Other Events. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, J.J. (1986). ‘Liability and Individualized Evidence.’ Law and Contemporary Problems 49, 199219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tribe, L. (1971). ‘Trial by Mathematics: Precision and Ritual in the Legal Process.’ Harvard Law Review 84, 1329–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar