Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T05:47:22.714Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 June 2010

Roger A. Shiner
Affiliation:
University of Alberta

Extract

Bogen has written an excellent book, packed with sensible and suggestive things about Wittgenstein's philosophy of language and about the problems that exercised him. Bogen treads successfully a narrow ridge few others have been able to tread. He has a very clear grasp of what both the earlier and the later Wittgenstein were up to, but he can stand back from Wittgenstein's work and present a lucid and dispassionate account of its philosophical strengths and weaknesses. He is not the kind of unsympathetic and unilluminating critic who regards the Wittgensteinian corpus as aphoristic, obscure and disorganized trivia. Nor is he the kind of acolyte who regards it as sufficient simply to refer his colleagues to the appropriate section of the Investigationswithout further explanation. Whatever thesis Bogen wants to find in Wittgenstein he documents fairly and carefully. Whatever view held by Wittgenstein Bogen wants to regard as penetrating or (even) correct, he usually defends himself independently of its being Wittgenstein's view and also of Wittgenstein's own arguments. Bogen also, in true Wittgensteinian fashion, makes throughout the book masterly use of the happy example. The net result is a book which can be read most profitably both by those interested in Wittgenstein and by those interested in the philosophy of language.

Type
Critical Notices/Études critiques
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1973

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M.An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Tractatus, Third Edition (London, Hutchinson, 1967).Google Scholar
Bambrough, J. R.Universals and Family Resemblances,” Proc. of Arist. Soc. LXI (1960–61), 207–22.Google Scholar
Bambrough, J. R.Principia Metaphysica,” Philosophy, XXXIX (1964), 97109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bambrough, J. R.Unanswerable Questions,” Arist. Soc. Suppl., Vol. XL (1966), 151172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bambrough, J. R.Objectivity and Objects,” Proc. of Arist. Soc. LXXII (1971–72), 6581.Google Scholar
Cowan, J. L.Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Logic,” Phil. Review LXX (1961), 362–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dilman, I.Induction and Deduction (Oxford, Blackwell, 1973).Google Scholar
Dummett, M.Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics,” Phil. Review. LXVIII (1959), 324–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fann, K. T.Wittgenstein's Conception of Philosophy (Oxford, Blackwell, 1969).Google Scholar
Griffin, J.Wittgenstein's Logical Atomism (Seattle, Washington U. P., 1969)Google Scholar
Newell, R. W.The Concept of Philosophy, (London, Methuen, 1967).Google Scholar
Pears, D. F.Wittgenstein, (London, Collins-Fontana, 1971).Google Scholar
Pitcher, G.The Philosophy of Wittgenstein (Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall, 1964).Google Scholar
Specht, E. K.The Foundations of Wittgenstein's Late Philosophy (Manchester, Manchester U.P., 1967).Google Scholar
Stroud, B.Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity,” Phil. Review LXXIV (1965), 504–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wisdom, J.Paradox and Discovery, (Oxford, Blackwell, 1965).Google Scholar