Skip to main content

Illness and disease: an empirical-ethical viewpoint

Abstract

Background

The concepts of disease, illness and sickness capture fundamentally different aspects of phenomena related to human ailments and healthcare. The philosophy and theory of medicine are making manifold efforts to capture the essence and normative implications of these concepts. In parallel, socio-empirical studies on patients’ understanding of their situation have yielded a comprehensive body of knowledge regarding subjective perspectives on health-related statuses. Although both scientific fields provide varied valuable insights, they have not been strongly linked to each other. Therefore, the article aims to scrutinise the normative-ethical implications of patient perspectives in building a bridge to the empirical ethics debates.

Main text

Three potential fields of tension between the illness and the disease perspective are presented. Consequently, findings from empirical research examining patient perspectives on illness are displayed and the practical implications and associated ethical issues which arise are discussed. This leads to the conclusion that an explicit and elaborate empirical-ethical methodology is needed to deal appropriately with the complex interaction between patients’ views and the medico-professional view of disease. Kon’s four-stage model of normative-empirical collaboration is then applied against the background of empirical data on patient perceptions. Starting from this exemplary approach, the article suggests employing empirical-ethical frameworks for further research on the conceptual and normative issues, as they help to integrate perspectives from the philosophy of medicine with socio-empirical research.

Conclusion

The combination of theoretical and empirical perspectives suggested contributes to a more nuanced discussion of the normative impact of patients’ actual understanding of illness. Further empirical research in this area would profit from explicitly considering potential ethical issues to avoid naturalistic fallacies or crypto-normative conclusions that may compromise healthcare practice. Vice versa, medico-theoretical debates could be enriched by integrating subjective views of those people who are immediately affected.

Peer Review reports

Background

The concept of illness and related ideas such as disease and sickness have developed into a complete “network of medical concepts” ([1], p. 8). Similar to other terms, such as injury, malady and disability, the ways in which they are used sometimes seem arbitrary and interchangeable in everyday language. By contrast, the terms have been the subject of scientific controversy for a long time and still remain without a “standard, normative meaning” ([2], p., 360). The conceptual triad of disease, illness and sickness – first introduced by Twaddle in 1968 [3] – has been especially widespread within this discourse. Twaddle defines disease as “physiological malfunction […] independent of subjective experience and social conventions” ([4], pp. 8-9). In Fleischman’s words, it simply “removes the patient from the pathology” ([5], p. 7). Conversely, illness refers to a “subjectively interpreted undesirable state of health” ([4], p. 10). Sickness, finally, stands for “a social identity […] defined by others with reference to the social activity of that individual” ([4], p. 11).

Twaddle’s conceptual triad is used nowadays in various scientific disciplines, such as sociology or philosophy of medicine, and has undergone extensive theoretical examination (e.g. [6]). The discussion generated multiple efforts to strengthen rigor, overcome deficiencies and to reconceptualise the triple division or its elements. Nordenfelt has especially criticised the conceptual division, as it does not allow any conclusions as long as it is not well-founded in a comprehensive theory of health [7, 8]. Sadegh-Zadeh summarises critically that the only result after decades of debate consists of “a few labels” ([9], p., 605) that transgress logical reasoning and do not allow a clear assignment of specific conditions to disease and illness as they are “all a matter of degree” ([9], p., 607). He, therefore, strives towards a new definition of these elements based on the idea of “fuzziness”.

The emphasis and application of the three concepts in western societies, whose medical paradigm is based on the triple distinction to a great degree, can be regarded as either a bridge or a barrier between the perspectives [7]. The former emphasis promotes the importance of lay views and prompts us to listen to the patients’ stories and feelings [10, 11] in times of medicalisation (e.g. [12, 13]) of live events and experiences. The latter accentuation stresses that referring to the distinction between the perspectives can lead to discrimination and “widens the gap between what patients seek and doctors provide” ([14], p. 9). Furthermore, it suggests that there is something like an objective “professional or expert” view of disease in contrast to the subjective illness experience of “lay” people (e.g. [2]). Danner Clouser et al., for example, highlight that the disease perspective presents itself as “more robust ontologically” ([15], p. 29). Unlike illness, disease seems to allow an objective assessment and detection of reasons with scientific methods that are expected to reveal an ultimate truth.

Boyd [16] holds that it is “elusive” to arrive at a consensus definition of disease, illness and sickness. Nevertheless, it can be noticed as a broad agreement and shared common understanding that the three concepts emphasise different aspects inherent in human ailment. As such, they can serve as a valuable heuristic to explore and analyse phenomena that appear in healthcare practice. One prominent interpretation of the interrelatedness between illness, disease and sickness (the “paramount example”) was suggested by Nordenfelt [17]. According to his position, the subjective experience of illness leads to seeking help from a medical expert who diagnoses the disease. This expert labelling then has consequences regarding the social (sickness) role of the person affected (Fig. 1).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Interrelatedness of the triad according to Nordenfelt’s “standard medical encounter” [17], own illustration

The interpretation and usage of the concepts of disease, illness and sickness have a considerable impact on various facets of health care and social life. Within the medical system, for example, the labelling of an individual as having a disease often remains contested: there are certain statuses, such as “internet addiction” [18,19,20], “burn out” or “obesity” [21], which are – not least depending on the specific national and cultural context – considered as disease or not. In addition, clinicians might disagree whether a person is actually affected by a certain disease or whether the limits of normalcy have not been surpassed in the concrete case. The ascription of having a disease becomes more complicated by the fact that the medically accepted thresholds are subject to constant modifications, as the recent case of US guidelines on hypertension shows impressively [22, 23].

Regarding illness, the patients’ concrete experiences have a considerable influence on health-related behaviour, adherence and the willingness to cooperate with healthcare personnel and institutions, as psychological research has shown [24,25,26,27,28,29]. Furthermore, the subjectively experienced burden of disease is, in the end, crucial for the success of diagnostic or therapeutic measures. The immediate experience of illness, however, does not usually appear in a non-reflective way. Instead, the way patients deal with illness is accompanied by the development of subjective explanatory models, for example regarding causes and modifying factors. The term “illness” (as used in this article), thus, comprises immediate and reflected appreciation of the ailment from the patients’ point of view. One can also include the patients’ engagement with the medico-professional perspective on disease in the latter, which may shape their bodily and mental perceptions as well as their explanatory models.

The concept of sickness, finally, which refers to the social and societal dimensions of ailment, has consequences for such different fields as the sick role in family contexts, health insurance and compensation or working place conditions. The “sickness dimension” of being ill or having a disease, thus, makes us aware that medical conditions cannot be reduced to biomedical or biostatistical conditions or to the subjective feelings of those who are affected. Instead, it is deeply embedded in social practices, ethical traditions and legal systems.

Such practical implications of the concepts of disease, illness and sickness for individuals’ lives and social practice are widely uncontested. At the same time, however, the concrete scope and normative impact of health-related concepts and their interrelatedness are still under discussion. The greatest part of the more recent debates in the philosophy of medicine focuses on the concept of disease, its theoretical embedding and normative implications [30,31,32,33,34]. Attempts to classify the various understandings of disease are extremely varied and do not allow an unambiguous and definite systematisation, for example, along the lines of naturalist and non-naturalist approaches [35,36,37]. However, in addition to the interpretation of disease, the concrete content of the illness concept is equally important from a scientific and practical or normative standpoint. Nevertheless, it has not attracted equal attention in the medico-theoretical debates so far. Consequently, this paper focuses on the duo of illness and disease, seeking to further clarify their interrelatedness beyond Boorse’s observation that they “are related somewhat as are low intelligence and stupidity” ([38], p. 84). Due to the complexity of the field, the concept of sickness will not be considered explicitly in this article. Many ideas developed in the paper (particularly regarding empirical research), however, are also highly relevant concerning sickness and related concepts such as the sickness role or sickness absence.

Starting from the observation that subjective interpretations of health have relevant consequences for individual people, the healthcare system and society, the article aims to further clarify the normative-ethical implications of patient perspectives. Insights from the debates in the philosophy of medicine will be confronted with interdisciplinary empirical studies on actual patient perspectives, which illuminate the narratives of those who are affected. In referring to debates on empirical ethics, this article aims to reconcile perspectives from the philosophy of medicine with socio-empirical research to arrive at a more nuanced discussion of the normative impact of patients’ actual understanding of illness. This can help researchers from different disciplines conducting empirical studies on illness perspectives to align their work better with the normative discourse. In addition, it can support healthcare professionals to foster learning from the “moral pathography” [39] presented and, thus, make sense of clinical experiences they have in therapeutic relationships.

Main text

Medico-theoretical discussions on disease and illness operate mostly independently of a second branch of research which is, however, closely related in terms of content: socio-empirical studies on patients’ actual understanding of their health-related situation. Whereas the – epistemic and normative – importance of patient perspectives is generally acknowledged [40], explicit links between the empirical research and medico-theoretical debates are mainly missing.

A large variety of methodological approaches has already been applied to study patient experiences of illness: qualitative research designs using in-depth interviews (generating narratives of illness experience) or focus groups and quantitative surveys measuring attitudes and mixed-method approaches appear [41,42,43]. In addition, researchers have used different forms of art, such as poems and paintings, as data sources [44]. The following section provides a brief overview of the research areas selected exemplarily examining patients’ experiences and perspectives on illness. The study selection is guided by three potential fields of tension between the illness and the disease perspective: (1) divergent interpretations of causes and context of the same condition, (2) illness in the absence of disease, and (3) disease in the absence of illness. Each of the three sections will highlight practical consequences and ethical challenges arising from the deviation between the empirically documented illness and the medico-professional perspective on disease.

Field of tension I: Illness and disease in contrast

Patients’ understanding of illness is typically presented in the form of narratives and, therefore, qualitative research designs are often used. Such research, on the one hand, aims to illuminate the “lived experience” of illness, focusing especially on what it means to live with a certain condition, for example, mental disorder [45], Huntington’s [46], Parkinson’s [47] or gastro-oesophageal reflux [48]. On the other hand, patients’ subjective views are explored to understand how they conceptualise their illness regarding circumstances and underlying causes [49,50,51]. The conceptions of illness particularly of patients living with a mental disorder have been investigated. Kangas [52], for example, conducted research on theories of depression through narratives of individuals suffering from this condition. Patients described different beliefs regarding reasons why they became depressed: shortcomings of childhood, work-related burn-out and provoking factors, such as life events associated with intense emotions leading to depression. Peter et al. [53] conducted in-depth interviews with individuals diagnosed with different mental health problems and reported how these patients’ perception of disease changed throughout the therapeutic experience.

Concerning somatic conditions, a difference has been demonstrated between patients suffering from chronic symptoms and those experiencing an acute onset: whereas the acutely ill often try to regain normalcy after disruption due to their impairment [54], the chronically ill describe their illness as omnipresent and as a never-ending work [55, 56] that forces them to adjust in all aspects of life and makes planning impossible [57,58,59]. In addition, culture has been shown to be a major factor that shapes beliefs, influences help-seeking behaviour, decision-making concerning treatment and the treatment expectations and outcomes (e.g. [60]). Maier and Straub, who did research on traumatised migrants state that: “There is a high potential for misunderstandings, and obviously a large gap between the respective concepts of illness and appropriate treatment” ([61], p., 233). Public health policies and prevention campaigns are particularly likely to fail if they do not take socio-cultural backgrounds into account [62].

It has also been demonstrated that patients’ theories regarding the cause and treatment of their illness, which may contrast with biomedical evidence and scientific ideas of aetiology, have an impact on health-related behaviour [27, 63,64,65]. The expectations patients have of certain treatments vary widely depending on their different perceptions of illness. This also has an impact on what kind of therapy they are willing to accept and adhere with. Studies have proved the significance of views of illness not only regarding coping and health-related behaviour, such as self-care, therapeutic adherence [66] and secondary prevention, but also rehabilitation (physical health) or recovery (mental health) and self-stigma.

Ethical challenges may arise if perceptions of illness counteract medico-professional definitions of disease and its prevention, e.g. regarding cancer [67]. Patients’ theories might be refuted as lay beliefs and, therefore, be regarded as irrational. In addition, ethical concerns arise in dealing with traditional methods of healing and the question when and how these attempts should be stopped because of expected negative consequences for the patients or their surroundings [68]. If these and other deviations between subjective interpretations and the medico-professional perspective on disease remain undetected, this can have a negative impact on prevention, therapy, rehabilitation and recovery as well as on the patient-physician relationship. Normative questions, thus, arise about ways to acknowledge both perspectives appropriately aiming at a fair integration of illness narratives with the scientific state-of-the-art.

Field of tension II: Illness without disease

The examples described so far refer to patients diagnosed with a certain disease who are feeling ill; at the same time, however, their concrete illness experience and explanatory models differ from the medico-professional perspective. Subjective illness and medically acknowledged disease, nonetheless, do not inevitably occur coincidentally. Instead, people may feel ill without professionals detecting a disease. This pertains, for example, to undesirable bodily complaints, such as pain, that is generally understood as a symptom leading the physician to the diagnose of a disease but sometimes appears without any physical cause [69]. Some of these symptoms (such as pain or fatigue) and syndromes (such as irritable bowel syndrome or fibromyalgia) remain without an obvious somatic cause, even after extensive diagnosis and testing. Thus, they are often referred to as “medically unexplained symptoms” (MUS) [70, 71]. Another example within in this field of tension includes cases where a physical disease has already been cured from a medical perspective but the person affected still feels ill [72]. Additionally, some patients see the doctor with complaints which make them feel ill (weakness, slowness and other indicators for frailty) but that can be explained by age-related changes in bodily functions and loss of functional capacity and, therefore, are not acknowledged as a disease by most physicians [73].

In the situations described, professionals often perceive patients as complicated and feel overstrained when they frequently reappear asking for help. Physicians also might become unsure how to react to patients’ suffering when no accurate (physical) diagnosis can be made. As a result, these patients are sometimes interpreted as having a psychosomatic character, which leads to a range of communicative and ethical challenges [71, 74].

From an ethical perspective, it is important to further analyse whether people who feel ill should be treated as healthy if there are no measurable, objective parameters to detect a disease. This is, for example, relevant regarding (long-term) sickness absence caused by MUS. Other challenges arise concerning obtaining the patient’s informed consent, which might be difficult or even unfeasible if it remains uncertain which diagnostic procedures and therapeutic options will reduce the patient’s burden of symptoms. Balancing the risk-benefit ratio to determine the further course of action in MUS cases is complicated but the abandonment of such an evaluation can cause serious harm through (missing) surgery, medication or diagnostic imaging [75]. Finally, how to address MUS in the communication process and decide what degree of certainty about the absence of a (rare) disease is necessary remains a major challenge.

Patients suffering from illness without medically detected disease do not only challenge the contemporary paradigm and culture of medicine, which prioritises medical and scientific explanations, but also strain healthcare resources [76] – for example, when patients insist on MRI and other costly diagnostic procedures – so that matters of justice in health care are affected when the perception of illness deviates from the medical perspective on diagnostics and treatment [71].

Field of tension III: Disease without illness

A third phenomenon regarding potential tensions between disease and illness relates to people who have been diagnosed with a certain disease but who are not feeling ill. The topic is closely linked to the impact of medico-technological advances, for example, routinely screening for specific diseases such as cancer. In this case, a disease is often detected at a very early stage when people are symptomless and do not feel ill. Martinez [77], for example, analysed the ambiguous experiences of women diagnosed with different forms and stages of cervical cancer (precursors) through using the Papanicolau smear test. These women describe themselves as being simultaneously in a state of subjective, health because they do not feel pain or other restrictions. Martinez summarises the women’s situation as “living on the borderlands of health, disease, and illness” (p. 798) where the diagnosis creates feelings of “disembodiment” (p. 800). Similar experiences of “struggling with unreliability of body” ([78], p. E446) are described in men diagnosed with prostate cancer and individuals with screening-detected colorectal cancer diagnosis [79] who assess themselves as being healthy.

Furthermore, this field of tension includes constellations where patients deny the existence of the attested disease. Some people, for example, claim HIV (human immunodeficiency virus) to be harmless and not to cause AIDS (acquired immunodeficiency syndrome) or any other serious diseases and still other denialism movements doubt that HIV exists at all [80]. Other groups of patients reject the credibility of scientific explanatory models concerning the origin of AIDS and build conspiracy theories [81]. Antiretroviral therapy, for them, is seen only as an instrument to increase the pharmaceutical industry’s profits. As a result of both denialism and conspiracy beliefs, prevention of HIV transmission and therapy of AIDS are significantly hindered.

Practical implications of the examples mentioned above, where individuals are diagnosed with a disease but do not feel ill, are manifold. Foremost, for example, regarding prostate cancer, the confusing situation where objective medical data and subjective feelings of well-being are contradictory, makes it hard for the people affected to choose between different treatment options, such as active surveillance or initial aggressive treatment, for example, surgery [82, 83]. Furthermore, in cases where the risk-benefit ratio is borderline or controversial, this conflict aggravates, as sometimes it is not even sure whether the individual will ever suffer from symptoms or become seriously harmed because of the disease diagnosed [84]. Instead, individuals might experience impairment of physical and mental well-being due to diagnostic procedures, the diagnosis they receive and unnecessary treatment. Long-term effects may mean that individuals are scared of having a disease because they experience that not suffering from symptoms is not necessarily an indicator for health. Consequently, people can become confused and uncertain about their body perception and might lose trust in their health-related feelings.

Ethical questions in this field arise when asymptomatic patients are diagnosed with a certain state that is treated as a disease, leaving their subjective perspective of feeling healthy unappreciated. Such an overemphasis of disease towards illness can lead to overdiagnosis [12, 85, 86], which is closely related to the sovereignty to define the patient’s condition. Although many individuals who are overdiagnosed in screening tests highlight the benefit (rather than the harm) which they perceive due to the feeling that they owe their lives to the overdiagnosis (known as the “popularity paradox” [87,88,89]), this cannot fully neutralise a patient’s right to an interpretative priority regarding their state of health. If the patient feels that his or her perception is not taken seriously, the physician-patient relationship can be compromised, resulting, for example, in a loss of trust. The concept of epistemic injustice, more specifically in this case, a “credibility deficit” [90] called “testimonial injustice” [90, 91], aims to capture this phenomenon which has been applied to analyse the medical field by Kidd and Carel [92,93,94].

There are further ethical challenges inherent to the appropriateness of medical care and the question of how to find the balance between over- and undertreatment especially regarding children [95, 96], mental illness [97] and culturally shaped beliefs. Furthermore, divergent perspectives concerning the state of health can lead to the question how to proceed with people who do not accept their diagnosis and refuse treatment. Informed consent can be challenging or impossible when patients do not feel ill at all, as one of the major preconditions is undermined: if the person affected does not appreciate the medical data introduced by the physician (or is not willing to accept them, respectively), consent to further diagnostic or treatment measures does not occur on an informed basis.

Evaluating the normative impact of patient perspectives on disease

The brief overview of selected fields of empirical research investigating patient perspectives on their conditions has demonstrated the variety of ethical questions which arise concerning the potential tension between illness as a subjective perception and disease as a medico-scientific attribution. Such normative issues, however, are currently not well reflected in the empirical research on patient experiences. The practical use which can legitimately be made from empirical knowledge about patient perspectives depends highly on normative premises regarding the authoritative status attributed to such findings. The transition from empirical findings on patients’ illness experiences to normative claims regarding the health care provided should be carefully reflected against the background of ethical theories, concepts or principles to avoid is-ought fallacies and related problems [98].

Empirical-ethical research has emerged as an innovative research field in the last two decades and is dedicated explicitly to the integration of socio-empirical data and normative theories, principles or concepts. Manifold positions can be taken principally regarding the interaction between the normative and descriptive aspects which are included in ethical judgements. Classifications of the empirical-ethical domain have been suggested using such criteria as the distinction between descriptive and prescriptive science, the locus of moral authority, types of normativity used and more [99]. Specific questions arise, for example, regarding the role of empirical data in the regulation of health care and biotechnology [100] or the adaptation of quality criteria for empirical-ethical research [101]. In addition to such theoretical reflections, various concrete methodologies have been suggested for conducting empirical-ethical studies in biomedicine and health care [102]. Making explicit the normative-empirical interaction in concrete research projects helps to unveil crypto-normative premises which often underlie practical conclusions drawn from empirical data [103].

Recent reviews demonstrate that the proportion of empirical publications in bioethics continues to increase [104] and that most European bioethicists are using empirical methods in their work [105]. Empirical-ethical studies deal with a wide range of bioethical topics, such as compulsory treatment in psychiatry [106], genetic testing [107], assisted reproduction [108] and the end-of-life context [109]. The topic of what constitutes a disease, however, has only rarely been addressed in the empirical-ethical debates [110].

An explicit link between the broad field of socio-empirical studies on patients’ perceptions of illness and the empirical-ethical debate is, thus, greatly lacking. A comprehensive and explicit reflection on the normative-empirical interaction, however, would be desirable for empirical studies on patient perspectives, for example, regarding the acknowledgement of patients’ explanatory models and health-related behaviour in the physician-patient relationship and their implications for the wider contexts of healthcare institutions and policies. Divergent empirical-ethical frameworks could be applied potentially to this field to make the relationship between empirical data and normative questions, principles and arguments explicit. In the following section, a suggestion will be made to utilise Kon’s differentiation between “Lay of the Land”, “Ideal Versus Reality”, “Improving Care” and “Changing Ethical Norms” to clarify the normative impact of patient perspectives on illness.

Four stages of normative-empirical collaboration

In a 2009 article, Alexander A. Kon exhibits four categories to classify empirical research in bioethics, which illuminate the interaction between descriptive data and normative-ethical issues [111]. Whereas Kon considers the four categories as being equally important and helpful, he, nevertheless, describes a hierarchical order between them: the scientific work of the higher categories builds logically on those insights derived in the lower categories. Kon exemplifies the four categories and their logical coherence by using empirical studies on patient autonomy. They can, however, also be read against the background of empirical data on patient perspectives on illness. Kon’s classification represents a rather pragmatic approach to arranging and handling the complex field of empirical-ethical research. In this, however, it can help researchers who conduct socio-empirical research on patients’ perception of illness to further clarify issues of normative-empirical interaction in their studies. It is, therefore, taken in the remainder of this article to sketch some first suggestions of how such a classification of empirical-ethical research could contribute to the quality of empirical research on patient viewpoints, particularly regarding the normative impact of the “illness perspective”.

Kon’s first category, “Lay of the Land”, aims to “define current practices, opinions, beliefs, or other aspects that may be considered the status quo” [111]. Such descriptive or explanatory work can not only provide starting points for further research but may also reveal perspectives for improving care. Concerning patient perspectives on disease, “Lay of the Land” can, for example, reveal differences between illness conceptions of differently affected groups (e.g. adults and children) or between the medico-scientific notion of disease and patients’ subjective perspectives on illness. Whereas normative questions are not answered directly by this unveiling work, it may still be helpful to explain problems occurring in clinical practice. Furthermore, ethical perspectives are opened and explicitly acknowledged regarding the authoritative status of (e.g. psychiatric) patient perspectives, which deviate from the “standard” view of disease in the professional context.

Building on “Lay of the Land” studies, “Ideal Versus Reality” research (Kon’s second category) assesses the extent to which clinical practice reflects ethical norms. Such studies are usually hypothesis-driven and aim for changes in the healthcare system. Research on patients’ illness perceptions may fulfil this “Ideal Versus Reality” function, for example, regarding the practice of informed consent in minors. In many countries, physicians are legally required to involve children in medical decision-making to an extent which is appropriate to the child’s developmental status and capacity. This requirement may also include respect towards children’s conception of their own illness – even if it deviates from the view of parents or healthcare professionals. Empirical knowledge about children’s actual understanding may, thus, be helpful to assess how far the norm to appropriately involve children in decision-making is valid and could be taken as a basis to restructure clinical practice.

The third category, called “Improving Care”, refers to projects which design and test novel methods aiming at ensuring compliance with ethical norms. So far, there are few (or no) empirical studies related to patient perspectives on illness which evaluate interventions for the improvement of clinical care. However, new research designs could be developed in this field. Healthcare institutions, for example, could implement communication training which explicitly includes aspects such as the patients’ own explanatory models for their condition and their interpretation of saluto- or pathogenetic factors. Patient satisfaction or therapy adherence could, for example, serve as endpoints for an evaluation of these programmes. In this way, the dealing deliberately with subjective conceptions of illness could be used for the further development of a patient-centred health care.

Finally, Kon’s category of “Changing Ethical Norms” is designated to studies and comprehensive analyses in which empirical findings inform ethical principles. This process may lead to an adaption of ethical norms regarding aspects that particularly count in practice. Kon uses the example of the development of our understanding of shared decision-making which has emerged, inter alia, from an over-emphasis on autonomous choice, which is not mirrored in practice. Regarding patient perspectives on illness, “Changing Ethical Norms” could mean that public health policies might deviate from medico-technical explanations of disease if this increases their acceptance in a population which adheres, for example, to animist or natural medicine. It might be helpful for the sake of prevention or to improve the access to healthcare services to also include the perspectives of those who are affected, even if they do not match medical science.

Conclusions

The brief analysis of prominent research fields and their normative impact demonstrates that further research on patient perspectives on illness would profit from explicitly considering potential ethical issues emanating from the results. These issues should be discussed against the background of empirical-ethical frameworks to deal systematically with the normative significance of patient perspectives on illness. A distinct empirical-ethical approach can help to avoid is-ought fallacies and crypto-normative conclusions that may arise from empirical studies on patient perspectives and compromise health-care practice. Designing studies in this way could also enrich the debate on empirical ethics methodology, as it allows a special focus on issues such as lay versus professional perspectives, epistemic injustice and the authenticity of viewpoints which are elicited in socio-empirical (mainly qualitative) research.

The medico-theoretical debates on disease, illness and sickness, on the other hand, could profit from a better consideration of the actual subjective views of those people who are experienced with illness. For example, the complex relationship between patients’ immediate experience of symptoms and their reflective dealing with illness and the professional perspective on disease can be understood more realistically when considering the results of empirical research. A fuller and differentiated understanding of patients’ actual experiences could enrich concepts from the philosophy of medicine regarding certain practice fields (e.g. the building of empirically based middle-range theories).

Further theoretical questions refer to the normative status of patient perspectives generally and to methodological issues of how to document the authentic voices of those who are primarily affected [40]. The increasing importance particularly of patient and public involvement makes us aware of the necessity of respecting patient perspectives in an appropriate form and preventing them being instrumentalised for the purposes of distinct groups. Theoretically reflected empirical research on patient perspectives of disease can help us in this and other aims and contribute to the ethical quality of health care.

Abbreviations

AIDS:

acquired immunodeficiency syndrome

HIV:

human immunodeficiency virus

MRI:

magnetic resonance imaging

MUS:

medically unexplained symptoms

References

  1. Nordenfelt L. Understanding the concept of health. 2007. http://www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek/site/papper/NordenfeltLennart.pdf. Accessed 20 Feb. 2018.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Nordby H. Medical explanations and lay conceptions of disease and illness in doctor–patient interaction. Theor Med Bioeth. 2008;29:357–70. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-008-9080-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Twaddle A. Influence and illness: Definitions and definers of illness behavior among older males in Providence, Rhode Island. Providence: Brown University; 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Twaddle A. Disease, illness and sickness revisited. In: Twaddle A, Nordenfelt L, editors. Disease, illness and sickness: three central concepts in the theory of health. Linköping: Studies on Health and Society 18; 1994. p. 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Fleischman S. I am ..., I have ..., I suffer from ...: a linguist reflects on the language of illness and disease. J Med Humanit. 1999;20:3–32. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1022918132461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Carel H, Cooper R, editors. Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays. London: New York Routledge; 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Hofmann B. On the triad disease, illness and sickness. Med Health Care Philos. 2002;27:651–73. https://doi.org/10.1076/jmep.27.6.651.13793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Nordenfelt L. On the disease, illness and sickness distinction: a commentary on Andre Twaddle's system of concepts. In: Twaddle A, Nordenfelt L, editors. Disease, illness and sickness: three central concepts in the theory of health. Linköping: Studies on Health and Society, 18; 1994. p. 19–36.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Sadegh-Zadeh K. Fuzzy health, illness, and disease. J Med Philos. 2000;25:605–38. https://doi.org/10.1076/0360-5310(200010)25:5;1-W;FT605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Biro D. An anatomy of illness. J Med Humanit. 2012;33:41–54. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10912-011-9161-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Charon R, DasGupta S, Hermann N, Irvine C, Marcus ER, Colón ER, et al., editors. The principles and practice of narrative medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hofmann B. Medicalization and overdiagnosis: different but alike. Med Health Care Philos. 2016;19:253–64. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9693-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Wardrope A. Medicalization and epistemic injustice. Med Health Care Philos. 2015;18:341–52. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9608-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Eisenberg L. Disease and illness distinctions between professional and popular ideas of sickness. Cult Med Psychiatry. 1977;1:9–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00114808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Danner Clouser K, Culver CM, Gert B. Malady: a new treatment of disease. The Hastings Cent Rep. 1981;11:29–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Boyd KM. Disease, illness, sickness, health, healing and wholeness: exploring some elusive concepts. Med Humanit. 2000;26:9–17. https://doi.org/10.1136/mh.26.1.9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Nordenfelt L. The concepts of health and illness revisited. Med Health Care Philos. 2007;10:5–10. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-006-9017-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Hall W, Carter A, Forlini C. The brain disease model of addiction: is it supported by the evidence and has it delivered on its promises? Lancet Psychiatry. 2015;2:105–10. https://doi.org/10.1016/S2215-0366(14)00126-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Holden T. Addiction is not a disease. CMAJ. 2012;184:679. https://doi.org/10.1503/cmaj.112-2033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Volkow ND, Koob G. Brain disease model of addiction: why is it so controversial? Lancet Psychiatry. 2015;2:677–9. https://doi.org/10.1016/S2215-0366(15)00236-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Hofmann B. Obesity as a socially defined disease: philosophical considerations and implications for policy and care. Health Care Anal. 2016;24:86–100. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-015-0291-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Whelton PK, Carey RM, Aronow WS, Casey DE, Collins KJ, Dennison Himmelfarb C et al. 2017 ACC/AHA/AAPA/ABC/ACPM/AGS/APhA/ASH/ASPC/NMA/PCNA Guideline for the prevention, detection, evaluation, and management of high blood pressure in adults: a report of the American College of Cardiology/American Heart Association Task Force on Clinical Practice Guidelines. J Am Coll Cardiol. 2017;71:e127-e248. doi:https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jacc.2017.11.006

  23. Muntner P, Carey RM, Gidding S, Jones DW, Taler SJ, Wright JT, et al. Potential U.S. population impact of the 2017 ACC/AHA high blood pressure guideline. J Am Coll Cardiol. 2018;71:109–18. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jacc.2017.10.073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Schlomann P, Schmitke J. Lay beliefs about hypertension: an interpretive synthesis of the qualitative research. J Am Acad Nurse Pract. 2007;19:358–67. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-7599.2007.00238.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Glattacker M, Heyduck K, Meffert C. Illness beliefs and treatment beliefs as predictors of short and middle term outcome in depression. J Health Psychol. 2013;18:139–52. https://doi.org/10.1177/1359105311433907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Clarke AL, Yates T, Smith AC, Chilcot J. Patient's perceptions of chronic kidney disease and their association with psychosocial and clinical outcomes: a narrative review. Clin Kidney J. 2016;9:494–502. https://doi.org/10.1093/ckj/sfw014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Petrie KJ, Weinman J. Patients’ perceptions of their illness. The dynamo of volition in health care. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2012;21:60–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Heyduck K, Meffert C, Glattacker M. Illness and treatment perceptions of patients with chronic low back pain: characteristics and relation to individual, disease and interaction variables. J Clin Psychol Med Settings. 2014;21:267–81. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10880-014-9405-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Kaptein AA, Schoones JW, Fischer MJ, Thong MSY, Kroep JR, van der Hoeven KJM. Illness perceptions in women with breast cancer-a systematic literature review. Curr Breast Cancer Rep. 2015;7:117–26. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12609-015-0187-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Hucklenbroich P. “Disease entity” as the key theoretical concept of medicine. J Med Philos. 2014;39:609–33. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhu040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Hofmann B. The concept of disease-vague, complex, or just indefinable? Med Health Care Philos. 2010;13:3–10. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-009-9198-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Schramme T. The significance of the concept of disease for justice in health care. Theor Med Bioeth. 2007;28:121–35. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-007-9031-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Cooper R. Disease. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci. 2002;33:263–82. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0039-3681(02)00018-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Boorse C. Concepts of health and disease. In: Gifford F, editor. Philosophy of medicine. Burlington; Amsterdam; Oxford: Elsevier; 2011. p. 13–63.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  35. Hofmann B. Complexity of the concept of disease as shown through rival theoretical frameworks. Theor Med. 2001;22:211–36.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Nordenfelt L. The opposition between naturalistic and holistic theories of health and disease. In: Carel H, Cooper R, editors. Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays. London: New York Routledge; 2013. p. 23–36.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Kingma E. Naturalism about health and disease: adding nuance for progress. J Med Philos. 2014;39:590–608. https://doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhu037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Boorse C. On the distinction between disease and illness. In: Caplan AL, McCartney JJ, Sisti D, editors. Health, disaese, and illness: oncepts in medicine. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press; 2004. p. 77–89.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Kidd IJ. Exemplars, ethics, and illness narratives. Theor Med Bioeth. 2017;38:323–34. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9411-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Schicktanz S, Schweda M, Franzen M. 'In a completely different light'? The role of 'being affected' for the epistemic perspectives and moral attitudes of patients, relatives and lay people. Med Health Care Philos. 2008;11:57–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Hughner RS, Kleine SS. Views of health in the lay sector: a compilation and review of how individuals think about health. Health (London). 2004;8:395–422. https://doi.org/10.1177/1363459304045696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Bowling A. Research methods in health: investigating health and health services. 4 ed. Maidenhead, GB, McGraw Hill: Open University Press; 2014.

  43. Glattacker M. Methoden der Erfassung von Krankheitsvorstellungen. In: Hoefert HW, Brähler E, editors. Krankheitsvorstellungen von Patienten - Herausforderung für Medizin und Psychotherapie. Lengerich: Pabst; 2013. p. 73–94.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kaptein AA, Meulenberg F, Smyth JM. A breath of fresh air: images of respiratory illness in novels, poems, films, music, and paintings. J Health Psychol. 2015;20:246–58. https://doi.org/10.1177/1359105314566613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Bartova Z. Learning from the experts: qualitative study of the lived experience of mental illness. Crawley: Edith Cowan University; 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Hagen N, Lundin S, O'Dell T, Petersén Å. L10 Huntington's illness: the lived experience of Huntington's disease. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 2012;83:A46. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp-2012-303524.144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Smith LJ, Shaw RL. Learning to live with Parkinson’s disease in the family unit: an interpretative phenomenological analysis of well-being. Med Health Care Philos. 2017;20:13–21. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9716-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Nilsson G, Larsson S, Johnsson F, Saveman BI. Patients' experiences of illness, operation and outcome with reference to gastro-oesophageal reflux disease. J Adv Nurs. 2002;40:307–15. https://doi.org/10.1046/j.1365-2648.2002.02372.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Riedl A, Maass J, Fliege H, Stengel A, Schmidtmann M, Klapp BF, et al. Subjective theories of illness and clinical and psychological outcomes in patients with irritable bowel syndrome. J Psychosom Res. 2009;67:449–55. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpsychores.2009.02.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Koehler M, Koenigsmann M, Frommer J. Coping with illness and subjective theories of illness in adult patients with haematological malignancies: systematic review. Crit Rev Oncol Hematol. 2009;69:237–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.critrevonc.2008.09.014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Gebremariam MK, Bjune GA, Frich JC. Lay beliefs of TB and TB/HIV co-infection in Addis Ababa, Ethiopia: a qualitative study. BMC Res Notes. 2011;4:277. https://doi.org/10.1186/1756-0500-4-277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Kangas I. Making sense of depression: perceptions of melancholia in lay narratives. Health (N Y). 2001;5:76–92. https://doi.org/10.1177/136345930100500104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Peter O, Lang J, Stein K, Wirth K, Jungbauer J. “Ich bin nicht die Diagnose – aber sie ist auch ein Teil von mir” – Eine qualitative Interviewstudie zu Sichtweisen von psychisch erkrankten Menschen. Psychiat Prax E-first. https://doi.org/10.1055/s-0043-100026.

  54. Morse JM, Johnson JL. Toward a theory of illness: the illness-constellation model. In: Morse JM, Johnson JL, editors. The illness experience. Dimensions of suffering. Newbury Park: SAGE; 1991. p. 315–342.

  55. Corbin J, Hildebrand B, Schaeffer D, Trajektkonzept D. In: Schaeffer D, editor. Bewältigung chronischer Krankheit im Lebensverlauf. Bern: Huber; 2009. p. 55–74.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Corbin JM. The Corbin and Strauss chronic illness trajectory model: an update. Sch Inq Nurs Pract. 1998;12:33–41.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Roing M, Sanner M. A meta-ethnographic synthesis on phenomenographic studies of patients' experiences of chronic illness. Int J Qual Stud Health Well-being. 2015;10:26279. https://doi.org/10.3402/qhw.v10.26279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Shaha M, Cox CL. The omnipresence of cancer. Eur J Oncol Nurs. 2003;7:191–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Ambrosio L, García JMS, Fernández MR, Bravo SA, Ayesa SDDC, Sesma MEU, et al. Living with chronic illness in adults: a concept analysis. J Clin Nurs. 2015;24:2357–67. https://doi.org/10.1111/jocn.12827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Simolka S, Schnepp W. Subjective perspectives of diabetes mellitus among immigrants in the former Soviet Union. Cent Eur J Nurs Midw. 2017;8:596–608. https://doi.org/10.15452/CEJNM.2017.08.0007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Maier T, Straub M. “My head is like a bag full of rubbish”: concepts of illness and treatment expectations in traumatized migrants. Qual Health Res. 2011;21:233–48. https://doi.org/10.1177/1049732310383867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Parveen S, Islam MS, Begum M, Alam M-U, Sazzad HMS, Sultana R, et al. It’s not only what you say, it’s also how you say it: communicating Nipah virus prevention messages during an outbreak in Bangladesh. BMC Public Health. 2016;16:726. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12889-016-3416-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Taïeb O, Bricou O, Baubet T, Gaboulaud V, Gal B, Mouthon L, et al. Patients’ beliefs about the causes of systemic lupus erythematosus. Rheumatology. 2010;49:592–9. https://doi.org/10.1093/rheumatology/kep430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Furman K. Mono-causal and multi-causal theories of disease: how to think virally and socially about the aetiology of AIDS. J Med Humanit 2017; E-pub doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s10912-017-9441-9.

  65. Rubincam C. “It’s natural to look for a source”: a qualitative examination of alternative beliefs about HIV and AIDS in Cape Town, South Africa. Public Underst Sci. 2017;26:369–84. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963662515611823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Al-Qazaz HK, Hassali MA, Shafie AA, Syed Sulaiman SA, Sundram S. Perception and knowledge of patients with type 2 diabetes in Malaysia about their disease and medication: a qualitative study. Res Social Adm Pharm. 2011;7:180–91. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sapharm.2010.04.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Hauser DJ, Nesse RM, Schwarz N. Lay theories and metaphors of health and illness. In: Zedelius CM, Müller B, Schooler JW, editors. The science of lay theories: how beliefs shape our culture, cognition, and health: Springer; 2017. p. 341–54.

  68. Mertz M. Complementary and alternative medicine: the challenges of ethical justification. Med Health Care Philos. 2007;10:329. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-007-9050-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Arnaudo E. Pain as illness. In: Carel H, Cooper R, editors. Health, illness and disease: philosophical essays: Routledge; 2014. p. 143–57.

  70. Rosendal M, Olde Hartman TC, Aamland A, van der Horst H, Lucassen P, Budtz-Lilly A, et al. “Medically unexplained” symptoms and symptom disorders in primary care: prognosis-based recognition and classification. BMC Fam Pract. 2017;18:18. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12875-017-0592-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  71. O’Leary D. Why bioethics should be concerned with medically unexplained symptoms. Am J Bioeth. 2018;18:6–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Servaes P, van der Werf S, Prins J, Verhagen S, Bleijenberg G. Fatigue in disease-free cancer patients compared with fatigue in patients with chronic fatigue syndrome. Support Care Cancer. 2001;9:11–7. https://doi.org/10.1007/s005200000165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  73. Smith R. In search of ‘non-disease. BMJ. 2002;324:883–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  74. Johansen M-L, Risor MB. What is the problem with medically unexplained symptoms for GPs? A meta-synthesis of qualitative studies. Patient Educ Couns. 2017;100:647–54. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pec.2016.11.015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  75. Flynn TW, Smith B, Chou R. Appropriate use of diagnostic imaging in low back pain: a reminder that unnecessary imaging may do as much harm as good. J Orthop Sports Phys Ther. 2011;41:838–46. https://doi.org/10.2519/jospt.2011.3618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  76. Warner A, Walters K, Lamahewa K, Buszewicz M. How do hospital doctors manage patients with medically unexplained symptoms: a qualitative study of physicians. J R Soc Med. 2017;110:65–72. https://doi.org/10.1177/0141076816686348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. Martínez RG. “What's wrong with me?”: cervical cancer in Venezuela-living in the borderlands of health, disease, and illness. Soc Sci Med. 2005;61:797–808. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socscimed.2004.08.050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  78. Krumwiede KA, Krumwiede N. The lived experience of men diagnosed with prostate cancer. Oncol Nurs Forum. 2012;39:E443–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Miles A, Wardle J, Atkin W. Receiving a screen-detected diagnosis of cancer: the experience of participants in the UK flexible sigmoidoscopy trial. Psychooncology. 2003;12:784–802. https://doi.org/10.1002/pon.705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Kalichman SC, Eaton L, Cherry C. “There is no proof that HIV causes AIDS”: AIDS denialism beliefs among people living with HIV/AIDS. J Behav Med. 2010;33:432–40. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10865-010-9275-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  81. Hogg R, Nkala B, Dietrich J, Collins A, Closson K, Cui Z, et al. Conspiracy beliefs and knowledge about HIV origins among adolescents in Soweto, South Africa. PLoS One. 2017;12:e0165087. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0165087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  82. Xu J, Neale AV, Dailey RK, Eggly S, Schwartz KL. Patient perspective on watchful waiting/active surveillance for localized prostate cancer. J Am Board Fam Med. 2012;25:763–70. https://doi.org/10.3122/jabfm.2012.06.120128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Kim C, Wright FC, Look Hong NJ, Groot G, Helyer L, Meiers P, et al. Patient and provider experiences with active surveillance: a scoping review. PLoS One. 2018;13:e0192097. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0192097.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  84. Wilt TJ, Jones KM, Barry MJ, Andriole GL, Culkin D, Wheeler T, et al. Follow-up of prostatectomy versus observation for early prostate cancer. N Engl J Med. 2017;377:132–42. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa1615869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  85. Carter SM, Degeling C, Doust J, Barratt A. A definition and ethical evaluation of overdiagnosis. J Med Ethics. 2016;42:705–14. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2015-102928.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  86. Carter SM, Rogers W, Heath I, Degeling C, Doust J, Barratt A. The challenge of overdiagnosis begins with its definition. BMJ. 2015;350:h869. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.h869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Gurney J, Chong A, Culliford-Semmens N, Tilton E, Wilson NJ, Sarfati D. The benefits and harms of rheumatic heart disease screening from the perspective of the screened population. Int J Cardiol. 2016;221:734–40. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijcard.2016.07.025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  88. Welch HG, Black WC. Overdiagnosis in Cancer. JNCI. 2010;102:605–13. https://doi.org/10.1093/jnci/djq099.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  89. Brodersen J, Kramer BS, Macdonald H, Schwartz LM, Woloshin S. Focusing on overdiagnosis as a driver of too much medicine. BMJ. 2018;362. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.k3494.

  90. Fricker M. Epistemic injustice: power and ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2007. p. 9–29.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Fricker M. Evolving concepts of epistemic injustice. In: Kidd IJ, Medina J, Gaile Pohlhaus J, editors. The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 53–60.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  92. Carel H, Kidd IJ. Epistemic injustice in medicine and healthcare. In: Kidd IJ, Medina J, Gaile Pohlhaus J, editors. The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 336–46.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  93. Kidd IJ, Carel H. Epistemic injustice and illness. J Appl Philos. 2017;34:172–90. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  94. Carel H, Kidd IJ. Epistemic injustice in healthcare: a philosophial analysis. Med Health Care Philos. 2014;17:529–40. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9560-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  95. Burroughs M, Tollefsen D. Learning to listen: epistemic injustice and the child. Episteme. 2016;13:359–77. https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2015.64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  96. Hemmingsson H, Ólafsdóttir LB, Egilson ST. Agreements and disagreements between children and their parents in health-related assessments. Disabil Rehabil. 2017;39:1059–72. https://doi.org/10.1080/09638288.2016.1189603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  97. Scrutton AP. Epistemic injustice and mental illness. In: Kidd IJ, Medina J, Pohlhaus Jr. G, editors. The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 347–355.

  98. de Vries R, Gordijn B. Empirical ethics and its alleged meta-ethical fallacies. Bioethics. 2009;23:193–201. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2009.01710.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  99. Molewijk B, Stiggelbout AM, Otten W, Dupuis HM, Kievit J. Empirical data and moral theory. A plea for integrated empirical ethics. Med Health Care Philos. 2004;7:55–69. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:MHEP.0000021848.75590.b0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  100. Holm S, Jonas MF, editors. Engaging the world: the use of empirical research in bioethics and the regulation of biotechnology. Amsterdam: IOS Press; 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Mertz M, Inthorn J, Renz G, Rothenberger LG, Salloch S, Schildmann J, et al. Research across the disciplines: a road map for quality criteria in empirical ethics research. BMC Med Ethics. 2014;15:17. https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-15-17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  102. Davies R, Ives J, Dunn M. A systematic review of empirical bioethics methodologies. BMC Med Ethics. 2015;16:15. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-015-0010-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  103. Salloch S, Schildmann J, Vollmann J. Empirical research in medical ethics: how conceptual accounts on normative-empirical collaboration may improve research practice. BMC Med Ethics. 2012;13:5. https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-13-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  104. Wangmo T, Hauri S, Gennet E, Anane-Sarpong E, Provoost V, Elger BS. An update on the “empirical turn” in bioethics: analysis of empirical research in nine bioethics journals. BMC Med Ethics. 2018;19:6. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-018-0246-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  105. Wangmo T, Provoost V. The use of empirical research in bioethics: a survey of researchers in twelve European countries. BMC Med Ethics. 2017;18:79. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-017-0239-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  106. Hem MH, Molewijk B, Pedersen R. Ethical challenges in connection with the use of coercion: a focus group study of health care personnel in mental health care. BMC Med Ethics. 2014;15:82. https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-15-82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  107. Ebbesen M, Pedersen BD. Using empirical research to formulate normative ethical principles in biomedicine. Med, Health Care Philos. 2006;10:33. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-006-9011-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  108. Frith L, Jacoby A, Gabbay M. Ethical boundary-work in the infertility clinic. Sociol Health Illn. 2011;33:570–85. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9566.2010.01308.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  109. Salloch S, Wäscher S, Vollmann J, Schildmann J. The normative background of empirical-ethical research: first steps towards a transparent and reasoned approach in the selection of an ethical theory. BMC Med Ethics. 2015;16:20. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-015-0016-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  110. Aultman JM. Conceptualizing disease: unifying the divide between philosophical inquiry and empirical research. Am J Bioeth. 2009;9:78–9. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265160902874387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  111. Kon AA. The role of empirical research in bioethics. Am J Bioeth. 2009;9:59–65. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265160902874320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the reviewers for their helpful comments that significantly helped to improve our manuscript.

Funding

No funding.

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

A.-H. S. and S.S. developed the article topic and structure jointly. Both authors contributed to the article by drafting and critically reviewing and revising the manuscript. Both authors read and approved the final version of the manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sabine Salloch.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Seidlein, AH., Salloch, S. Illness and disease: an empirical-ethical viewpoint. BMC Med Ethics 20, 5 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-018-0341-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-018-0341-y

Keywords