Skip to main content
Log in

Electron Charge Density: A Clue from Quantum Chemistry for Quantum Foundations

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Within quantum chemistry, the electron clouds that surround nuclei in atoms and molecules are sometimes treated as clouds of probability and sometimes as clouds of charge. These two roles, tracing back to Schrödinger and Born, are in tension with one another but are not incompatible. Schrödinger’s idea that the nucleus of an atom is surrounded by a spread-out electron charge density is supported by a variety of evidence from quantum chemistry, including two methods that are used to determine atomic and molecular structure: the Hartree-Fock method and density functional theory. Taking this evidence as a clue to the foundations of quantum physics, Schrödinger’s electron charge density can be incorporated into many different interpretations of quantum mechanics (and extensions of such interpretations to quantum field theory).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is also how Born [15] retells the story. Other authors explicitly challenge the common narrative and defend the potential value of Schrödinger’s original charge density role (e.g., Einstein [16, p. 168–169]; Jaynes [17]; Bader [18,19,20]; Bell [21, p. 39–40]; Bacciagaluppi and Valentini [22, Chap. 4]; Allori et al. [23]; Norsen [24, Chap. 5]; Gao [6, 7]).

  2. See also [25, Sect. 3.6]; [26, Chap. 17]; [27, p. 10, 147, 460].

  3. Similar examples appear in [29, p. 151]; [18, p. 6]; [30, p. 771]; [31, p. 1141]; [32, p. 223]; [27, p. 403, 460].

  4. Szabo and Ostlund [29, Sect. 3.1.1] sound like they may be thinking along the same lines when they contrast the Coulomb potential sourced by an electron’s “instantaneous position” with the Coulomb potential arrived at by taking a psi-squared-weighted average over the electron’s possible positions. Nelson [33] compares the above understanding of amplitude-squared as describing time-averaged particle motion to a number of alternatives.

  5. In quantum chemistry, see (for example) [29, Sect. 3.8.3]; [18, Sect. 1.3]; [20]; [31]; [27, p. 403].

  6. The Hartree-Fock Method can also be used for excited states [29, Sect. 2.2.6], but we will not discuss that application here.

  7. See, for example, [35, Chap. 9]; [36, Sect. 17.2]; [37, p. 432]; [29, Sect. 2.3.6]; [27, Sect. 11.1].

  8. See [29, Sect. 2.1.2]; [28, Sect. 10.1]; [32, Chap. 8]; [27, Sect. 13.1].

  9. For certain combinations of atoms, there will be multiple local minima corresponding to different stable arrangements of the nuclei (structural isomers and stereoisomers). See [38]; [27, Sect. 15.10]; [39].

  10. This Hamiltonian appears in [27, p. 345].

  11. Modifying the Hartree-Fock method, you can use the relativistic Dirac equation in place of the non-relativistic Schrödinger equation. With that modification, it is called the “Dirac-Fock” or “Dirac-Hartree-Fock” method [40]; [27, p. 581].

  12. Usually, it is assumed that each of these spin orbitals can be written as the product of a single component complex-valued spatial wave function and a two-component spinor that has no spatial dependence. In the restricted Hartree-Fock method (which can be used when there are an even number of electrons), one adds the assumption that electrons come in pairs having exactly the same spatial wave function and opposite spins (see [29, Chap. 3]; [41, p. 12]; [32, Sect. 7.17]).

  13. For discussion of how good this approximation is, see [36, Chap. 18]; [42, p. 164]; [27, Sect. 11.1].

  14. The interpretation of correlation energy is discussed in [43, Sect. II.C]; [37, p. 436]; [28, Sect. 9.8].

  15. This method is presented in [29, Chap. 4]; [28, Sect. 9.8]; [32, Sect. 9.6]; [27, Sect. 16.2]

  16. See [31, 44,45,46].

  17. See footnote 28.

  18. In classical electrostatics, the density of potential energy for a distribution of charge \(\rho ^q(\vec {x})\) in a potential \(V(\vec {x})\) can be written as \(\frac{1}{2}\rho ^q(\vec {x}) V(\vec {x})\) [47, Sect. 1.11]; [48, Sect. 2.4]. Because there will be an equal contribution to the potential energy from the nuclei in the potential sourced by the electron charge density \(\rho ^q(\vec {x})\), (16) does not contain the factor of \(\frac{1}{2}\). Moving from electrostatics to electromagnetism, this potential energy of charged matter is replaced by electromagnetic field energy [49, Chap. 5]; [48, Sect. 2.4.4]. However, for our purposes here (where we are only concerned with electrostatic Coulomb attraction and repulsion), it will be convenient to treat this kind of energy as potential energy possessed by matter.

  19. See [18, p. 9]; [27, problem 16.28].

  20. Note that the availability of this interpretation is independent of the Hartree-Fock approximation. For any wave function (Slater determinant or not), the contribution to the expectation value of the energy from the third term in (8) is equal to the classical electrostatic energy of the Schrödinger charge distribution (6) derived from that wave function interacting with the point charge nuclei.

  21. The derivation of (17)–(21) from the electron-electron interaction term in (8) appears in [37].

  22. By treating the nuclei as point charges and only considering contributions to the energy from pairs of distinct nuclei, we have also left out any contributions from nuclear self-repulsion.

  23. Schrödinger [13, Sect. 3] applied his charge density role for amplitude-squared to the interpretation of such Coulomb integrals when analyzing multi-electron atoms. In the included discussion with Born, Heisenberg, and Fowler, Schrödinger briefly discusses Hartree’s method (a precursor to Hartree-Fock that leaves out the exchange integrals) in order to show that his “hope of achieving a three-dimensional conception [a physical understanding of what is happening in three-dimensional space] is not quite utopian,” though he notes the remaining challenge of incorporating and interpreting exchange terms [22, p. 428–429].

  24. This way of rearranging terms is mentioned in [37, p. 436]; [50, p. 5048]; [41, p. 7].

  25. See [27, Sect. 9.4 and 11.1].

  26. McQuarrie [28, p. 482–489] reviews in detail a similar Hartree-Fock calculation of the ground state of the helium atom, summing over just two terms instead of the five in (24).

  27. Calculations of the bond angle of \(\hbox {H}_2\)O have been discussed in the literature on scientific realism as a point of agreement between the different interpretations of quantum mechanics [52, p. S309]; [53, Sect. 4.5.2].

  28. As Levine [27, Sect. 15.8] explains, the Hartree-Fock method does not (and cannot) yield a unique set of orbitals. There are alternative sets of orbitals that lead to the same multi-electron wave function when you take the Slater determinant.

  29. See [57, p. 69]; [58].

  30. Although Levine [27, Sect. 16.5] calls the electron density an “electron probability density,” he does not mean by this that integrating the electron density (7) over any spatial region gives the probability of finding at least one electron in that region. For sufficiently small regions, the probability of finding more than one electron in the region is negligible and the integrated electron density over that region can be interpreted as giving the probability of finding one (or at least one) electron in that region. However, for large regions the possibility of finding multiple electrons cannot be neglected. The integral of the electron density (7) over all space is N (the total number of electrons) not 1 (the probability of finding at least one electron if you look everywhere). Thus, the electron density may be interpreted as an expected number density (as was explained in Sect. 2) but, speaking precisely, it cannot be interpreted as a probability density.

  31. This way of writing the energy functional matches [41, Eq. 3.2.3]; [32, Eq. 9.36]; [27, Eq. 16.36], though here I have also included the potential energy associated with repulsion between the nuclei to parallel the presentation of the Hartree-Fock method in Sect. 3.1 (as in [60, Eq. 6.12]).

  32. This extension is explained clearly in [62, p. 5384].

  33. See [41, Eq. 7.1.1 & 7.1.13]; [62, Eq. 3.14]; [64, Eq. 5.11]; [60, Eq. 7.5]; [32, p. 320]; [58, Eq. 18]; [27, Eq. 16.44].

  34. For more on the self-interaction correction, see [50]; [41, Sect. 8.3]; [62, 65]; [57, footnote 33]; [64, Sect. 2.3 & 6.7]; [61, Sect. 4.7]; [66].

  35. These applications are discussed in [67]; [60, Sect. 8.9]; [68]; [27, p. 571].

  36. See [11, Sect. 2]; [12, p. 1066–1068]; [69, Sect. 3.1]; [29, Sect. 3.4.7]; [70]; [20, p. 2]; [22, Sect. 4.4]; [27, Sect. 14.2].

  37. See also [71]; [72]; [69, p. 40]; [41, Sect. 1.6]; [25, Sect. 6.2]; [19]; [20, Sect. 4.1].

  38. A third option, GRWf, adds to the ontology special points in spacetime where collapse events (flashes) occur. One could potentially associate these events with momentarily existing point particles that have both mass and charge. Or, one could formulate GRWf so that spacetime contains neither mass nor charge.

  39. See also [78, p. 38]; [79]. Ghirardi et al. [76, Sect. 4.3] consider adding a charge density in addition to a mass density, but reject the idea for reasons that are particular to the continuous spontaneous localization theory that they are discussing (and would not apply to GRW).

  40. For discussion of this supposed virtue of GRWm, see [79, 82,83,84].

  41. One might also wonder whether the matter density of GRWm acts a source for the gravitational field. Derakhshani [92] has explored the idea that it does, which would provide support for calling the matter density a “mass density.”

  42. Because there is no electrostatic self-interaction, in Sect. 3.1 the potential energy of each electron would be determined by only looking at the electromagnetic fields sourced by the other particles. This raises awkward questions as to whether there are many electromagnetic fields or just one [49, p. 36, 158].

  43. In addition to densities of mass and charge, GRWmc (and Smc below) should also include densities of momentum and current to describe the flow of mass and charge.

  44. Another option would be GRWc, with only a charge density and no mass density. (A potential problem for GRWc is mentioned by Allori et al. in [23, footnote 1].)

  45. For reasons that we can put aside here, Stern-Gerlach spin measurements for individual charged particles are difficult and neutral atoms are used instead [93, p. 230]; [94, p. 181]; [95, Sect. 2].

  46. One might similarly argue that Schrödinger’s charge density is already present, deflating the disagreement between S0, Sm, and Smc.

  47. In a realistic scenario, the wave function would branch into many pieces that could be sorted into a z-spin up cluster and a z-spin down cluster [107, Sect. 9], [97, 108, Sect. 3.11]. For our purposes here, we can idealize and speak of two branches post-measurement.

  48. Carroll [109, Chap. 8] makes similar moves regarding the status of energy in the multiverse as a whole and energy within each branch.

  49. See [110, p. 153]; [111, p. 154].

  50. See [115,116,117]; [33, p. 645]; [118]; [7, footnote 5].

  51. Gao [6, Chap. 8] combines this “random discontinuous motion of particles” with a collapse dynamics for the wave function. Without this wave function collapse, his proposal would be a many-worlds theory: Bell’s Everett (?) theory [119]; [120, Sect. 5.1]; [75, Sect. 6.2]; [23, Sect. 4]; [121]; [6, Chap. 8].

  52. Similar approaches are discussed in [122,123,124,125,126].

  53. It would be unwise to assign each electron a smaller charge so that the total electron charge (across all worlds) for the helium atom is what you’d expect, \(-2e\). One problem is that the branching that occurs upon measurement within this interpretation is a process where clusters of worlds separate from one another (in configuration space), leading to a dimming like that discussed for the many-worlds interpretation. For example, if you decide to move your helium atom (with total electron charge \(-2e\)) left or right depending on the result of a quantum measurement with two equiprobable outcomes, then once that is done the total electron charge of the atom will be \(-e\) (not \(-2e\)) in the cluster of worlds where the atom was moved to the left and will also be \(-e\) (not \(-2e\)) in the cluster where the atom was moved to the right.

  54. See [127,128,129] and references therein.

  55. Ultimately, it may be best to view classical fermion fields (like the Dirac field) as Grassmann-valued, not complex-valued. The reasons for this and the challenges that accompany such a picture will not be discussed here (see [127, 130,131,132,133,134,135,136]). The problems with Grassmann field values have led some to advocate only using wave functionals for bosons [137, 138].

  56. I have recently studied this classical field description of electrons in a series of papers focused on understanding electron spin as the actual rotation of energy and charge [95, 136, 139, 140].

  57. See [133, Chap. 4]; [127, 134, 135].

References

  1. Thomson, J.J.: On the structure of the atom: an investigation of the stability and periods of oscillation of a number of corpuscles arranged at equal intervals around the circumference of a circle; with application of the results to the theory of atomic structure. Philos. Mag. Ser. 6 7(39), 237–265 (1904)

  2. Bader, R.F.W., Matta, C.F.: Atoms in molecules as non-overlapping, bounded, space-filling open quantum systems. Found. Chem. 15, 253–276 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Hall, M.J.W., Deckert, D.-A., Wiseman, H.M.: Quantum phenomena modeled by interactions between many classical worlds. Phys. Rev. X 4, 041013 (2014)

  4. Sebens, C.T.: Quantum mechanics as classical physics. Philos. Sci. 82(2), 266–291 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Gao, S.: Reality and meaning of the wave function. In: Gao, S. (ed.), Protective Measurement and Quantum Reality: Toward a New Understanding of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 211–229. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2014)

  6. Gao, S.: The Meaning of the Wave Function: In Search of the Ontology of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2017)

  7. Gao, S.: Is an electron a charge cloud? A reexamination of Schrödinger’s charge density hypothesis. Found. Sci. 23, 145–157 (2018)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Gao, S.: A puzzle for the field ontologists. Found. Phys. 50, 1541–1553 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Born, M.: Zur Quantenmechanik der Stoßvorgänge [On the Quantum Mechanics of Collisions]. Zeitschrift für Physik, 37, 863–867 (1926). English translation in Wheeler, J.A., Zurek, W.H. (eds.): Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1983)

  10. Schrödinger, E.: Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem (Dritte Mitteilung) [Quantization as a Problem of Eigenvalues (Part III)]. Ann. Phys. 80, 437–490 (1926). English translation in Schrödinger, E.: Collected Papers on Wave Mechanics, Blackie & Son Limited, Translated by J.F. Shearer and W.M. Deans (1928)

  11. Schrödinger, E.: Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem (Vierte Mitteilung) [Quantization as a Problem of Eigenvalues (Part IV)]. Ann. Phys. 81, 109–139 (1926). English translation in Schrödinger, E.: Collected Papers on Wave Mechanics, Blackie & Son Limited, Translated by J.F. Shearer and W.M. Deans (1928)

  12. Schrödinger, E.: An undulatory theory of the mechanics of atoms and molecules. Phys. Rev. 28(6), 1049–1070 (1926)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  13. Schrödinger, E.: La Mécanique des Ondes [Wave Mechanics]. Electrons et Photons: Rapports et discussions du cinquième conseil de physique tenu à Bruxelles du 24 au 29 octobre 1927 sous les auspices de l’institut international de physique Solvay, pp. 185–213. English translation in [22] (1928)

  14. Schrödinger, E.: Letter from Schrödinger to Lorentz, 6 June 1926. In Przibram, K., (ed.), Letters on Wave Mechanics, pp. 61–74. Philosophical Library. Translated by M. J. Klein (1934)

  15. Born, M.: Statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics. Science 122(3172), 675–679 (1955)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  16. Einstein, A.: On the method of theoretical physics. Philos. Sci. 1(2), 163–169 (1934)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Jaynes, E.T.: Survey of the Present Status of Neoclassical Radiation Theory. In Mandel, L. and Wolf, E., (eds.), Coherence and Quantum Optics, pp. 35–81. Plenum Press, Berlin (1973)

  18. Bader, R.F.W.: Atoms in Molecules: A Quantum Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Bader, R.F.W.: Letter to the Editor: Quantum mechanics, or orbitals? Int. J. Quant. Chem. 94(3), 173–177 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Bader, R.F.W.: The Density in Density Functional Theory. J. Mol. Struct. 943, 2–18 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Bell, J.S.: Against ‘Measurement’. Phys. World 3, 33–40 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Bacciagaluppi, G., Valentini, A.: Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2009)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: Many worlds and Schrödinger’s first quantum theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 62, 1–27 (2011)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Norsen, T.: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Springer, Berlin (2017)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Gillespie, R.J., Popelier, P.L.A.: Chemical Bonding and Molecular Geometry: From Lewis to Electron Densities. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Longair, M.: Quantum Concepts in Physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2013)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Levine, I.N.: Quantum Chemistry, 7th edn. Pearson, Boston (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  28. McQuarrie, D.A.: Quantum Chemistry, 2nd edn. University Science Books, Mill Valley, CA (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Szabo, A., Ostlund, N.S.: Modern Quantum Chemistry, revised edition. McGraw-Hill, New York (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Shusterman, A.J., Shusterman, G.P.: Teaching chemistry with electron density models. J. Chem. Edu. 74(7), 771–776 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Matta, C.F., Gillespie, R.J.: Understanding and interpreting molecular electron density distributions. J. Chem. Educ. 79(9), 1141–1152 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Atkins, P., Friedman, R.: Molecular Quantum Mechanics, 5th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Nelson, P.G.: How do electrons get across nodes?: A problem in the interpretation of the quantum theory. J. Chem. Educ. 67(8), 643–647 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Pauling, L.: The Nature of the Chemical Bond and the Structure of Molecules and Crystals, 3rd edn. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Slater, J.C.: Quantum Theory of Atomic Structure, vol. 1. McGraw-Hill, New York (1960)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Slater, J.C.: Quantum Theory of Atomic Structure, vol. 2. McGraw-Hill, New York (1960)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Blinder, S.M.: Basic concepts of self-consistent-field theory. Am. J. Phys. 33(6), 431–443 (1965)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  38. Löwdin, P.-O.: On the long way from the Coulombic Hamiltonian to the electronic structure of molecules. Pure Appl. Chem. 61(12), 2065–2074 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Franklin, A., Seifert, V.A.: The problem of molecular structure just is the measurement problem. Br. J. Philos. Sci. (forthcoming)

  40. Desclaux, J.P.: Tour historique. In: Schwerdtfeger, (ed.), Relativistic Electronic Structure Theory, Part 1: Fundamentals. Elsevier, New York (2002)

  41. Parr, R.G., Yang, W.: Density-Functional Theory of Atoms and Molecules. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Scerri, E.R.: Has chemistry been at least approximately reduced to quantum mechanics?. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 160–170 (1994)

  43. Löwdin, P.-O.: Correlation problem in many-electron quantum mechanics I. Review of different approaches and discussion of some current ideas. In Prigogine, I., (ed.), Advances in Chemical Physics, Volume 2, pp. 207–322 (1958)

  44. Scerri, E.R.: Have orbitals really been observed? J. Chem. Educ. 77(11), 1492–1494 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Scerri, E.R.: The recently claimed observation of atomic orbitals and some related philosophical issues. Philos. Sci. 68(3), S76–S78 Supplement: Proceedings of the 2000 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers (2001)

  46. Spence, J.C.H., O’Keeffe, M., Zuo, J.M.: Have orbitals really been observed? J. Chem. Educ. 78(7), 877 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Jackson, J.D.: Classical Electrodynamics, 3rd edn. Wiley, Hoboken, NJ (1999)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  48. Griffiths, D.J.: Introduction to Electrodynamics, 4th edn. Pearson, Glenview, IL (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  49. Lange, M.: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Physics: Locality, Energy, Fields, and Mass. Blackwell, Malden, MA (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  50. Perdew, J.P., Zunger, A.: Self-interaction correction to density-functional approximations for many-electron systems. Phys. Rev. B 23(10), 5048–5079 (1981)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  51. Clementi, E., Roetti, C.: Roothaan-Hartree-Fock atomic wavefunctions: Basis functions and their coefficients for ground and certain excited states of neutral and ionized atoms, Z\(\le \)54. Atomic Data Nuclear Data Tables 14, 177–478 (1974)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  52. Cordero, A.: Realism and underdetermination: some clues from the practices-up. Philos. Sci. 68(3), S301–S312 Supplement: Proceedings of the 2000 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers (2001)

  53. Callender, C.: Can we quarantine the quantum blight? In: French, S., Saatsi, J. (eds.) Scientific Realism and the Quantum, pp. 57–76. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2020)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  54. Aung, S., Pitzer, R.M., Chan, S.I.: Approximate Hartree-Fock wavefunctions, one-electron properties, and electronic structure of the water molecule. J. Chem. Phys. 49, 2071–2080 (1968)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  55. Pitzer, R.M., Merrifeld, D.P.: Minimum basis wavefunctions for water. J. Chem. Phys. 52, 4782–4787 (1970)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  56. Dunning, T.H., Pitzer, R.M., Aung, S.: Near Hartree-Fock calculations on the ground state of the water molecule: energies, ionization potentials, geometry, force constants, and one-electron properties. J. Chem. Phys. 57, 5044–5051 (1972)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  57. March, N.H.: Density functional theory: an introduction. Am. J. Phys. 68, 69–79 (2000)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  58. Becke, A.D.: Perspective: fifty years of density-functional theory in chemical physics. J. Chem. Phys. 140, 18A301 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Seminario, J.M.: An introduction to density functional theory in chemistry. In Seminario, J. M. and Politzer, P., (eds.), Modern Density Functional Theory: A Tool for Chemistry, pp. 1–27. Elsevier, New York (1995)

  60. Martin, R.M.: Electronic Structure: Basic Theory and Practical Applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  61. Engel, E., Dreizler, R.M.: Density Functional Theory: An Advanced Course. Springer, Berlin (2011)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  62. Baerends, E.J., Gritsenko, O.V.: A quantum chemical view of density functional theory. J. Phys. Chem. A 101(30), 5383–5403 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Kohn, W., Sham, L.J.: Self-consistent equations including exchange and correlation effects. Phys. Rev. 140(4A), A1133–A1138 (1965)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  64. Koch, W., Holthausen, M.C.: A Chemist’s Guide to Density Functional Theory, 2nd edition. Wiley-VCH, Weinheim (2001)

  65. Baerends, E.J., Gritsenko, O.V.: Away from Generalized Gradient Approximation: Orbital-dependent exchange-correlation functionals. J. Chem. Phys. 123, 062202 (2005)

  66. Tsuneda, T., Harao, K.: Self-interaction corrections in density functional theory. J. Chem. Phys. 140, 18A513 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Kim, K., Jordan, K.D.: Comparison of density functional and MP2 calculations on the water monomer and dimer. J. Phys. Chem. 98, 10089–10094 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Baseden, K.A., Tye, J.W.: Introduction to density functional theory: calculations by hand on the helium atom. J. Chem. Educ. 91, 2116–2123 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Milonni, P.W.: Semiclassical and quantum-electrodynamical approaches in non-relativistic radiation theory. Phys. Rep. 25(1), 1–81 (1976)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  70. Bader, R.F.W., Larouche, A., Gatti, C., Carroll, M.T., MacDougall, P.J., Wiberg, K.B.: Properties of atoms in molecules: dipole moments and transferability of properties. J. Chem. Phys. 87, 1142–1152 (1992)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  71. Feynman, R.P.: Forces on molecules. Phys. Rev. 56, 340–343 (1939)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  72. Deb, B.M.: The force concept in chemistry. Rev. Mod. Phys. 45(1), 22–43 (1973)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  73. Bader, R.F.W., Fang, D.-C.: Properties of atoms in molecules: caged atoms and the Ehrenfest force. J. Chem. Theory Comput. 1, 403–414 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. Tumulka, R.: The ‘unromantic pictures’ of quantum theory. Phys. Today 40, 3245–3273 (2007)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  75. Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: On the common structure of Bohmian mechanics and the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber theory. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 59, 353–389 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  76. Ghirardi, G.C., Grassi, R., Benatti, F.: Describing the macroscopic world: closing the circle within the dynamical reduction program. Found. Phys. 25, 5–38 (1995)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  77. Ghirardi, G.: Macroscopic reality and the dynamical reduction program. In Dalla Chiara, M.L., Doets, K., Mundici, D., van Benthem, J., (eds.), Structures and Norms in Science, pp. 221–240. Springer, Berlin (1997)

  78. Goldstein, S.: Quantum theory without observers-part two. Phys. Today 51(4), 38–42 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Maudlin, T.: Completeness, supervenience, and ontology. J. Phys. A 40, 3151–3171 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  80. Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: Predictions and primitive ontology in quantum foundations: a study of examples. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 65, 323–352 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  81. Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: The quantum formalism and the GRW formalism. J. Stat. Phys. 149, 142–201 (2012)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  82. Ney, A., Phillips, K.: Does an adequate physical theory demand a primitive ontology? Philos. Sci. 80(3), 454–474 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Ney, A., Albert, D.: The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  84. Ney, A.: The World in the Wave Function: A Metaphysics for Quantum Physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2021)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  85. Forrest, P.: Quantum Metaphysics. Blackwell, Oxford (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  86. Belot, G.: Quantum states for primitive ontologists: a case study. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 2, 67–83 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  87. Hubert, M., Romano, D.: The wave-function as a multi-field. Eur. J. Philos. Sci. 8, 521–537 (2018)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  88. Chen, E.K.: Our fundamental physical space: an essay on the metaphysics of the wave function. J. Philos. 114(7), 27 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  89. Chen, E.K.: Realism about the wave function. Philos. Compass 14(7), 12611 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  90. Romano, D.: Multi-field and Bohm’s theory. Synthese (forthcoming)

  91. Maudlin, T.: Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity, 3rd edn. Wiley-Blackwell, New York (2011)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  92. Derakhshani, M.: Newtonian semiclassical gravity in the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber theory with matter density ontology. Phys. Lett. A 378, 990–998 (2014)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  93. Ballentine, L.E.: Quantum Mechanics: A Modern Development. World Scientific, Singapore (1998)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  94. Griffiths, D.J.: Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edn. Pearson Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, NJ (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  95. Sebens, C.T.: Particles, fields, and the measurement of electron spin. Synthese (forthcoming)

  96. Bedingham, D., Dürr, D., Ghirardi, G., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., Zanghì, N.: Matter density and relativistic models of wave function collapse. J. Stat. Phys. 154, 623–631 (2014)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  97. Wallace, D.: Decoherence and ontology. In Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., Wallace, D., (eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory, & Reality, pp. 53–72. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)

  98. Wallace, D.: A prolegomenon to the ontology of the everett interpretation. In: Ney, A., Albert, D., (eds.), The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 203–222. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

  99. Vaidman, L.: Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/ (2018)

  100. Lewis, P.J.: On the status of primitive ontology. In: Gao, S., (ed.), Collapse of the Wave Function: Models, Ontology, Origin, and Implications, pp. 154–166. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2018)

  101. Dasgupta, S.: Absolutism vs comparativism about quantity. In: Bennett, K., Zimmerman, D.W. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Vol. 8, pp. 105–148. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

  102. Dasgupta, S.: How to be a Relationalist. In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (forthcoming)

  103. Martens, N.C.M.: Regularity comparativism about mass in Newtonian gravity. Philos. Sci. 84, 1226–1238 (2017)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  104. Martens, N.C.M.: Machian comparativism about mass. Br. J. Philos. Sci. (forthcoming)

  105. Martens, N.C.M.: The (un)detectability of absolute Newtonian masses. Synthese 198, 2511–2550 (2021)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  106. Baker, D.J.: Some consequences of physics for the comparative metaphysics of quantity. In: Bennett, K., Zimmerman, D.W. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 12. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2021)

  107. Wallace, D.: Quantum probability from subjective likelihood: improving on Deutsch’s proof of the probability rule. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 38(2), 311–332 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  108. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  109. Carroll, S.: Something Deeply Hidden: Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime. Dutton, New York (2019)

    Google Scholar 

  110. Holland, P.: The Quantum Theory of Motion. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  111. Dürr, D., Teufel, S.: Bohmian Mechanics. Springer, Berlin (2009)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  112. Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Lam, V., Hubert, M.: The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 68, 133–161 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  113. Esfeld, M., Deckert, D.-A.: A Minimalist Ontology of the Natural World. Routledge, New York (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  114. Esfeld, M.: A proposal for a minimalist ontology. Synthese 197, 1889–1905 (2020)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  115. Nelson, E.: Quantum Fluctuations. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1985)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  116. Goldstein, S.: Stochastic mechanics and quantum theory. J. Stat. Phys. 47, 645–667 (1987)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  117. Bohm, D., Hiley, B.J.: Non-locality and locality in the stochastic interpretation of quantum mechanics. Phys. Rep. 172(3), 93–122 (1989)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  118. Bacciagaluppi, G.: Nelsonian mechanics revisited. Found. Phys. Lett. 12, 1–16 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  119. Bell, J.S.: Quantum mechanics for cosmologists. In: Isham, C., Penrose, R., and Sciama, D. (eds.), Quantum Gravity 2, pp. 611–637. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1981)

  120. Barrett, J.A.: The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds. Oxford University Press (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  121. Maudlin, T.: Local beables and the foundations of physics. In: Bell, M., Gao, S. (eds.), Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 Years of Bell’s Theorem, pp. 317–330. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2016)

  122. Holland, P.: Computing the wavefunction from trajectories: particle and wave pictures in quantum mechanics and their relation. Ann. Phys. 315(2), 505–531 (2005)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  123. Tipler, F.J.: What about quantum theory? Bayes and the Born interpretation. arXiv preprint quant-ph/0611245, (2006)

  124. Schiff, J., Poirier, B.: Communication: quantum mechanics without wavefunctions. J. Chem. Phys. 136, 031102 (2012)

  125. Boström, K.J.: Quantum mechanics as a deterministic theory of a continuum of worlds. Quant. Stud. 2(3), 315–347 (2015)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  126. Bokulich, A.: Losing sight of the forest for the psi: beyond the wavefunction hegemony. In: French, S., Saatsi, J. (eds.), Scientific Realism and the Quantum, pp. 185–211. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2020)

  127. Struyve, W.: Pilot-Wave approaches to quantum field theory. J. Phys. 306, 012047 (2011)

  128. Tumulka, R.: On Bohmian mechanics, particle creation, and relativistic space-time: happy 100th birthday, David Bohm! Entropy 20(6), 462 (2018)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  129. Dürr, D., Lazarovici, D.: Understanding Quantum Mechanics: The World According to Modern Quantum Foundations. Springer, Berlin (2020)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  130. Floreanini, R., Jackiw, R.: Functional representation for Fermionic quantum fields. Phys. Rev. D 37(8), 2206 (1988)

  131. Jackiw, R.: Analysis on infinite-dimensional manifolds—Schrödinger representation for quantized fields. In: Éboli, M.G., Santoro, A. (eds.), Field Theory and Particle Physics, pp. 78–143. World Scientific, Singapore (1990)

  132. Hatfield, B.: Quantum Theory of Point Particles and Strings. Frontiers in Physics, vol. 75. Addison-Wesley, Redwood (1992)

  133. Valentini, A.: On the Pilot-Wave Theory of Classical, Quantum and Subquantum Physics PhD thesis ISAS, Trieste, Italy (1992)

  134. Valentini, A.: Pilot-wave theory of fields, gravitation, and cosmology. In: Cushing, J.T., Fine, A., Goldstein, S. (eds.), Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal, pp. 45–66. Kluwer Academic, Berlin (1996)

  135. Struyve, W.: Pilot-wave theory and quantum fields. Rep. Progress Phys. 73(10), 106001 (2010)

  136. Sebens, C.T.: Putting positrons into classical Dirac field theory. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 70, 8–18 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  137. Bohm, D., Hiley, B.J., Kaloyerou, P.N.: An ontological basis for the quantum theory. Phys. Rep. 144(6), 321–375 (1987)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  138. Bohm, D., Hiley, B.J.: The Undivided Universe: An Ontological Interpretation of Quantum Theory. Routledge, London (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  139. Sebens, C.T.: How electrons spin. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 68, 40–50 (2019)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  140. Sebens, C.T.: Possibility of small electron states. Phys. Rev. A 102(5), 052225 (2020)

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you to Craig Callender, Eddy Keming Chen, Scott Cushing, Maaneli Derakhshani, Mario Hubert, Joshua Hunt, Gerald Knizia, Logan McCarty, and Eric Winsberg for helpful feedback and discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Charles T. Sebens.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sebens, C.T. Electron Charge Density: A Clue from Quantum Chemistry for Quantum Foundations. Found Phys 51, 75 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-021-00480-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-021-00480-7

Keywords

Navigation