Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Beyond quantitative and qualitative traits: three telling cases in the life sciences

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper challenges the common assumption that some phenotypic traits are quantitative while others are qualitative. The distinction between these two kinds of traits is widely influential in biological and biomedical research as well as in scientific education and communication. This is probably due to both historical and epistemological reasons. However, the quantitative/qualitative distinction involves a variety of simplifications on the genetic causes of phenotypic variability and on the development of complex traits. Here, I examine three cases from the life sciences that show inconsistencies in the distinction: Mendelian traits (dwarfism and pigmentation in plant and animal models), Mendelian diseases (phenylketonuria), and polygenic mental disorders (schizophrenia). I show that these traits can be framed both quantitatively and qualitatively depending, for instance, on the methods through which they are investigated and on specific epistemic purposes (e.g., clinical diagnosis versus causal explanation). This suggests that the received view of quantitative and qualitative traits has a limited heuristic power—limited to some local contexts or to the specific methodologies adopted. Throughout the paper, I provide directions for framing phenotypes beyond the quantitative/qualitative distinction. I conclude by pointing at the necessity of developing a principled characterisation of what phenotypic traits, in general, are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This standard reconstruction is, however, historically inaccurate (see Footnote #8).

  2. Note that this idealised explanation represents a standard one in quantitative genetics (e.g., Pierce 2017; Purcell 2013).

  3. For some critical discussions on nature/nurture and heritability analyses, see Block (1995), Lewontin (1974) and Tabery (2014).

  4. Mather (1941, 1943) originally called “oligogenic” the inheritance pattern characterising these traits and defined it as involving one or a few genes. However, over time, the term ‘oligogenic’ became ambiguous and almost synonymic with ‘monogenic’ (see, e.g., Katsanis 2016).

  5. For a comprehensive database of Mendelian traits, see https://omim.org (Accessed 18 August 2019). See also https://www.who.int/genomics/public/geneticdiseases/en/index2.html (Accessed 19 July 2019).

  6. However, these limitations are uniform across the searched titles; so, the research should not present any biases when examining trends in the use of the terms over time or across research areas.

  7. Note that, although most biological characteristics are thought to be quantitative, much more attention in genetics textbooks is given to Mendelian traits—the analysis of quantitative genetics is usually confined to a chapter towards the end of the book (e.g., Hartl and Jones 1998; Pierce 2017; Snustad and Simmons 2012).

  8. The unification of biometrics and Mendelism is usually attributed to Fisher’s 1918 infinitesimal model (e.g., Morrison 2007; Plomin et al. 2013; Visscher and Goddard 2019). However, well before Fisher, scholars from both sides achieved similar results or proposed ways for bridging the gap between the two, including East (1910), Johannsen (1903), Nilsson-Ehle (1909), Pearson (1900), Tammes (1911), Yule (1902), but also Mendel himself as well as Weldon in unpublished works (see Cock 1973; Jamieson and Radick 2013; Müller-Wille and Richmond 2016; Porter 2005; Radick 2005; Roll-Hansen 1978; Stamhuis 1995). I thank Staffan Müller-Wille (personal communication, January 2017) and Ida H. Stamhuis (July 2019) for pointing at these works.

  9. On the concept of genetic difference-maker and other definitions of genetic causality, see Burian and Kampourakis (2013), Griffiths and Stotz (2013), Okasha (2009) and Waters (2007).

  10. Note, for instance, that many traits that have been long considered Mendelian or monogenic, like eye and hair colour, have proved to be polygenic (see McDonald 2012; Sturm and Frudakis 2004).

  11. I thank James DiFrisco for pointing at this literature (personal communication, August 2018).

  12. In metaphysical terms, characters and states can be considered determinables and determinates, respectively (on this distinction, see Wilson 2017). For instance, ‘red eye’ and ‘brown eye’ are determinates of the determinable ‘eye colour.’.

  13. Note that my definition of characters and states is consistent with Lawrence’s (2008) but departs from that of scholars working on homology. For instance, according to Wagner, “the relationship between character identity and character states is the same as that for gene identity and alleles in genetics” (2014, pp. 53–54). This seems to imply that there is a one-to-one relationship between, for instance, the alleles a, b and c of the gene x and the relative states a*, b*, and c* of the character x*. However, in my definition, the relationship between a gene and its possible alleles (at the genotypic level) and a character and its possible states (at the phenotypic level) is just analogical and should not be understood in causal terms. Indeed, different states of the same character can have different types of developmental causes. For instance, the state a* can be due to just one difference-maker, but the state b* can be influenced by many genes or involve environmental influences. Moreover, the developmental causes of a character can differ greatly from those of its states. For example, the character ‘eye colour’ in flies develops under the influences of many genes, but the state ‘red eye’ can depend on just one genetic difference-maker. In other words, the species-specific development of a trait on the one hand, and the development of specific variants of such trait on the other, can be due to (partly) different developmental causes.

  14. For instance, at the behavioural level, IQ represents a single dimension on which all individuals can be placed. However, this dimension does not correspond to a single cognitive or biological phenomenon: rather, the behavioural generality of intelligence is realised by the interaction between many cognitive and neurobiological processes, e.g., working memory, processing speed, reasoning, metacognition, and neural plasticity, as well as linguistic, mathematical, and visuospatial abilities (see Kovacs and Conway 2016; Kray and Frensch 2002; Serpico 2018; Van der Maas et al. 2006).

  15. Here, I refer to the definition of schizophrenia adopted in contemporary psychiatric nosography (i.e., the one usually cited by behavioural geneticists), which is mostly based on the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM), now at its fifth edition (APA 2013).

  16. Diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia involve other aspects concerning, e.g., the level of social functioning and the persistence of symptoms over time. These aspects are not relevant to my discussion.

  17. Note that, although diagnosis remains categorical, the latest edition of DSM includes a sort of ‘spectrum’ of psychotic disorders, where some conditions are characterised by fewer (or less severe) symptoms than major disorders (APA 2013, p. 122; see also Fusar-Poli et al. 2013). I thank Valentina Petrolini for pointing at this literature (personal communication, January 2020). About categorical versus dimensional approaches in psychiatry, see Keil et al. (2017).

  18. While the name ‘threshold model’ is somewhat standard, ‘quantitative-liability model’ is of my choice.

  19. On this view, mental disorders would correspond to so-called practical kinds (see Haslam 2014; Zachar 2000).

  20. Note that the model assumes that there is a frequency distribution for the severity of every symptom, and each person displays all symptoms to some degree (Jang 2005, p. 47).

  21. It is well possible that more than one schizophrenia state will be identified, each of which associated with its own typical symptoms, biomarkers, and aetiologies. This would not represent an obstacle for my proposal to conceive of schizophrenia(s) as a state(s) instead of a character(s).

  22. On this view, the schizophrenia state(s) would be stably associated with some symptoms and biomarkers, and this cluster of properties would allow us to distinguish between the schizophrenia state(s) and other possible states of the neuroendocrine-metabolic system.

References

  • Ahluwalia KB (2009) Genetics, 2nd edn. New Age International, New Delhi

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association (2013) Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 5th edn. American Psychiatric Publishing, Arlington

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Block N (1995) How heritability misleads about race. Cognition 56(2):99–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooker RJ (2018) Genetics: analysis & principles, 6th edn. McGraw Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM, Kampourakis K (2013) Against “genes for”: could an inclusive concept of genetic material effectively replace gene concepts? In: Kampourakis K (ed) The philosophy of biology. A companion for educators. Springer, Berlin, pp 597–628

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton PR, Bowden JM, Tobin MD (2007) Epidemiology and genetic epidemiology. In: Balding DJ, Bishop M, Cannings C (eds) Handbook of statistical genetics, vol 2. Wiley, Hoboken, pp 1111–1140

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlborg O, Haley CS (2004) Epistasis: too often neglected in complex trait studies? Nat Rev Genet 5(8):618–625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen R, Shi L, Hakenberg J, Naughton B, Sklar P, Zhang J, Zhou H, Tian L, Prakash O, Lemire M, Sleiman P (2016) Analysis of 589,306 genomes identifies individuals resilient to severe Mendelian childhood diseases. Nat Biotechnol 34(5):531–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cock AG (1973) William Bateson, mendelism and biometry. J Hist Biol 6(1):1–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colless DH (1985) On “character” and related terms. Syst Zool 34(2):229–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper DN, Krawczak M, Polychronakos C, Tyler-Smith C, Kehrer-Sawatzki H (2013) Where genotype is not predictive of phenotype: towards an understanding of the molecular basis of reduced penetrance in human inherited disease. Hum Genet 132(10):1077–1130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyle JT (2006) Glutamate and schizophrenia: beyond the dopamine hypothesis. Cell Mol Neurobiol 26(4–6):363–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dar-Nimrod I, Heine SJ (2011) Genetic essentialism: on the deceptive determinism of DNA. Psychol Bull 137(5):800–818

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietz AG, Goldman SA, Nedergaard M (2020) Glial cells in schizophrenia: a unified hypothesis. Lancet Psychiatry 7:272–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiFrisco J (2019) Developmental homology. In: Nuno de la Rosa L, Müller GB (eds) Evolutionary developmental biology: a reference guide. Springer, Berlin, pp 1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • DiFrisco J, Jaeger J (2019) Beyond networks: mechanism and process in evo-devo. Biol Philos 34(6):54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1970) Genetics of the evolutionary process. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes SM, Matthews L (2019) Heritability. In: Zalta EN (ed) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/heredity

  • East EM (1910) A Mendelian interpretation of variation that is apparently continuous. Am Nat 44(518):65–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eley TC, Rijsdijk F (2005) Introductory guide to the statistics of molecular genetics. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 46(10):1042–1044

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falconer DS (1965) The inheritance of liability to certain diseases, estimated from the incidence among relatives. Ann Hum Genet 29(1):51–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falconer DS, Mackay TFC (1996) Introduction to quantitative genetics. Longman Group, Essex

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1918) The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian inheritance. Trans R Soc Edinb 52:399–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA, Immer FR, Tedin O (1932) The genetical interpretation of statistics of the third degree in the study of quantitative inheritance. Genetics 17(2):107–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Freudenstein JV (2005) Characters, states and homology. Syst Biol 54(6):965–973

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fristrup KM (2001) A history of character concepts in evolutionary biology. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, Cambridge, pp 15–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusar-Poli P, Borgwardt S, Bechdolf A, Addington J, Riecher-Rössler A, Schultze-Lutter F, Keshavan M, Wood S, Ruhrmann S, Seidman LJ, Valmaggia L (2013) The psychosis high-risk state: a comprehensive state-of-the-art review. JAMA Psychiatry 70(1):107–120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galton F (1894) Natural inheritance. Macmillan & Co, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb G (1995) Some conceptual deficiencies in ‘developmental’ behavior genetics. Hum Dev 38(3):131–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffing B (1950) Analysis of quantitative gene action by constant parent regression and related techniques. Genetics 35(3):303–321

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P, Stotz K (2013) Genetics and philosophy: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartl DL, Jones EW (1998) Genetics: principles and analysis, 4th edn. Jones and Bartlett Publishers, Sudbury

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartwell L, Goldberg ML, Fischer JA, Hood LE (2018) Genetics: from genes to genomes, 6th edn. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslam N (2014) Natural kinds in psychiatry: conceptually implausible, empirically questionable, and stigmatizing. In: Kincaid H, Sullivan JA (eds) Classifying psychopathology. Mental kinds and natural kinds. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 11–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Insel TR (2010) Rethinking schizophrenia. Nature 468(7321):187–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Insel TR (2014) The NIMH research domain criteria (RDoC) project: precision medicine for psychiatry. Am J Psychiatry 171(4):395–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger J, Monk N (2014) Bioattractors: dynamical systems theory and the evolution of regulatory processes. J Physiol 592(11):2267–2281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson A, Radick G (2013) Putting Mendel in his place: how curriculum reform in genetics and counterfactual history of science can work together. In: Kampourakis K (ed) The philosophy of biology. A companion for Educators. Springer, Berlin, pp 577–595

    Google Scholar 

  • Jang KL (2005) The behavioral genetics of psychopathology: A clinical guide. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen W (1903) Über Erblichkeit in Populationen und in reinen Linien. Gustav Fischer Verl, Jena

    Google Scholar 

  • Katsanis N (2016) The continuum of causality in human genetic disorders. Genome Biol 17(1):233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil G, Keuck L, Hauswald R (eds) (2017) Vagueness in psychiatry. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempthorne O (1978) A biometrics invited paper: logical, epistemological and statistical aspects of nature-nurture data interpretation. Biometrics 34(1):1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler KS (2005) “A gene for…”: the nature of gene action in psychiatric disorders. Am J Psychiatry 162(7):1243–1252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler KS (2014) The dopamine hypothesis of schizophrenia: an updated perspective. In: Kendler KS, Parnas J (eds) Philosophical issues in psychiatry III: the nature and sources of historical change. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 283–294

    Google Scholar 

  • Klug WS, Cummings MR, Spencer CA, Palladino MA, Ward SM (2016) Concepts of genetics. Eleventh Edition, Pearson

    Google Scholar 

  • Knopik VS, Neiderhiser JM, DeFries JC, Plomin R (2017) Behavioral genetics, 7th edn. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovacs K, Conway AR (2016) Process overlap theory: a unified account of the general factor of intelligence. Psychol Inq 27(3):151–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kray J, Frensch P (2002) A view from cognitive psychology: g–(G)host in the correlation matrix? In: Sternberg R, Grigorenko E (eds) The general factor of intelligence. How general is it?. Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, pp 183–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence E (ed) (2008) Henderson’s dictionary of biology, 14th edn. Pearson Education, Harlow

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin R (1974) Annotation: the analysis of variance and the analysis of causes. Am J Hum Genet 26(3):400–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Mather K (1941) Variation and selection of polygenic characters. J Genet 41(1):159–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather K (1943) Polygenic inheritance and natural selection. Biol Rev 18(1):32–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather K (1964) Human diversity. The nature and significance of differences among men. Oliver & Boyd, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Mather K, Jinks JL (1982) Biometrical genetics: the study of continuous variation. Chapman & Hall, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDonald JH (2012) Myths of human genetics: introduction to the myths. http://udel.edu/~mcdonald/mythintro.html. Accessed 22 July 2019

  • Mendel G (1866) Versuche über Pflanzen-Hybriden. Verhandlungen des Naturforschenden Vereines in Brünn, IV

  • Milton CC, Ulane CM, Rutherford S (2006) Control of canalization and evolvability by Hsp90. PLoS ONE 1(1):e75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan TH, Sturtevant AH, Muller HJ, Bridges CB (1915) The mechanism of Mendelian heredity. Henry Holt and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2007) The development of population genetics. In: Matthen M, Stephens C (eds) Philosophy of biology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 309–333

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille S, Richmond ML (2016) Revisiting the origins of genetics. In: Müller-Wille S, Brandt C (eds) Heredity explored: between public domain and experimental science, 1850–1930. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 367–394

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RM, Pettersson ME, Carlborg O (2013) A century after Fisher: time for a new paradigm in quantitative genetics. Trends Genet 29(12):669–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nilsson-Ehle H (1909) Kreuzungsuntersuchungen an hafer und weizen. vol 20, No. 2. H. Ohlssons buchdruckerei

  • Norton B (1975) Metaphysics and population genetics: Karl Pearson and the background to Fisher’s multi-factorial theory of inheritance. Ann Sci 32(6):537–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2009) Causation in biology. In: Menzies P, Beebee H, Hitchcock C (eds) The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 707–725

    Google Scholar 

  • Online Mendelian Inheritance in Man, OMIM® (2019) McKusick-Nathans Institute of Genetic Medicine, Johns Hopkins University (Baltimore, MD). https://omim.org. Accessed 18 Aug 2019

  • Orgogozo V, Morizot B, Martin A (2015) The differential view of genotype–phenotype relationships. Front Genet 6(179):1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrowski MF, Jarne P, David P (2000) Quantitative genetics of sexual plasticity: the environmental threshold model and genotype-by-environment interaction for phallus development in the snail Bulinus truncatus. Evolution 54(5):1614–1625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson K (1900) The grammar of science, 2nd edn. Adam & Charles Black, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierce BA (2017) Genetics: a conceptual approach, 6th edn. Freeman & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Plomin R, Haworth CMA, Davis OSP (2009) Common disorders are quantitative traits. Nat Rev Genet 10:872–878

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plomin R, DeFries JC, Knopik VS, Neiderhiser JN (2013) Behavioral genetics, 6th edn. Worth Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock C (1989) The genetics of eye color in Drosophila melanogaster. Tested Studies for Laboratory Teaching, pp 141–155

  • Porter TM (2005) The biometric sense of heredity: statistics, pangenesis and positivism. In: Müller-Wille S, Rheinberger HJ (eds) A cultural history of heredity III: 19th and early 20th centuries. Max Planck Institute for the History of Science, Berlin, pp 31–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine WB (1971) The origins of theoretical population genetics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Purcell S (2013) Appendix. Statistical methods in behavioral genetics. In: Plomin R, DeFries JC, Knopkin VS, Neiderhiser JN (eds) behavioral genetics, 6th edn. Worth Publishers, New York, pp 357–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Radick G (2005) Other histories, other biologies. R Inst Philos Suppl 56:21–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radick G (2011) Physics in the Galtonian sciences of heredity. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 42(2):129–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratner C (2004) Genes and psychology in the news. New Ideas Psychol 22(1):29–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger HJ, Müller-Wille S, Meunier R (2015) Gene. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/gene

  • Roff DA, Stirling G, Fairbairn DJ (1997) The evolution of threshold traits: a quantitative genetic analysis of the physiological and life-history correlates of wing dimorphism in the sand cricket. Evolution 51(6):1910–1919

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen N (1978) The genotype theory of Wilhelm Johannsen and its relation to plant breeding and the study of evolution. Centaurus 22(3):201–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford SL (2003) Between genotype and phenotype: protein chaperones and evolvability. Nat Rev Genet 4(4):263–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz J (2009) In pursuit of the gene. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriver CR (2007) The PAH gene, phenylketonuria, and a paradigm shift. Hum Mutat 28:831–845

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serpico D (2018) What kind of kind is intelligence? Philos Psychol 31(2):232–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snustad DP, Simmons MJ (2012) Principles of genetics, 6th edn. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamhuis IH (1995) A female contribution to early genetics: Tine Tammes and Mendel’s laws for continuous characters. J Hist Biol 28(3):495–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strachan T, Read AP (2011) Human molecular genetics, 4th edn. Garland Science, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturm RA, Frudakis TN (2004) Eye colour: portals into pigmentation genes and ancestry. Trends Genet 20(8):327–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery J (2014) Beyond versus: the struggle to understand the interaction of nature and nurture. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tammes T (1911) Das Verhalten fluktuierend variierender Merkmale bei der Bastardierung. Recueil des travaux botaniques Neerlandais 8(3/4):201–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Turkheimer E (2011) Still missing. Res Hum Dev 8(3–4):227–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Maas HJL, Dolan CV, Grasman RPPP et al (2006) A dynamical model of general intelligence: the positive manifold of intelligence by mutualism. Psychol Rev 113(4):842–861

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Visscher PM, Goddard ME (2019) From RA Fisher’s 1918 paper to GWAS a century later. Genetics 211(4):1125–1130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Visscher PM, Hill WG, Wray NR (2008) Heritability in the genomics era–concepts and misconceptions. Nat Rev Genet 9(4):255–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1941) Evolution of developmental systems. Nature 147(3717):108–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (2008) The basic ideas of biology. Biol Theory 3(3):238–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GPW (2014) Homology, genes, and evolutionary innovation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waters CK (2007) Causes that make a difference. J Philos 104(11):551–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson J (2017) Determinables and determinates. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/determinate-determinables

  • Yule GU (1902) Mendel’s laws and their probable relations to intra-racial heredity. New Phytol 1(10):222–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zachar P (2000) Psychiatric disorders are not natural kinds. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 7(3):167–182

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhu M, Yu M, Zhao S (2009) Understanding quantitative genetics in the systems biology era. Int J Biol Sci 5(2):161–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by the University of Genoa. The funding source had no role other than financial support. I thank Andrea Borghini, James DiFrisco, Kate E. Lynch, Staffan Müller-Wille, Valentina Petrolini, John R. G. Turner, Marco Viola, and two anonymous reviewers for their feedback on previous versions of the manuscript. I also thank Cristina Amoretti, John Dupré, Flavia Fabris, Marcello Frixione, Gregory Radick, and Luca Rivelli for fruitful and enriching discussions on the topic.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Davide Serpico.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (DOCX 221 kb)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Serpico, D. Beyond quantitative and qualitative traits: three telling cases in the life sciences. Biol Philos 35, 34 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09750-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09750-6

Keywords

Navigation