Skip to main content
Log in

The Logics of Discovery in Popper’s Evolutionary Epistemology

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Popper is well known for rejecting a logic of discovery, but he is only justified in rejecting the same type of logic of discovery that is denied by consequentialism. His own account of hypothesis generation, based on a natural selection analogy, involves an error-eliminative logic of discovery and the differences he admits between biological and conceptual evolution suggest an error-corrective logic of discovery. These types of logics of discovery are based on principles of plausibility that are used in the generation as opposed to the preliminary evaluation of hypotheses. The normative relevance of these principles is grounded in the distinction between strategic and definitory rules.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This term is due to Monk (1977).

  2. “The Logic of Scientific Discovery” is a misleading translation of “Logik der Forschung.” A more accurate translation would be “The General Rules of Scientific Research.” However, Popper uses the term ‘discovery’ to refer to the whole of scientific inquiry—both the generation and evaluation of hypotheses—while the traditional use of ‘discovery’ by philosophers of science refers only to the process of generating hypotheses.

  3. Hoyningen-Huene (1987) delineates six ways in which this distinction can be interpreted, none of which involves the rejection of a logic of discovery.

  4. Ayer (1946, pp. 85–86) distinguishes between logical and psychological content. With this distinction, it can be granted that a purely formal logic of discovery does not generate anything novel in the purely logical sense, but that the uncovering of content not previously noticed is still psychologically novel.

  5. The change to a new problem situation could turn the generative process into one of serendipity and not a logic of discovery, but before a satisfactory solution to a problem is found, scientists do not as a rule change the problem on which they are working.

  6. Bradie (1986) labels these the evolutionary epistemology of mechanisms (EEM) and the evolutionary epistemology of theories (EET).

  7. Rescher’s position differs from the others because he rejects the natural selection analogy on the level of theories but accepts it on the level of methods. That is, he rejects thesis Darwinism but defends methodological Darwinism.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (1970). Inference to scientific laws. In R. Stuewer (Ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 5, pp. 87–104). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Akeroyd, F. (2004). Popper's evolutionary epistemology revamped. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 35, 385–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. (1946). Language, truth and logic. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, J. (1896). A new factor in evolution, American Naturalist, 30, 441–451, 536–553.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. (1984). The retreat to commitment. Peru, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blachowicz, J. (1998). Of two minds: The nature of inquiry. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradie, M. (1986). Assessing evolutionary epistemology. Philosophy and Biology, 1, 401–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. (1974a). Evolutionary epistemology. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper (pp. 416–483). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. (1974b). Unjustified variation and selective retention in scientific discovery. In F. Ayala (Ed.), Studies in the philosophy of biology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1986). The blind watchmaker. (Reprinted in Philosophy of Biology, 61 ff., by M. Ruse, Ed., Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).

  • Hadamard, J. (1945). The psychology of invention in the psychological field. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. (1958). The logic of discovery. Journal of Philosophy, 55(25), 1073–1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herbart, J. (1816). A textbook in psychology: An attempt to found the science of psychology on experience, metaphysics and mathematics. New York: Appleton.

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34(3), 503–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1987). Discovery and justification. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 18(4), 501–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanterovich, A. (1993). Scientific discovery: Logic and tinkering. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, K. (1987). The logic of discovery. Philosophy of Science, 54, 435–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kepler, J. (1596). Mysterium cosmographicum (A. Duncan, Trans.). New York: Abaris.

  • Kepler, J. (1609). Astronomia Nova (W. Donahue, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

  • Kleiner, S. (1993). The logic of discovery: A theory of the rationality of scientific research. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1980). Why was the logic of discovery abandoned? In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery, logic and rationality. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1977). The logic of discovery. Philosophy Research Archives, 3, 1–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1990). Discovery logics. Philosophica, 45(1), 7–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1998). Discovery—logic of. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy (pp. 99–103). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2004). Abduction as a logic and methodology of discovery: The importance of strategies. Foundations of Science, 9, 267–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. (1908). A neglected argument for the reality of God. In The Peirce Edition Project (Ed.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 2, pp. 434–450). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1976). Unended quest. An intellectual autobiography. Glasgow: William Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1979). Objective knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K., & Eccles, J. (1977). The self and its brain. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. An analysis of the foundations and the structure of knowledge. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1977). Methodological pragmatism. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D., & Aiston, S. (2006). The myth of scientific method in contemporary educational research. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 40(2), 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1986). Taking Darwin seriously. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shah, M. (2007). Is it justifiable to abandon all search for a logic of discovery? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(3), 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1973). Does scientific discovery have a logic? Philosophy of Science, 40, 471–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E., & Lipton, P. (1989). Where guesses come from: Evolutionary epistemology and the anomaly of guided variation. Biology and Philosophy, 4, 33–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1980). Against evolutionary epistemology. In P. Asquith & R. Giere (Eds.), PSA (pp. 187–196). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1981). The autonomy of a logic of discovery. In J. Slater, W. Sumner, & F. Wilson (Eds.), Pragmatism and purpose (pp. 248–260). Toronto: Toronto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. (1953). Genetic assimilation for acquired character. Evolution, 7, 118–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. (1990). Confessions of a creationist. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Evolution, cognition, and realism. Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mehul Shah.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Shah, M. The Logics of Discovery in Popper’s Evolutionary Epistemology. J Gen Philos Sci 39, 303–319 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-008-9070-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-008-9070-0

Keywords

Navigation