Skip to content
BY 4.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter January 12, 2022

The Quasi-Empirical Epistemology of Mathematics

  • Ellen Yunjie Shi EMAIL logo

Abstract

This paper clarifies and discusses Imre Lakatos’ claim that mathematics is quasi-empirical in one of his less-discussed papers A Renaissance of Empiricism in the Recent Philosophy of Mathematics. I argue that (1) Lakatos’ motivation for classifying mathematics as a quasi-empirical theory is epistemological; (2) what can be called the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics is not correct; (3) analysing where the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics goes wrong will bring to light reasons to endorse a pluralist view of mathematics.

1 Introduction

In A Renaissance of Empiricism in the Recent Philosophy of Mathematics,[1] Imre Lakatos claims that mathematics is quasi-empirical. What does Lakatos mean by this claim? Why does he think that mathematics is quasi-empirical? And most importantly, is this claim correct? This paper aims to investigate these questions.

In Section 2, I address the first two questions. I first explain what Lakatos means by the terms “Euclidean theories” and “quasi-empirical theories” in Renaissance. In order to do so, I make clear Lakatos’ motivation of classifying mathematics as a Euclidean theory or, alternatively, a quasi-empirical theory, by referring to another one of his papers Infinite Regress and Foundations of Mathematics.[2] As we will see, this motivation is mostly epistemological. Then I present Lakatos’ arguments leading to his conclusion that mathematics is quasi-empirical.

The question of whether mathematics is indeed quasi-empirical is discussed in Section 3. If mathematics is quasi-empirical, then an immediate question “what are the falsifiers for mathematics?” arises (Lakatos 1976, p. 202). According to Lakatos, there are two kinds of potential falsifiers for mathematics: logical falsifiers and heuristic falsifiers (Lakatos 1976, p. 213). Logical falsifiers are concerned with the consistency of the quasi-empirical theory. More specifically, they are logical contradictions of the form p ¬ p . Lakatos believed that when a theory derives a logical contradiction the theory is falsified. However, I argue that is not always the case. There are inconsistent theories (Mortensen 1995) in mathematics, all of which derive logical contradictions but remain legitimate parts of mathematics. Heuristic falsifiers, on the other hand, are the informal theories intended to be formalised in mathematics. I argue that no epistemic source can support any mathematical statement to be taken as a heuristic falsifier. Therefore, I conclude in this section that mathematics is not quasi-empirical.

Given that the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics is not correct, in Section 4, I investigate what instead should be the correct picture of mathematics. Based on the arguments in Section 3, I argue that truth-value injections[3] and transmissions in mathematics do not carry the epistemic weight as Lakatos thinks. The truth-value injections are mostly pragmatic. They are “artificial” – that is to say, the truth-value injections are stipulated by mathematicians. And so there can be more than one way of such truth-value injections. Therefore, I suggest that the correct picture of mathematics should be pluralistic. There can be a plurality of equally legitimate mathematical systems with their own pragmatic virtues, even if they are mutually incompatible. The truth-values of mathematical statements are thus relative to systems. The truth-value transmission of a theory thus only establishes the truth-values of the statements relative to the system. Lakatos’ quasi-empirical epistemology does capture the idea of extrinsic justifications for axioms in mathematics, which are, roughly speaking, the justifications by the desirable consequences of having the axiom. But he is wrong to view it as the single methodology of mathematics and to attach significant epistemic values to the justifications.

2 Lakatos’ Quasi-Empirical Epistemology of Mathematics

2.1 Euclidean Theories and Quasi-Empirical Theories

In one of his under-discussed papers[4] A Renaissance of Empiricism in the Recent Philosophy of Mathematics, Imre Lakatos makes the claim that mathematics is quasi-empirical. But what does it mean for a theory to be quasi-empirical? In Renaissance, the definition of quasi-empirical theories is presented in contrast to Euclidean theories. According to Lakatos, both Euclidean theories and quasi-empirical theories are deductive systems. To draw the distinction between them, we follow Lakatos in calling the sentences in the deductive systems whose truth-values are initially injected basic statements. Then a deductive system is a Euclidean theory if it is the deductive closure of the true basic statements, otherwise it is quasi-empirical (Lakatos 1976, p. 206). Lakatos states in Renaissance that the ideal of a theory (e.g. Euclidean geometry) was once thought to be Euclidean, which, in greater detail, is:

a deductive system with an indubitable truth-injection at the top (a finite conjunction of axioms) – so that truth, flowing down from the top through the safe truth-preserving channels of valid inferences, inundates the whole system. (Lakatos 1976, p. 205)

However, it turned out that scientific theories could not be modelled as a Euclidean theory. Instead, they are quasi-empirical theories:

Scientific theories turned out to be organised in deductive systems where the crucial truth-value injection was at the bottom – at a special set of theorems. But truth does not flow upwards. (Lakatos 1976, p. 205)

It is important to note that, in Lakatos’ characterisation of quasi-empirical theories, there is no requirement on the nature of a theory.[5] That is to say, a quasi-empirical theory doesn’t have to be an empirical theory. Whether a theory is empirical depends on whether its basic statements are concerned with spatio-temporal entities. While whether a theory is quasi-empirical is decided by the direction of the truth-value[6] flow of the theory, i.e. the upward flow of falsity.

Further comparisons between Euclidean theories and quasi-empirical theories are made in Renaissance (Lakatos 1976, p. 206). A Euclidean theory may be claimed to be true; while a quasi-empirical theory is either conjectural or false. The characteristic logical flow for a Euclidean theory is the transmission of truth from axioms to the rest of the theory; while the characteristic flow for a quasi-empirical theory is the re-transmission of falsity from false basic statements to the hypothesis. In a Euclidean theory, the true basic statements prove the rest of the system; while in a quasi-empirical theory, the true basic statements are explained by the rest of the system.

However, the distinctions between Euclidean theories and quasi-empirical theories made above can seem somewhat confusing: surely in any deductive system truth flows downwards and falsity flows upwards, how do these two truth-value flows help to differentiate two kinds of theories? In addition, why does Lakatos note that in a quasi-empirical theory the true basic statements are explained by the rest of the system instead of just saying that they are proved by the rest of the system? To clear up the confusion, I believe that it is crucial to make clear Lakatos’ motivation for suggesting the classification of theories into Euclidean ones and quasi-empirical ones in the first place, which can be found in another one of his papers Infinite Regress and Foundations of Mathematics. In the opening section of Regress, Lakatos reports a sceptical argument which concluded there can be no foundations of any knowledge:

One can try to pin down the meaning of a term either by defining it in other terms – this leads to infinite regress – or by defining it in “perfectly well known terms”. But what does one mean by “perfectly well known terms”? The abyss of infinite regress opens up again …… But even allowing for “exact” concepts, how can we prove that a proposition is true? How can we avoid the infinite regress in proofs, even if we could avoid the infinite regress in definitions? Meaning and truth can only be transferred, but not established. But if so, how can we know? (Lakatos 1962, pp. 156–157)

According to this sceptical argument, it seems impossible to pin down the exact meaning of a term. And even if we have managed to pin down the exact concepts, how can we establish the truth of a proposition through a proof while there can be an infinite regress in finding more and more fundamental premises for the proof?[7] The sceptics thus provided a negative answer to the question “how do we know?” by denying that we can have any knowledge at all. Consequently, Lakatos remarks that “it has become a vital problem for rationalism to stop these exasperating twin infinite regresses[8] and to provide knowledge with a firm bedrock” (Lakatos 1962, p. 157). Lakatos then introduces three enterprises which tried to achieve this: the Euclidean Programme, the Empiricist Programme and the Inductivist Programme.[9] The Euclidean Programme, roughly speaking, models a theory into a Euclidean theory; and the Empiricist Programme organises a theory into what he called an empiricist theory – the term was later replaced by “quasi-empirical theory” (Shaffer 2015, p. 5). Therefore, we can see that the classification of a theory as a Euclidean or a quasi-empirical theory is essentially an attempt to explain the epistemology of that theory. The epistemic bedrock of a theory is thus its basic statements, which for a Euclidean theory is the set of axioms and for a quasi-empirical theory is some special theorems.[10] It now becomes clear that the truth-value transmissions possess an epistemic significance for Lakatos. In a Euclidean theory, the axioms receive initially injected truth values True, which establish the truth of the rest of the system. The initial truth-value injection should be non-arbitrary: the axioms need to be indubitably true to be able to justify our beliefs in them and their consequences. A Euclidean theory is thus infallible. While in a quasi-empirical theory, some statements at the bottom of the theory receive initially injected truth values. If the truth value injected is True, it doesn’t flow upwards – it can’t establish the truths of the rest of the system. Only the falsity of the basic statement can establish the falsity of (at least one of) the statements at the above. A quasi-empirical theory is thus fallible. Therefore in a quasi-empirical theory true basic statements are not proved by the rest of the system simply because the rest of the system is not true[11] so they are unable to transfer truth to the basic statements.[12]

To mark the epistemic motivation behind Lakatos’ claim that mathematics is quasi-empirical, I shall call this view of mathematics the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics.

2.2 “Mathematics is Quasi-Empirical”

In the first section of Renaissance, Lakatos lists a number of quotations from philosophers and mathematicians suggesting that the search for a set of infallible self-evident axioms for mathematics had failed; some axioms are justified by the consequences which could not be derived without them. The quotations, Lakatos believes, showed that “mathematical empiricism and inductivism (not only as regards the origin or method, but also regards the justification, of mathematics) is more alive and widespread than many seem to think” (Lakatos 1976, p. 205). In other words, there was a renaissance of empiricism in the philosophy of mathematics. Philosophers of mathematics – for example, Russell, Carnap, Curry and Quine, from whom Lakatos quotes – were having second thoughts on the infallibility of mathematics. Also, a similarity between the justifications for mathematics and natural sciences was observed.

Additionally, in Regress and Renaissance, Lakatos extensively discusses the turn in Bertrand Russell’s views on mathematics. As reported by Lakatos, in the early years of his career, Russell ambitiously took up Frege’s unaccomplished task of founding mathematics on logic (Irvine 1989, p. 306). However, later Russell changed his mind and advocated for a regressive methodology of mathematics (Russell 1907). Russell’s main argument was that some axioms[13] that serve as the foundations of mathematics are not analytic truths. Moreover, Russell claimed that it’s often not the case that people who know the basic arithmetical propositions are able to write out the proofs of them from the logical principles – they may even not know these logical principles (Russell 1907, p. 572). People don’t tend to think that it’s the lengthy proofs from the logical principles to the arithmetical propositions that establish the truths of them: if the logical principles turn out to negate the arithmetical propositions, we are more likely to amend the logical premises rather than the arithmetical propositions (Irvine 1989, p. 308). Therefore, Russell argued that our beliefs in the arithmetical propositions are not justified by the axioms.[14] Russell also observed there is a close analogy between the methodology of mathematics and that of natural sciences. Just like Maxwell’s equations are believed because of the observed truth of their logical consequences, axioms in mathematics are believed on account of their consequences (Lakatos 1962, p. 175).

Similarly, it was observed by Lakatos that the set-theoretical axioms of mathematics that were devised to avoid Russell’s paradoxes are not indubitably true or even indubitably consistent (Lakatos 1976, p. 208). Therefore Lakatos argues that one shouldn’t organise mathematics into a Euclidean theory – instead, he claims that mathematics is quasi-empirical. That is to say, our beliefs in axioms of mathematics are justified by their consequences, which play the role of the basic statements. Axioms are not indubitably true – they are always conjectural. Mathematics is therefore fallible. But this, Lakatos claims, doesn’t commit us to mathematical scepticism, as we only need to admit the fallibility of daring speculations (Lakatos 1962, p. 183), by which he means axioms.

In Renaissance and Regress Lakatos also mentions Hilbert’s program. But it is a bit unclear what Lakatos actually thinks of Hilbert’s program. He classifies it as a Euclidean Programme (Lakatos 1976, p. 209), but he then remarks that “analysis is a quasi-empirical theory but the Euclidean consistency proof will see to it that it should have no falsifiers” (Lakatos 1976, p. 209). Also, in Regress, he characterises Hilbert’s meta-mathematics as an attempt to help mathematics pass the test for consistency as an empiricist theory (Lakatos 1962, p. 179). So it seems that Lakatos doesn’t think that Hilbert’s program can organise mathematics into a Euclidean theory. But then why is it Euclidean itself? An editorial note on (Lakatos 1976, p. 209) sheds some light on the question:

Lakatos is, perhaps, wrong to think that Hilbert’s philosophy, at least as here presented, can be subsumed easily under Euclideanism. Metamathematics is an informal unaxiomatised theory and such theories do not have the required deductive structure to be candidates for Euclidean status.

Therefore, Lakatos may mistakenly think that Hilbert’s program was intended to be a Euclideanisation of meta-mathematics which, if successful, would establish the infallibility of the consistency of mathematics. Unfortunately, its goal was proven to be impossible by Gödel’s incompleteness theorems (at least in Lakatos’ eyes). As a result, the impossibility of establishing the consistency of mathematics provides another source for the fallibility of mathematics.

3 Potential Falsifiers for Mathematics

For Lakatos to develop the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics, it is crucial to figure out what the basic statements of mathematics are (Lakatos 1976, p. 202). The basic statements are also known as potential falsifiers as they can provide potential falsifications to the rest of the theory. Although Lakatos doesn’t offer a full account of what potential falsifiers for mathematics are in Renaissance, he claims that there are two kinds: logical falsifiers and heuristic falsifiers. The logical falsifiers are the ones which we test the consistency of a theory against. They are statements of the form p ¬ p , i.e. logical contradictions. If a set of axioms leads to a logical falsifier, then at least one of the axioms would be falsified. The heuristic falsifiers are analogous to the empirical facts in natural sciences. They are the informal theory that is intended to be formalised[15] in mathematics. Nevertheless, Lakatos remarks that heuristic falsifiers don’t necessarily exist for all formal theories in mathematics. Some formal theories, such as group theory, have replaced the informal theories so rapidly that heuristic falsifiers for them are inconceivable (Lakatos 1976, p. 214). But if they exist, the incompatibility – which usually means the contradiction – between heuristic falsifiers and the consequences that some axiom derives falsifies that axiom.

In this section, I discuss both the logical falsifiers and the heuristic falsifiers. I show that (1) the candidates for logical falsifiers don’t always falsify; (2) it is difficult to give a satisfactory account for the epistemic source of the heuristic falsifiers (if they exist), whatever they may be; (3) given both (1) and (2), we should have doubt the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics.

3.1 Logical Falsifiers

Rejecting an axiom which derives a logical contradiction is a commonly accepted practice in mathematics. Most famously, the axiom (schema) of naive comprehension (which states that every property determines a set) was “abandoned” as it leads to Russell’s Paradox. Lakatos also deems consistency an essential property for a theory. Hence, for him, the impossibility to establish the consistency for mathematics (Section 2.2) opens up a source for the fallibility of axioms, for it could be the case that some day mathematicians find that current axioms derive a logical contradiction. Thus he characterised logical contradictions as logical falsifiers which are able to falsify axioms.

Nevertheless, the presence of a logical contradiction in a system doesn’t have to be “fatal”. The above example doesn’t tell the full story of naive comprehension. It wasn’t put to an end by Russell’s Paradox. Although the majority of mathematical community no longer work with the axiom of naive comprehension, there are still mathematicians sticking to it, as Mortensen described, “to retain the full power of the natural comprehension principle (every predicate determines a set), and tolerate a degree of inconsistency in set theory” (Mortensen 2017). After all, apart from Russell’s Paradox, there seems to be no obvious reason why one should reject naive set theory (Mortensen 2017). In order to retain naive comprehension, and to avoid the theory being trivial,[16] these mathematicians give up the logical principle ex contradictione quodlibet (ECQ)[17] which allows anything to be derived from a logical contradiction in their system. A logic which drops (ECQ) from its rules of inference is called a paraconsistent logic. Mathematical theories with paraconsistent logics comprise inconsistent mathematics. Naive comprehension thus can be retained in the inconsistent set theory. It has been proved that there is a classical recapture in the naive set theory formulated with a paraconsistent logic: the main theorems of ordinal and arithmetic can be proved (Weber 2010) and a theory of cardinal numbers can be developed as Cantor’s Theorem is retained (Weber 2012). Besides, the proof of the well-ordering principle and thus the axiom of choice can also be provided (Weber 2010). These results suggest that inconsistent set theory is not only interesting in its own right, but is also a promising theory that is able to provide new insights on foundations of mathematics. Therefore, the axiom of naive comprehension, though leading to a logical “falsifier”, is not sentenced to death as the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics would expect. Quite the opposite, it is vibrantly alive somewhere in mathematics, albeit not be in the mainstream.

The axiom of naive comprehension is not falsified by Russell’s Paradox. The inconsistent theories are not falsified by the logical contradictions within them. Therefore, we shouldn’t describe logical contradictions as falsifiers – a role that logical contradictions don’t have. Certainly we can choose not to work in an inconsistent theory as probably most mathematicians do. But such choices shouldn’t be pictured as falsifications. To say that inconsistent theories are falsified ignores the values behind inconsistent theories and disregards the actual mathematical research.

Two possible objections can be raised at this point. First, Lakatos notes that refutations don’t happen every day for quasi-empirical theories. There are occasional long stagnating periods – the periods when some theory is dominant. During the stagnating periods people tend to forget the fallibility of the axioms (Lakatos 1976, p. 219). One might argue that logical contradictions do impose falsifications to inconsistent theories but the falsifications are currently being ignored because we are in a stagnating period. This objection can be refuted straightaway. Inconsistent theories are by no means dominant in current mathematical research. Nor are the paraconsistent logics. There isn’t any authority of inconsistent theories which prevents people from falsifying them. Therefore it cannot be the case that it is the stagnant periods which keep inconsistent theories from the falsifications by logical contradictions.

The second objection is based on the idea that a falsification doesn’t always lead to a complete abandonment. For example, Newtonian mechanics is falsified but it is in use, since it is convenient to explain many phenomena using Newtonian mechanics. One might argue that for inconsistent theories, similarly, that they are alive because they offer conveniences in some ways. But in essence they are falsified, and they are merely handy substitutions for some other not-yet-falsified consistent theories, or for better consistent theories to be proposed in the future. That is to say, eventually mathematicians strive for consistency; an inconsistent theory is only present when there is no better alternative consistent theory. Although it is hardly the case for the inconsistent set theory, this objection does raise an interesting question concerning the motivations and the values of studying inconsistent mathematics in general. To properly address the objection, I briefly discuss inconsistent mathematics.

There are in fact many motivations for studying inconsistent theories. For example, Priest believes that the existence of semantic paradoxes such as the Liar Paradox suggests that our linguistic principles are inconsistent. Also, it is natural to have the phrases like “… is true” in human’s languages, i.e. “inconsistency is the natural outcome of spontaneity” (Priest 2006, p. 5, p. 6). Thus, instead of striving for consistency by amending our linguistic principles, it may be more favourable to resolve the paradoxes with paraconsistent logics. Besides, the idea of relevance that a correct natural entailment should rest on the conceptual connections between the antecedent and the consequence casts suspicion on (ECQ) and provides a reason in favour of paraconsistent logics (Mortensen 1995). Moreover, Mortensen suggests that the epistemic limit of finite humans and computers and the time limit for a machine to familiarise itself with the environment give rise to a possibly inconsistent database to reason with.[18] In such inconsistent data environments, the rule (ECQ) should be abandoned for it allows us to derive everything. Mortensen believes that “the study of inconsistent theories is indicated as part of the long-term goal of artificial intelligence” (Mortensen 1995, p. 9).

Inconsistent theories in mathematics other than the inconsistent set theory are also of research value. Here I briefly present one example of them: inconsistent arithmetics. The relevant arithmetic R#, which is basically Peano arithmetic formulated with the relevance logic, can be shown to have a non-trivial model with only finistic methods in Hilbert’s sense (Meyer and Mortensen 1984, p. 919). Meyer believes that this result provides a way to revive Hilbert’s program: the relevant arithmetic distinguishes negation inconsistency[19] from triviality while Peano arithmetic doesn’t, though R# cannot prove its negation consistency as a result of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, its non-triviality can nevertheless be established in a finistic way. Besides, there are a series of non-trivial models of R#. These models are called RM3 i where three represents that there are three truth-values, and the domains of RM3 i are modulo arithmetics with modulo i (i is a natural number). RM3 i was proven to have be inconsistent for every i (Meyer and Mortensen 1984, p. 919). They provide inconsistent models for R#, which comprise inconsistent arithmetics. They are interesting in their own rights (their properties were explored in Meyer and Mortensen 1984) and they have triggered some philosophical discussions. For instance, Priest[20] raises the question of which arithmetic – Peano classical arithmetic or one of the inconsistent arithmetics – is the correct arithmetic? Priest points out that anything that the classical Peano arithmetic endorses, inconsistent arithmetics endorse. So advocates of consistent arithmetic must provide reasons why consistency is good, which he suggests are lacking. The question becomes more interesting as inconsistent arithmetics can be desirable in some respect. For instance, every RM3 i is decidable (Meyer and Mortensen 1984, p. 920); and inconsistent arithmetics can contain their own truth predicates without running into any problem (Priest 2006, p. 236).

Besides inconsistent arithmetics, there are inconsistent theories in various other fields of mathematics: calculus, topology, category theory, etc.[21] But I think the example of inconsistent arithmetics itself suffices to show the point that inconsistent theories have intrinsic value in their inconsistency. It is not the case that inconsistent theories are only present since there is no better alternative consistent theory, nor is it the case that consistency always outweighs inconsistency. The second objection raised above is hence refuted. Therefore, to re-state the interim conclusion, logical contradictions don’t always falsify. The quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics makes a too strong claim that logical contradictions are falsifiers.

In addition, the “birth processes” of the two inconsistent theories discussed above don’t seem to match the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics. The truth-value flows are top-down, as in the Euclidean theories. But what is different is that mathematicians don’t seem to be troubled with dubitable truth-value injections at the top. The naive comprehension is in some theory true (inconsistent set theory) and in some theory not true (for example, ZFC). But that doesn’t stop some mathematicians from using it to transmit truth-values downwards. Remember that the indubitability of axioms is required for the epistemological account of mathematics (Section 2.1). The examples in this subsection indicate that the truth-value injection and transmission in mathematics don’t necessarily carry epistemic weight, which I will argue in details in the later part of this paper.

3.2 Heuristic Falsifiers

Although Lakatos doesn’t offer a definite account of which mathematical propositions are heuristic falsifiers in Renaissance, our discussion is not hampered, since the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics can be refuted without considering what heuristic falsifiers for mathematics exactly are, if they exist at all. This is because, as I will show, no matter what they are, the epistemic priorities assigned to them by the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics do not conform to mathematical practices.

Heuristic falsifiers of mathematics are essentially mathematical statements which play the role of empirical facts in natural sciences. Suppose that they do exist for a mathematical theory, then, first of all, axioms are tested against heuristic falsifiers. Secondly, axioms are supposed to explain them. Thirdly, the quasi-empirical epistemology requires an epistemic source for the truth-value injections to the heuristic falsifiers. This is because, as remarked earlier, the heuristic falsifiers are the epistemic bedrock for mathematics according to the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics (Section 2.1). Hence their truth-value injections must be epistemically justified. I hereby call the source where the epistemic justifications for the truth-value injections to heuristic falsifiers come from the epistemic source for heuristic falsifiers. In Renaissance, Lakatos points out that one question for the quasi-empirical epistemology to settle is that: “what is the ‘nature’ of mathematics, that is, on what basis are truth-values injected into its potential falsifiers?” (Lakatos 1976, p. 218). The question concerns exactly the epistemic sources for the potential falsifiers. Finally, as when testing axioms against heuristic falsifiers, we test axioms indirectly against the epistemic sources for heuristic falsifiers, the epistemic sources for them should also act just like heuristic falsifiers for mathematics in this respect. That is to say, epistemic sources for heuristic falsifiers should also be able to provide falsifications.

In this subsection, I show that there can be no satisfactory epistemic source for any mathematical statements that supports them to be heuristic falsifiers. I do so by discussing two kinds of epistemic sources: intuition and empirical experience. This is because these are the two primary epistemic sources. A piece of knowledge comes either from experience or not. If it doesn’t come from experience, nor is it an analytic truth,[22] then we must know it by some kind of intuition. I argue in the rest of this subsection that neither intuition nor experience is able to support heuristic falsifiers in fulfilling the above expectations that the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics has for them.

3.2.1 Intuition

Mathematical intuition, roughly speaking, refers to the ability of people to perceive mathematical objects or mathematical truths, if they exist at all. It is a controversial issue that whether intuition is a reliable epistemic source for mathematics. On the one hand, there is no consensus on what is mathematically intuitive. Mathematical intuition varies from mathematician to mathematician. Intuition is different from perception in this respect as people may find differences in what they perceive but there is a general consensus on what is being perceived. Moreover, we don’t even know what mathematical intuition exactly is and how we come to have mathematical intuition.[23] Hence there can hardly be universal agreement on whether a given mathematical statement is justified by intuition. Thirdly, intuition is in many cases unsatisfactory support to a mathematical statement. The intermediate value theorem, which says that for any continuous function defined on the interval [a, b] and for any r between f(a) and f(b), there must be some c in [a, b] such that f(c) = r, was once accepted for being intuitive and required no proof. However, mathematicians are not content with just “being intuitive”. Later with the development of mathematical analysis, a purely analytical proof for the intermediate value theorem was given, based on the rigorous definition of continuity. Appeals to intuition will finally give way to rigorous proofs (Linnebo 2017, p. 22). Therefore, mathematical intuition isn’t a strong enough epistemic source to inject truth-values to mathematical statements.

More importantly, mathematicians sometimes choose to modify their intuition rather than giving up their theory. For example,[24] when the formal definition of the real number system was first laid down by Weierstrass and his contemporaries, it was once a disastrous fact to them that their definition led to the conclusion that there exist continuous functions which are nowhere differentiable. However, instead of giving up the definition of the real number system that they laid down, mathematicians decided to accept the consequence and modify their intuitions (Davies 2005). As a result, intuition changes. Nowadays the existence of a continuous but nowhere differentiable function is no longer problematic, as modern mathematical analysis has been part of the standard university mathematics curriculum for a long time. In light of this example, we can see that intuition is not a strong enough source for mathematical statements to be tested against it. Therefore, intuition cannot support any mathematical statements to be heuristic falsifiers.

3.2.2 Experience

Empirical experience is another possible epistemic source for heuristic falsifiers of mathematical statements. Lakatos explicitly indicates that he doesn’t think that mathematics is empirical (Lakatos 1976, p. 213), and the Millian empirical attitude towards mathematics has already received heavy attacks from Frege (1953). However, there is still an attempt to found mathematics epistemically by empirical experience in an indirect way, namely Quine’s naturalism. In Quine’s view, there is no distinction between being analytic and being synthetic, hence mathematics and physics are not separable in this respect. Also, he believes that no statement can be tested alone, a theory is always tested as a whole as the testable consequences are drawn from premises from various parts of the theory as a whole (Quine 2004). Hence mathematics gets tested ultimately by empirical experience. It might be suggested that some mathematical statements are justified epistemically by experience through an intermediary – natural sciences (as many statements in natural sciences, especially physics, are based upon mathematical premises) – and play the role of heuristic falsifiers.[25] However, even in this way, experience still can’t be a satisfactory epistemic source for mathematical statements to be heuristic falsifiers in Lakatos’ quasi-empirical epistemology. Firstly, under Quine’s naturalism, the truth-values that mathematical statements receive are always open to falsifications (although such falsifications would be very unwelcome as mathematics is posited in the deep inside of the totality of knowledge). But how can we say that experience offers mathematical statements an epistemic source while the basic mathematical statements are not even true? Secondly, given naturalism combined with the quasi-empirical epistemology, mathematics would be too limited, for mathematics would then be primarily about explaining the part of it that is employed by natural sciences. Thirdly, in Quine’s naturalist account of mathematics, mathematical statements are open to falsifications from natural sciences. However, in the actual practice, natural sciences are not capable of falsifying mathematics. For instance, Euclidean geometry is not refuted by the general theory of relativity, it is still a legitimate theory of mathematics which is studied by mathematicians on its own right.[26] Moreover, I believe that not only Quine’s naturalist account of mathematics, but any attempt to found mathematics on experience cannot be satisfactory for the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics. This is because that experience itself cannot play the role of falsifiers for mathematics at the first place, since we don’t test mathematics against experience. Therefore, the discussion of Quine’s naturalism of mathematics alone suffices for our purpose here.

Therefore, experience cannot support mathematical statements being heuristic falsifiers. As both intuition and experience cannot be the epistemic source of mathematical heuristic falsifiers, I argue that there can’t be any heuristic falsifier in mathematics.

3.3 Mathematics is not Quasi-Empirical

Given that (1) logical contradictions don’t always falsify, and (2) there can’t be any heuristic falsifier in mathematics, then the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics is not correct. As the above analysis shows, the problem for the quasi-empirical epistemology – or, more generally, for Lakatos’ classification of mathematics into Euclidean theories and quasi-empirical theories in the first place – is that the epistemic requirement on the truth-value injections and truth-value flows in mathematics is too strict. Lakatos requires indubitable initially-injected truth-values for axioms in a Euclidean theory since he wants to stop the infinite regress in proofs and to account for the epistemology of the theory (Section 2.1). And since set-theoretical axioms are not indubitably true and they don’t seem to have initially-injected truth-values, Lakatos rejects the Euclidean picture of mathematics and argues for the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics. He argues that the statements at the bottom of mathematics are epistemically prior to axioms – they receive initial truth-value injections. Then the epistemological question for mathematical axioms – i.e. how do we come to know mathematical axioms? – is transferred to basic statements at the bottom. But as Section 3.2 shows, the question “how do we know mathematical basic statements?” is by no means easier to answer, since there isn’t a satisfactory epistemic source which can support any basic statement founding all of mathematics.

The above arguments indicate that the truth-value injections in mathematics don’t always come together with adequate epistemic justifications since there may not be any. Hence the truth-value flows don’t have to start with epistemically justified propositions to transmit truth. A mathematical theory can start with non-indubitable (fallible) axioms at the top (such as the inconsistent set theory in Section 3.1) or with non-falsifying statements at the bottom. The quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics does capture the idea of extrinsic justifications for axioms in mathematics. But attaching epistemic values to these justifications and viewing them as the only kind of justifications in mathematics cause problems.

Lakatos himself also notices the problem of the quasi-empirical epistemology as he writes in Renaissance:

A heuristic falsifier after all is a falsifier only in a Pickwickian sense: it does not falsify the hypothesis, it only suggests a falsification – and suggestions can be ignored. It is only a rival hypothesis …… The crucial role of heuristic refutations is to shift problems to more important ones, to stimulate the development of theoretical frameworks with more content. One can show of most classical refutations in the history of science and mathematics that they are heuristic falsifications. The battle between rival mathematical theories is most frequently decided also by their relative explanatory power.

Lakatos observes that, even if there is a heuristic falsifier at all for a theory, it doesn’t have to falsify. Since a falsification is essentially a rival hypothesis, people usually choose between the rival between hypotheses on the basis of their “relative explanatory power”. A similar remark of Lakatos can be found in Lakatos (1978, p. 155). It seems that Lakatos might have questioned his quasi-empirical epistemology after he proposed it, so he later shifted to a different view of mathematics[27] where mathematical theories are compared and selected based on their explanatory power. But we don’t really need to choose a theory at the cost of another as the co-existence of inconsistent set theory and ZFC and the co-existence of Euclidean geometry and non-Euclidean geometries shows that there doesn’t have to be. The evidence in this section suggests a more liberal picture of mathematics, which I explain in the next section.

4 Mathematical Pluralism

Given that the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics fails, what should the correct picture of mathematics be? To answer this question, I would like to first summarise our discussion on inconsistent mathematics (Section 3.1). First, we observe that there are (very broadly) two different views towards the axiom schema of naive comprehension. The majority of mathematicians no longer work with it because it derives Russell’s Paradox. But there is still inconsistent set theory which retains the naive comprehension. Therefore we can see that different – even incompatible – theories co-exist in mathematics. Secondly, unlike some axioms in ZFC (for example, the axiom of choice), mathematicians accept the naive comprehension in the naive set theory not because of its consequence. Quite the other way round: the naive set theory is “adjusted” by dropping (ECQ), in order to retain the naive comprehension. Hence the acceptance of the naive comprehension is not justified extrinsically. It is also not indubitably true. It seems that there is no epistemic justification for our belief in the naive comprehension. The justification is, at best, pragmatic, or in other words, serving some mathematicians’ interests. Thirdly, there are various motivations for studying inconsistent theories of mathematics. None of which seems to be able to provide epistemic justifications for our belief in the theories. Instead, they stem from mathematicians’ own interests and beliefs. And the reasons why mathematicians accept and work in such theories are primarily these motivations.

The observations made above suggest that epistemic justifications are in fact not necessary for one to introduce or accept a mathematical system.[28] The justification is instead pragmatic, and is based on one’s motivation. The motivations can be different, even incompatible. Therefore, there can be a plurality of different but equally legitimate systems co-existing in mathematics, which serve different mathematical interests and motivations. Mathematical truths, therefore, are stipulated within specific mathematical systems for pragmatic reasons. The truth-value injections of mathematical statements are thus pragmatic. And the truth-value injections and transmissions only establish the truth values of the statements relative to the system. The justifications of mathematical statements by intuition and experience are not strong enough to be epistemic (Section 3.2), but they can always be pragmatic. And the pragmatic justifications can be injected either to the top or the bottom of the theory. That is to say, both intrinsic justifications and extrinsic justifications can be explained as pragmatic.

As remarked above, the introduction of mathematical systems depends heavily on mathematicians’ own interests and motivations. Mathematicians are willing to work in a “strange-looking” system if that serves their interests (for example, inconsistent mathematics). And there is no standard for mathematicians’ motivations and interests. Just as Carnap stated in (Carnap 2001): “In logic, there are no morals. Everyone is at liberty to build up his own logic.” (p. 52), everyone is at liberty to build up their own system. That said, it doesn’t imply that any system goes as mathematics. Adequate pragmatic justifications must be provided by mathematicians to introduce a system to mathematics which illustrate their motivations and interests. Otherwise the motivations cannot be appreciated and shared by other mathematicians for them to work on it as well. But then one might raise the question: what is the standard for adequate pragmatic justifications? My answer is that there may even be no such standard. The acceptance of a system in mathematics depends heavily on mathematicians’ interests and motivations. And we simply cannot set a standard for one’s interests and motivations – there are no morals for them. Also, even if we can summarise current mathematical interests, we cannot predict what future mathematicians might be interested in. People before the nineteenth century who were educated under the massive influence of Euclid’s Elements would probably not imagine that there will be mathematicians working on non-Euclidean geometries. We can see that with the development of mathematics, human minds have continuously been stretched. And we can’t anticipate what future mathematicians will be interested in, and their motivations will be closely intertwined with the future advancements in mathematics and other subjects. So it might be wiser for us to refrain from setting a standard for pragmatic justifications. And the lack of such standard won’t cause chaos to mathematics. At the end of the day it is mathematicians who decide to work with some system or not. If a system is of no one’s interests at all, then there will hardly be any mathematicians doing serious research on it and such research won’t be appreciated by the mathematical community.[29] Therefore I don’t think that we need to worry that there will be “too much mathematics”.

I don’t aim to provide a full account of mathematical pluralism in this paper. Further work is obviously required to flesh out the full description of the mathematical pluralism and pragmatic justifications for mathematics. But I do argue that the case study of inconsistent mathematics and the arguments in Section 3.2 show that we should be pluralists about mathematics. It can be misleading to seek epistemic justifications for mathematical statements. The correct picture of mathematics should be pluralistic in the sense delineated above. The justifications in mathematics are pragmatic. Instead of asking the question “how do we know this mathematical proposition?”, one should be concerned with “for what pragmatic reasons do we accept some mathematical system?”. At the end of Regress, Lakatos writes: “Why not honestly admit mathematical fallibility, and try to defend the dignity of fallible knowledge from cynical scepticism?” (Lakatos 1962, p. 184). I hereby claim: why not honestly admit mathematical pluralism, and try to defend the dignity of pragmatic justifications of mathematical systems?

5 Conclusions

To conclude, I argue that the quasi-empirical epistemology proposed by Lakatos in Renaissance is incorrect since the falsifying power and the epistemic values it assigns to falsifiers cannot be satisfied by any statement. In particular, inconsistent mathematics is a compelling counterexample to the quasi-empirical epistemology of mathematics, which shows that the justifications for mathematical theories are pragmatic, not epistemic. Consequently there can be different, even incompatible, theories co-existing in mathematics. Therefore I argue that we should take a more liberal view towards mathematics – i.e. the mathematical pluralism.


Corresponding author: Ellen Yunjie Shi, Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California Irvine, Irvine, USA, E-mail:

Acknowledgement

I would like to thank Wesley Wrigley for his patient supervision during the Masterclass and his extremely helpful comments on the early drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank the two anonymous reviewers of this paper whose reviews greatly helped in the revision processes. Finally, I am grateful to Deniz Sarikaya, Sophie Nagler and Hannah Pillin for organising the Lakatos’ Undone Work Masterclass.

References

Carnap, R. 2001. Logical Syntax of Language. London: Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Davies, E. B. 2005. “A Defence of Mathematical Pluralism.” Philosophia Mathematica 13 (3): 252–76, https://doi.org/10.1093/philmat/nki017.Search in Google Scholar

Frege, G. 1953. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Gödel, K. 1964. “What is Cantor’s Continuum Problem?” In Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, edited by P. Benacerraf, and H. Putnam, 470–86. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139171519.025Search in Google Scholar

Irvine, A. D. 1989. “Epistemic Logicism & Russell’s Regressive Method.” Philosophical Studies 55 (3): 303–27, https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00355328.Search in Google Scholar

Koetsier, T. 1991. Lakatos’ Philosophy of Mathematics: A Historical Approach. North Holland: Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co.Search in Google Scholar

Lakatos, I. 1962. “Infinite Regress and Foundations of Mathematics.” In Symposium: The Foundations of Mathematics. Supplementary Volume – Aristotelian Society, Vol. 36, 155–84. Oxford: Oxford University Press on behalf of The Aristotelian Society.10.1017/CBO9780511624926.002Search in Google Scholar

Lakatos, I. 1976. “A Renaissance of Empiricism in the Recent Philosophy of Mathematics.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (3): 201–23, https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/27.3.201.Search in Google Scholar

Lakatos, I. 1978. “Cauchy and the Continuum.” The Mathematical Intelligencer 1: 151–61, https://doi.org/10.1007/bf03023263.Search in Google Scholar

Lakatos, I. 2015. In Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical Discovery, edited by J. Worrall, and E. Zahar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781316286425Search in Google Scholar

Linnebo, Ø. 2017. Philosophy of Mathematics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Maddy, P. 1992. Realism in Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/019824035X.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Martin, D. A. 2005. “Gödel’s Conceptual Realism.” The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2): 207–24, https://doi.org/10.2178/bsl/1120231631.Search in Google Scholar

Meyer, R. K., and C. Mortensen. 1984. “Inconsistent Models for Relevant Arithmetics.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (3): 917–29, https://doi.org/10.2307/2274145.Search in Google Scholar

Mortensen, C. 1995. Inconsistent Mathematics. Kluwer Mathematics and its Applications Series. Dordrecht: Kluwer.10.1007/978-94-015-8453-1Search in Google Scholar

Mortensen, C. 2017. “Inconsistent Mathematics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017), edited by E. N. Zalta. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Also available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/mathematics-inconsistent/.10.1007/978-94-015-8453-1Search in Google Scholar

Parsons, C. 1980. “Mathematical Intuition.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80 (1): 145–68, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/80.1.145.Search in Google Scholar

Priest, G. 2006. In Contradiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199263301.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Priest, G., K. Tanaka, and Z. Weber. 2018. “Paraconsistent Logic.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018), edited by E. N. Zalta. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Also available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/logic-paraconsistent/.Search in Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. O. 2004. Quintessence: Basic Readings from the Philosophy of W. V. Quine. Cambridge, London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Russell, B. A. W. 1907. “The Regressive Method of Discovering the Premisesof Mathematics.” In Essays in Analysis, edited by D. Lackey, 272–83. London: George Allen Unwin, 1973.Search in Google Scholar

Shaffer, M. J. 2015. “Lakatos’ Quasi-Empiricism in the Philosophy of Mathematics.” Polish Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 71–80, https://doi.org/10.5840/pjphil20159211.Search in Google Scholar

Weber, Z. 2010. “Transfinite Numbers in Paraconsistent Set Theory.” The Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1): 71–92, https://doi.org/10.1017/s1755020309990281.Search in Google Scholar

Weber, Z. 2012. “Transfinite Cardinals in Paraconsistent Set Theory.” The Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2): 269–93, https://doi.org/10.1017/s1755020312000019.Search in Google Scholar

Published Online: 2022-01-12

© 2021 Ellen Yunjie Shi, published by De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 24.4.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/krt-2021-0029/html
Scroll to top button