Skip to main content
Log in

Free will and mystery: looking past the Mind Argument

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Among challenges to libertarians, the Mind Argument has loomed large. Believing that this challenge cannot be met, Peter van Inwagen, a libertarian, concludes that free will is a mystery. Recently, the Mind Argument has drawn a number of criticisms. Here I seek to add to its woes. Quite apart from its other problems, I argue, the Mind Argument does a poor job of isolating the important concern for libertarians that it raises. Once this concern has been clarified, however, another argument serves to renew the challenge. The Assimilation Argument challenges libertarians to explain how ostensible exercises of free will are relevantly different from other causally undetermined outcomes, outcomes that nobody would count as exercises of free will. In particular, libertarians must explain how agents can have the power to settle which of two causally possible futures becomes the actual future. This will require them to distinguish cases where this power is supposedly present from similar cases where it’s clearly absent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Mind Argument gets its name from the journal Mind, where several prominent versions of the argument have appeared (see, for example, Hobart 1934).

  2. The other, closely related, challenge has come to be known as the Luck Argument. According to the Luck Argument, causally undetermined actions are a matter of luck or chance, and thus do not provide a basis for holding the agent morally responsible (see Mele 2006, Chap. 3, for an important discussion of this argument). Here I leave the Luck Argument to one side.

  3. I defend an earlier version of the Assimilation Argument in Shabo (2011a).

  4. Recent critiques of the Mind Argument can be found in Graham (2010), Coffman and Smith (2010), and Franklin (forthcoming). And McKay and Johnson (1996) have presented an influential counterexample to an inference rule that figures in both the Consequence Argument and the Mind Argument.

  5. But see Finch and Warfield (1998) for an attempt to replace β with a principle that supports the Consequence Argument but not the Mind Argument.

  6. Graham (op. cit., pp. 288–289) has also questioned whether the Mind Argument really depends on β; however, Graham’s basis for doing so is somewhat different from mine.

  7. McKay and Johnson (op. cit.) present a convincing counterexample to β; since my concern isn’t with β, I won’t review this counterexample. As will be seen, however, the concern I raise for van Inwagen’s version of the Mind Argument also applies to Nelkin’s (2001) version, which forgoes β (see note 9).

  8. Kane (1999, 2007) develops an account that features conflicting mental efforts, based on incommensurable reasons that the agent has for making each choice. For another event-causal approach, see Ekstrom (2000, 2003).

  9. The same point applies, mutatis mutandis, to Nelkin’s (2001) version of the Mind Argument, which derives N(R occurred) from the substantive premise N[DB occurred & (DB occurred ⊃ R occurred)], and the tautology, □{[DB occurred & (DB occurred ⊃ R occurred)] ⊃ R occurred}. If the agent had a choice about whether R occurred—something this argument gives us no reason to deny—the first premise is false.

  10. Indeed, van Inwagen (2008, p. 338) expressly draws this modal conclusion from the Mind Argument. However, he doesn’t make it clear how the necessity claim (necessarily, if a prospective action is causally undetermined by the past and the laws, the agent lacks the ability to perform it) is supposed to follow from the premises of the Mind Argument, given that some of the statements that occur after the assumption for conditional proof are contingent statements.

  11. Warfield (2000, p. 169) presents this as a criticism of this version of the Consequence Argument. In response, I have argued (2011b) that van Inwagen isn’t committed to the modal claim, but only to the weaker claim that this conjunction is actually false: determinism is true and we have free will.

  12. When searching for a previous reference in the literature to “the power to settle” which of two causally possible actions one performs, I came across Steward (2009). While I do not share Steward’s view that this power is required for action, I believe that she has struck upon an especially promising way of expressing the main concern about free will and undetermined actions. Other ways of expressing this (or a related) concern are in terms of whether the agent has the power to ensure that one undetermined outcome or the other ensues (Haji 2001, p. 190), or whether the agent has “antecedent-determining control” of the undetermined outcome (Kane 1996, p. 144). I believe that the settling formulation has advantages over these other characterizations.

  13. We might put this by saying that, according to van Inwagen, Alice cannot have well-founded confidence that she will tell the truth in full recognition of these antecedent probabilities. If Alice did not suspect that the outcome is subject to these probabilities, her confidence that she will tell the truth might be such that she could sincerely promise to do so; however, this confidence wouldn’t be well founded. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this point.

  14. Franklin (forthcoming) suggests—incorrectly, in my view—that this claim is incoherent.

  15. In an intriguing recent discussion of the Rollback Argument, Fischer (2011) considers a case in which the device implanted is doubly randomizing: it is a matter of chance whether it activates or remains inoperative; and, if it does activate, it randomizes the agent’s choice. I discuss such a doubly randomizing device in support of the Rollback Argument in Shabo (2011a); Fischer, however, shows how such a case can be used to challenge the Rollback Argument. I plan to address Fischer’s argument in future work.

  16. Why is it difficult to see the choice (or “choice”) in Case 4 as based on Alice’s reasons, notwithstanding that a “snapshot” of her brain immediately before this event is indistinguishable from a snapshot of her brain in Case 5 at the same instant, and notwithstanding that her choices in the Case 4 replays will make sense to her just as their counterparts in the Case 5 replays do? Presumably, this is because her actions in the Case 4 replays, where the device operates, have deviant causal histories, ones that preclude those actions from being appropriately based on her reasons.

References

  • Clarke, R. (2003). Libertarian accounts of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coffman, E. J., & Smith, D. (2010). The fall of the Mind Argument and some lessons about free will. In J. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & D. Shiers (Eds.), Action, ethics, and responsibility: Topics in contemporary philosophy series (pp. 127–148). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, L. W. (2000). Free will. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, L. W. (2003). Free will chance, and mystery. Philosophical Studies, 113, 153–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finch, A., & Warfield, T. (1998). The Mind Argument and libertarianism. Mind, 107, 515–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2011). Indeterminism and control: An approach to the problem of luck. In M. Freeman (Ed.), Law and neuroscience: Current legal issues, Vol. 13. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (To be reprinted in Fischer, Deep control: Essays on free will and human value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.)

  • Franklin, C. E. (forthcoming). Farewell to the Luck (and Mind) Argument. Philosophical Studies.

  • Graham, P. A. (2010). Against the Mind Argument. Philosophical Studies, 148, 273–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2001). Control conundrums: Modest libertarianism responsibility, and explanation. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 82, 178–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobart, R. E. (1934). Free will as involving determinism and inconceivable without it. Mind, 58, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1999). Responsibility luck, and chance. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 217–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (2007). Libertarianism. In J. M. Fischer, R. Kane, D. Pereboom, & M. Vargas (Eds.), Four views on free will (pp. 5–43). D. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T., & Johnson, D. (1996). A reconsideration of an argument against compatibilism. Philosophical Topics, 24, 113–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2003). Agents’ abilities. Noûs, 37, 447–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2001). The Consequence Argument and the Mind Argument. Analysis, 61, 107–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shabo, S. (2011a). Why free will remains a mystery. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92, 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shabo, S. (2011b). What must a proof of incompatibilism prove? Philosophical Studies, 154, 361–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steward, H. (2009). The truth in compatibilism and the truth of libertarianism. Philosophical Explorations, 12, 167–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2000). Free will remains a mystery. Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 1–19. (Reprinted in and cited from R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 158–177). New York: Oxford University Press.)

  • van Inwagen, P. (2002). The mystery of metaphysical freedom. In R. Kane (Ed.), Free will (pp. 189–195). Oxford: Blackwell Readings in Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2008). How to think about the problem of free will. Journal of Ethics, 12, 327–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warfield, T. (2000). Causal determinism and human freedom are incompatible: A new argument for incompatibilism. Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 167–180.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I presented a draft of Sects. 2–4 at the University of Tennessee Knoxville and the University of Delaware. I would like to thank audiences at both places for thoughtful and engaging discussion. Special thanks to E.J. Coffman for valuable conversation and correspondence on some of the key issues raised here. Thanks also to John Nolt for a very helpful discussion of the role of probability in these arguments. I would also like to thank John Martin Fischer and an anonymous referee for Philosophical Studies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Seth Shabo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shabo, S. Free will and mystery: looking past the Mind Argument. Philos Stud 162, 291–307 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9760-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9760-z

Keywords

Navigation