Skip to main content
Log in

The neuroscientific study of free will: A diagnosis of the controversy

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Benjamin Libet’s work paved the way for the neuroscientific study of free will. Other scientists have praised this research as groundbreaking. In philosophy, the reception has been more negative, often even dismissive. First, I will propose a diagnosis of this striking discrepancy. I will suggest that the experiments seem irrelevant, from the perspective of philosophy, due to the way in which they operationalize free will. In particular, I will argue that this operational definition does not capture free will properly and that it is based on a false dichotomy between internal and external causes. However, I will also suggest that this problem could be overcome, as there are no obvious obstacles to an operationalization of free will that is in accord with the philosophical conception of free will.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Libet (2002), where he provides a long list of fellow scientists who have “not only accepted our findings and interpretations, but have even enthusiastically praised these achievements and their experimental ingenuity” (p. 292).

  2. One can get a good sense of the striking differences in the assessment of Libet’s findings (and related empirical evidence) from a discussion of the topic “Is free will an illusion?” in the Chronicle of Higher Education (2012, March 18), which includes contributions from scientists and philosophers.

  3. See, for instance, the contributions by philosophers to the peer commentaries to Libet (1985) and to Pockett et al. (2006), Baer et al. (2008), and Sinnott-Armstrong and Nadel (2011). The most detailed engagement with Libet’s challenge by a philosopher is Mele (2009).

  4. Although I have come across this view many times in conversation with other philosophers, it is difficult to find clear statements in print. The main reason for this is probably that the philosophers who publish academic work on this topic are the ones who take the empirical challenge to free will seriously, whereas the ones who think it is irrelevant do not bother to write about it. However, statements of the view that the evidence is simply irrelevant to free will (or “no threat at all”) are provided by three philosophers on the BBC Radio 4 program “In our time: philosophy” (2011, March 10).

  5. Arguably, what-decisions are more significant, because when-decisions are usually subordinate to what-decisions in the sense that we usually decide when to do something in order to decide how to implement a what-decision.

  6. Two recent studies have raised serious questions concerning the measurement and interpretation of the RP. The experiments in Miller et al. (2011) suggest that effects of the clock-monitoring could be partly responsible for the main finding in the Libet experiment. The experiments conducted by Schurger et al. (2012) suggest that the precise timing of the decision is partly determined by ongoing spontaneous fluctuations of neural activity and that the decision to act might occur much later in the RP process than Libet assumed. Further, experiments conducted by Schlegel et al. (forthcoming) raise serious doubts about Haggard and Eimer’s findings concerning the role of the LRP. Given this, it seems no longer credible to hold that the main findings of the Libet experiment are an established empirical fact (as it has often been claimed). However, further experiments are required to establish the truth on those issues, and the mentioned studies do not challenge the results of Soon et al. (2008).

  7. According to Libet, a conscious intention to initiate a movement “should precede or at least coincide with the onset of the specific cerebral processes that mediate the act” (1985, p. 529). One has to assume here that by “mediate the act” Libet meant “initiate the act”. Otherwise, the conclusion that the initiation of a spontaneous voluntary act begins unconsciously does not follow. Further, one must assume that the RP is such a “specific cerebral processes” that initiates the act. This assumption, I should mention, has attracted a lot of criticism. See Keller and Heckhausen (1990), Zhu (2003), Mele (2009), for instance.

  8. Another prominent empirical challenge concerning the role of consciousness in the initiation of action is due to Wegner (2002), who argued that the experience of conscious will is an illusion. On some occasions, Wegner appears to use the terms ‘conscious will’ and ‘free will’ interchangeably, but he does not draw any explicit conclusions about free will. I have addressed Wegner’s challenge elsewhere (Schlosser 2012a).

  9. See, however, Schlegel at al. (forthcoming).

  10. However, the findings are controversial due to the fact that the unconscious brain activations predict the conscious choices only with a relatively low accuracy of about 60 %. In other words, the decoded unconscious brain activations raise the probability of the subsequent conscious choices to just above the level of chance.

  11. See note 4.

  12. Note that this provides a necessary condition: the choice of an action is made with free will proper only if it is based on reasons. It is not meant to provide a sufficient condition; it is not meant to give a full definition; and it is not meant to give an explanation of what freedom is.

  13. See also Fischer and Ravizza’s (1998) influential account of reason-responsiveness. They argue that “reason-receptivity” is relative to subjective features of the agent, but that it cannot be reduced to “the agent’s point of view”. Rather, reason-receptivity must be “grounded in reality” (p. 73). Further, they claim that this view fits with “the widest possible selection of plausible views about reasons for action” (p. 68, note 11). Note that this view is compatible even with source libertarianism, according to which the agent must be the source or origin of his or her free choices (Kane 1996, for instance). All source libertarians acknowledge that the agent should be influenced by reasons. Given that genuine reason-responsiveness requires at least some sensitivity to external factors, even source libertarians can and should allow the influence of external factors.

  14. One might think that such an action was free only if the reason did not determine the action and only if the agent could have done otherwise. According to compatibilists, free choices may be causally determined. What matters, rather, is that the choice of the action is not coerced or manipulated. This condition is satisfied: the fact that one is persuaded by a factor is incompatible with being coerced or manipulated by that factor. In contrast, incompatibilists would insist that the reason must not determine the choice. This is also compatible with what I have claimed: we may assume that a factor that provides a reason exerts only a causal influence on the choice of the action. Is it required that the agent could have done otherwise? This issue has been very controversial (see, for instance, Dennett 1984; Van Inwagen 1989; Kane 1996). Fischer and Ravizza (1998) have argued that reason-responsiveness does not require the ability to do otherwise. Elsewhere, I have proposed that the ability to do otherwise can be analyzed in terms of reason-responsiveness (Schlosser 2012b). Be that as it may. The important point is that nothing hangs on this issue here, for everything that I have claimed here is compatible with both the affirmation and the denial of the view that the agent must be able do to otherwise.

  15. I assume here that the conscious events that proximately precede the movements are conscious intentions. I should note, however, that this assumption has also been questioned. For instance, Keller and Heckhausen (1990, p. 359) suggested that the conscious events in question were the “result of selective attention” to look for an urge to move, which was, in turn, induced by the artificial setup and the instructions of the experiment. They suggested, in other words, that the conscious events in question are neither intentions nor conscious events that precede ordinary actions.

  16. I assume here that causation may be non-deterministic, such that causes raise the probability of effects.

  17. See note 10.

References

  • Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baer, J., Kaufman, J. C., & Baumeister, R. F. (Eds.). (2008). Are We free? Psychology and Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BBC Radio 4. (2011, March 10). In our time: Philosophy. http://downloads.bbc.co.uk/podcasts/radio4/iotp/iotp_20110310-1023b.mp3. Accessed 15 Oct 2012.

  • Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intentions, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chronicle of Higher Education. (2012, March 18). Is free will an illusion? http://chronicle.com/article/Is-Free-Will-an-Illusion-/131159/. Accessed 15 Oct 2012.

  • Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian accounts of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2000). Practical reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danquah, A. N., Farrell, M. J., & O’Boyle, D. J. (2007). Biases in the subjective timing of perceptual events: Libet et al. (1983) revisited. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 616–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. Journal of Philosophy, 60, 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. In L. Foster & J. W. Swanson (Eds.), Experience and theory. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glimcher, P. W., Fehr, E., Camerer, C., & Poldrack, R. A. (Eds.). (2009). Neuroeconomics: Decision making and the brain. London: Elsevier Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, P. M., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Implementation intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of effects and processes. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 69–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gomes, G. (2002). Problems in the timing of conscious experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 191–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glynn, I. M. (1990). Consciousness and time. Nature, 348, 477–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2011). Does brain science change our view of free will? In R. Swinburne (Ed.), Free will and modern science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Eimer, M. (1999). On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research, 126, 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Libet, B. (2001). Conscious intention and brain activity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 47–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haynes, J. D. (2011). Beyond Libet: Long-term prediction of free choices from neuroimaging signals. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & L. Nadel (Eds.), Conscious will and responsibility (pp. 85–96). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hobart, R. E. (1934). Free will as involving determinism and inconceivable without it. Mind, 3, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joordens, S., van Duijn, M., & Spalek, T. M. (2002). When timing the mind one should also mind the timing: Bias in the measurement of voluntary actions. Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 231–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, I., & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding spontaneous motor acts: Voluntary vs. involuntary control. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 76, 351–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Science, 8, 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 47–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (2002). The timing of mental events: Libet’s experimental findings and their implications. Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 291–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W., & Pearl, D. K. (1983). Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential): The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain, 106, 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B. F. (2004). How the mind explains behavior: Folk explanations, meaning, and social interaction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B. F. (2011). Time to give up the dogmas of attribution: An alternative theory of behavior explanation. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 297–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2009). Effective intentions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J., Shepherdson, P., & Trevena, J. (2011). Effects of clock monitoring on electroencephalographic activity: Is unconscious movement initiation an artifact of the clock? Psychological Science, 22, 103–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1997). Reason and motivation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 71, 99–130.

  • Pockett, S., Banks, W. P., & Gallagher, S. (Eds.). (2006). Does consciousness cause behavior?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlegel, A., Alexander, P., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Roskies, A., Tse, P., & Wheatley, T. (forthcoming). Barking up the wrong free: Readiness potentials reflect processes independent of conscious will. Experimental Brain Research.

  • Schlosser, M. E. (2012a). Causally efficacious intentions and the sense of agency: In defense of real mental causation. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 32, 135–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, M. E. (2012b). Free will and the unconscious precursors of choice. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 365–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurger, A., Sitta, J. D., & Dehaene, S. (2012). An accumulator model for spontaneous neural activity prior to self-initiated movement. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109(42), E2904–E2913.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Nadel, L. (Eds.). (2011). Conscious will and responsibility: A tribute to Benjamin Libet. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H. J., & Haynes, J. D. (2008). Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 543–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1989). When is the will free? Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 399–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (2004). Free will demystified: A dispositional account. Philosophical Topics, 32, 427–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, T. L., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Does changing behavioral intentions engender behavior change? A meta-analysis of the experimental evidence. Psychological Bulletin, 132(2), 249–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom within reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, J. (2003). Reclaiming volition: An alternative interpretation of Libet’s experiment. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, 61–77.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus E. Schlosser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schlosser, M.E. The neuroscientific study of free will: A diagnosis of the controversy. Synthese 191, 245–262 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0312-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0312-2

Keywords

Navigation