Skip to main content
Log in

Is Yogācāra Phenomenology? Some Evidence from the Cheng weishi lun

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There have been several attempts of late to read Yogācāra through the lens of Western phenomenology. I approach the issue through a reading of the Cheng weishi lun (Treatise on the Perfection of Consciousness Only), a seventh-century Chinese compilation that preserves the voices of multiple Indian commentators on Vasubandhu’s Triṃśikāvijñaptikārikā (Thirty Verses on Consciousness). Specifically, I focus on the “five omnipresent mental factors” (pañcasarvatraga, Chin. wu bianxing xinsuo) and the “four aspects” (Chin. sifen) of cognition. These two topics seem ripe, at least on the surface, for phenomenological analysis, particularly as the latter topic includes a discussion of “self-awareness” (svasaṃvedana, svasaṃvitti, Chin. zizheng). Yet we find that the Cheng weishi lun account has little in common with the tradition associated with Husserl and his heirs. The categories and modes of analysis in the Cheng weishi lun do not emerge from or aver to a systematic reflection on the nature of “lived experience” so much as they are focused on subliminal processes and metaphysical entities that belong to the domain of the noumenal. In my conclusion I suggest that the later pramāṇa tradition associated with Dignāga and Dharmakīrti—a tradition that profoundly influenced later Yogācāra exegesis in Tibet—did indeed take a “phenomenological turn.” But my comparison shows that both traditions falter when it comes to relating conceptual content to non-conceptual experience, and thus there is reason to be skeptical about claims that phenomenology is epistemologically grounded in how the world presents itself first-personally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

[Note: texts in the Taishō shinshū daizōkyō 大正新修大藏經 (edited by Takakusu Junjirō 高楠順次郎 and Watanabe Kaigyoku 渡邊海旭, Tokyo: Taishō issaikyō kankōkai, 1924–1932) are indicated by the text number (“T.”) followed by the volume, page, register (a, b, or c), and line number(s).]

  • Arnold, D. A. (2005). Buddhists, brahmins, and belief: Epistemology in Indian and Buddhist philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. A. (2010). Self-awareness (svasaṃvitti) and related doctrines of Buddhists following Dignāga: Philosophical characterizations of some of the main issues. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 38(3), 323–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. A. (2012). Brains, buddhas, and believing: The problem of intentionality in classical Buddhist and cognitive-scientific philosophy of mind. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 227–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1997). Biology versus computation in the study of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 159–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, S. (1982). Selfless persons: Imagery and thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, F. (1999). Three texts on consciousness only. Berkeley, CA: Numata Center for Buddhist Translation and Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coseru, C. (2012). Perceiving reality: Consciousness, intentionality, and cognition in Buddhist philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de La Vallée Poussin, L. (1928). Vijnaptimatratasiddhi : la siddhi de Huian-Tsang (2 Vols.). Paris: P. Geunther.

  • de La Vallée Poussin, L. (1988–1990). Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam (L. M. Pruden, Trans.) (4 Vols.). Berkeley: Asian Humanities Press.

  • Deleanu, F. (2013). Meditative practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and liberation through the thing-in-itself. In U. T. Kragh (Ed.), The foundation for yoga practitioners: The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi treatise and its adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet (pp. 884–919). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dhammajoti, K. L. (2007). Ākāra and direct perception (pratyakṣa). Pacific World (3rd series), 9, 245–272.

  • Dhammajoti, K. L. (2009). Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma (4th revised ed.). Hong Kong: Center for Buddhist Studies, University of Hong Kong (1st ed. published in Colombo, 2002).

  • Dreyfus, G. (1996). Can the fool lead the blind? Perception and the given in Dharmakīrti’s thought. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 24(3), 209–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, G. (1997). Recognizing reality: Dharmakīrti’s philosophy and its Tibetan interpretations. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, G. (2007). Is perception intentional? A preliminary exploration of intentionality in Dharmakīrti. In B. Kellner, H. Krasser, M. T. Much, & H. Tauscher (Eds.), Pramāṇakīrti: Papers dedicated to Ernst Steinkellner on the occasion of his 70th birthday (pp. 95–113). Vienna: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien, Universität Wien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eckel, M. D. (2008). Bhāviveka and his Buddhist opponents: Chapters 4 and 5 of the Verses on the Heart of the Middle Way (Madhyamakahṛdayakārikāḥ) with the commentary entitled The Flame of Reason (Tarkajvāla). Harvard Oriental Series 70. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Eltschinger, V. (2009). On the career and the cognition of yogins. In E. Franco (Ed.), Yogic perception, meditation, and altered states of consciousness (pp. 169–213). Vienna: Verlag der Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engle, A. B. (2009). The inner science of Buddhist practice: Vasubandhu’s summary of the five heaps with commentary by Sthiramati. Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franco, E. (2009). Yogic perception, meditation, and altered states of consciousness. Vienna: Verlag der Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frauwallner, E. (2010). The philosophy of Buddhism (G. L. Sangpo, Trans.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. (Original German ed., Die Philosophie des Buddhismus, Berlin: Akademie-Verlag 1956, 3rd ed., 1969; 4th ed., 1994.)

  • Fukihara Shōshin 富貴原章信. (1988). Yuishiki no kenkyū: sanshō to shibun 唯識の研究: 三性と四分. Tokyo: Kokusho kankōkai.

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2013). The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2015). Phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2015 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/self-consciousness-phenomenological/.

  • Ganeri, J. (1999). Self-intimation, memory and personal identity. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 27(5), 469–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. L. (2006). The conventional status of reflexive awareness: What’s at stake in a Tibetan debate? Philosophy East and West, 56(2), 201–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. L. (2011). Ask not what Buddhism can do for cognitive science; ask what cognitive science can do for Buddhism. Bulletin of Tibetology, 47, 15–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. L. (2015). Engaging Buddhism: Why it matters to philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, J. C. (2015). Paving the great way: Vasubandhu’s unifying Buddhist philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, R. F. (2006). How Buddhism began: The conditioned genesis of the early teachings (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. (1986). On being mindless: Buddhist meditation and the mind–body problem. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammerstrom, E. J. (2010). Buddhists discuss science in Modern China (1895–1949). Ph.D. Dissertation, Indiana University.

  • Harvey, P. (1989). Consciousness mysticism in the discourses of the Buddha. In K. Werner (Ed.), The yogi and the mystic: Studies in Indian and comparative mysticism (pp. 81–99). Richmond, Surrey: Curzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, P. (1995). The selfless mind: Personality, consciousness and nirvāṇa in early Buddhism. Richmond, Surrey: Curzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hattori, M. (1968). Dignāga, On perception, being the Pratyakṣapariccheda of Dignāga’s Pramāṇasamuccaya from the Sanskrit fragments and the Tibetan versions. Harvard Oriental Series No. 47. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1965). Philosophy and the crisis of European man. In Q. Lauer (Trans.), Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy (pp. 149–192). New York: Harper & Row. (A translation of “Die Philosophie in der Krisis europäischen Menschheit,” delivered in Vienna in 1935.)

  • Husserl, E. (1981). Pure phenomenology, its method and its field of investigation. In P. McCormick & F. A. Elliston (Eds.), Husserl: Shorter works (R. W. Jordan, Trans.) (pp. 10–17). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (A translation of “Die reine Phänomenologie ihr Forschungsgebiet und ihre Methode,” presented at the University of Freiburg in 1917.)

  • Kawamura, L. S. (1964). A study of the Triṃśikā–Vijñapti-Bhāṣya. M.A. Thesis, Kyoto University.

  • Kellner, B. (2010). Self-awareness (svasaṃvedana) in Dignāga’s Pramāṇasamuccaya and -vṛtti: A close reading. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 38(3), 203–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellner, B. (2014). Changing frames in Buddhist thought: The concept of ākāra in Abhidharma and in Buddhist epistemological analysis. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 42(2–3), 275–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellner, B., & McClintock, S. (2014). Ākāra in Buddhist philosophical and soteriological analysis: An introduction. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 42(4), 427–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kern, I. (1988). The structure of consciousness according to Xuanzang. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 19(3), 282–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kern, I. (1992). Object, objective phenomenon and objectivating act according to the ‘Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi’ of Xuanzang (600–644). In D. P. Chattopadhyaya, L. Embree, & J. Mohanty (Eds.), Phenomenology and Indian philosophy (pp. 262–269). Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Krasser, H. (2004). Are Buddhist Pramāṇavādins non-Buddhistic? Dignāga and Dharmakīrti on the impact of logic and epistemology on emancipation. Hōrin, 11, 129–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kritzer, R. (2005). Vasubandhu and the Yogācārabhūmi: Yogācāra elements in the Abhidharmakośabhāṣya. Studia Philologica Buddhica Monograph Series 18. Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.

  • Lopez, D. S. (2008). Buddhism & science: A guide for the perplexed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lopez, D. S. (2012). The scientific Buddha: His short and happy life. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lusthaus, D. (2002). Buddhist phenomenology: A philosophical investigation of Yogācāra Buddhism and the Ch’eng wei-shih lun. London: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makeham, J. (Ed.). (2014). Transforming consciousness: Yogācāra thought in modern China. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matilal, B. K. (1986). Perception: An essay on classical Indian theories of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCrea, L. (2013). The transformations of Mīmāṃsā in the larger context of Indian philosophical discourse. In E. Franco (Ed.), Periodization and historiography of Indian philosophy (pp. 127–143). Vienna: Verein Sammlung de Nobili; Institut für Südasien-, Tibet- und Buddhismuskunde der Universität Wien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriyama, S. (2010). On self-awareness in the Sautrāntika epistemology. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 38(3), 261–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruegg, D. S. (1969). La théorie du tathāgatagarbha et du gotra: Études sur la sotériologie et la gnoséologie du Bouddhisme. Publications de l’École Française d’Extrême-Orient 70. Paris: École Française d’Extrême-Orient.

  • Schmithausen, L. (1976). On the problem of the relation of spiritual practice and philosophical theory in Buddhism. In German scholars on India (Vol. 2, pp. 235–250). Bombay: Nachiketa Publications.

  • Schmithausen, L. (2007). Ālayavijñāna: On the origin and the early development of a central concept of Yogācāra philosophy. Tokyo: International Institute for Buddhist Studies. (Reprint with Addenda and Corrigenda.)

  • Schmithausen, L. (2014). The genesis of Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda: Responses and reflections. Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharf, R. H. (2014). Is nirvāṇa the same as insentience? Chinese struggles with an Indian Buddhist ideal. In J. Kieschnick & M. Shahar (Eds.), India in the Chinese imagination: Myth, religion, and thought (pp. 131–160). Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinkellner, E. (2005). Dignāga’s Pramāṇasamuccaya, Chap. 1: A hypothetical reconstruction of the Sanskrit text with the help of the two Tibetan translations on the basis of the hitherto known Sanskrit fragments and the linguistic materials gained from Jinendrabuddhi’s Ṭīkā. Published Online http://www.ikga.oeaw.ac.at/Mat/dignaga_PS_1.pdf.

  • Tagawa, S. (2009). Living Yogacara: An introduction to consciousness-only Buddhism (C. Muller, Trans.). Boston: Wisdom Books.

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuck, A. (1990). Comparative philosophy and the philosophy of scholarship: On the Western interpretation of Nāgārjuna. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, W. S. (2003). The Buddhist unconscious: The ālaya–vijñāna in the context of Indian Buddhist thought. London: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, A. (2006). The self’s awareness of itself: Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha’s arguments against the Buddhist doctrine of no-self. Vienna: Sammlung de Nobili, Institut für Südasien-, Tibet-und Buddhismuskunde der Universität Wien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, A. (2010). Bhaṭṭa Rāmakaṇṭha’s elaboration of self-awareness (svasaṃvedana), and how it differs from Dharmakīrti’s exposition of the concept. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 38(3), 297–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wei, T. (1973). Ch’eng wei-shih lun: The doctrine of mere-consciousness. Hong Kong: Ch’eng wei-shih lun Publication Committee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, P. (1998). The reflexive nature of awareness: A Tibetan Madhyamaka defence. London: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yao, Z. (2005). The Buddhist theory of self-cognition. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert H. Sharf.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sharf, R.H. Is Yogācāra Phenomenology? Some Evidence from the Cheng weishi lun . J Indian Philos 44, 777–807 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-015-9282-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10781-015-9282-7

Keywords

Navigation