Skip to main content

Husserl and Leibniz: Notes on the Mathesis Universalis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 614 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 384))

Abstract

The notion of mathesis universalis appears in many of Edmund Husserl’s works, where it corresponds essentially to “a universal a priori ontology”. This paper has two purposes; one, largely exegetical, of clarifying how Husserl elaborates on Leibniz’ concept of mathesis universalis and associated notions like symbolic thinking and symbolic knowledge filtering them through the lesson of the so called “bohemian Leibniz”, Bernard Bolzano; another, more properly philosophical, of examining the role that the universal mathesis is allowed to play, and the space it occupies in Husserl’s intuition-based epistemology.

[L]a bonne caractéristique est.

une des plus grandes aides

de l’esprit humain ([A] good symbolism

is one the greatest aids to the human mind

Leibniz, N.E. IV, Ch.7, § 6)

[O]hne die Möglichkeit symbolischer […] Vorstellungen

gäbe es kein höheres Geistesleben, geschweige denn eine Wissenschaft

([W]ithout the possibility of symbolic representations […]

there would not exist a higher spiritual life, and even less science

Husserl, Zur Logik der Zeichen, PdA 349)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cp. Piccolomini’s Commentarium de certitudine mathematicarum (1547), ch. 7; Dasypodius’ mathematical writings (1564a, b, 1571, 1593); van Roomen’s Apologia pro Archimede (1597). All these Authors, except for van Roomen, refer to Proclus’ Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements, especially to the first prologue of the Commentary, which deals with the mathematical sciences in general. In Proclo’s commentary there are many hints at a common mathematical discipline that shall precede all other mathematical disciplines and has, therefore, a more general character. Crapulli 1969 offers a very interesting investigation about the development of the idea of the mathesis in the XVI century.

  2. 2.

    Before Descartes and Leibniz there were mainly two criteria for gathering together mathematical disciplines, namely, that they all had, in some way, quantity as their object (think of the disciplines traditionally unified in the Quadrivium) and an higher degree of certitude in proofs with respect to non-mathematical disciplines.

  3. 3.

    Descartes Rule IV, AT.X, 372–379, here 374f. Actually it is a recurrent theme by Descartes that “all sciences are concatenated”, “that it is much more easier to apprehend them all together, then to separate one of them from the others” and focus solely on a unique one (Rule I, AT.X, 361). Hereto also cp. AT.X, 255: “[one single science] cannot be brought to perfection, without doing the same with the others”. Responsibility for translations from German, French and Latin is ours, even when we refer to, benefit from, or simply echo published translations.

  4. 4.

    AT.X, 376.

  5. 5.

    Pappus of Alexandria (290–350 c. AD) and Diophantus of Alexandria (201/215(?)-285–299(?) AD) were Alexandrian Greek Mathematicians.

  6. 6.

    AT.X, 378.

  7. 7.

    loc. cit.

  8. 8.

    loc. cit.

  9. 9.

    AT.X, 378–379.

  10. 10.

    Descartes 1954.

  11. 11.

    Gerolamo Cardano (1501–1576) was an Italian mathematician, physicians and astrologers. He occupies an important place in the history of Renaissance philosophy. He wrote more than 200 works in the most disparate fields, but especially, mathematics, medicine, philosophy and astrology. Among his works we remember his Artis magnae sive de regulis algebraicis liber unus (1545), commonly known as Ars magna, that draws the anger of Nicolò Tartaglia for having published the solution of third degree equations revealed to him by Tartaglia 6 years earlier, though under oath, not to reveal it.

  12. 12.

    Scipione del Ferro (1465–1596) was an Italian mathematician who first discovered a method to solve the depressed cubic equations.

  13. 13.

    Niccolo Fontana Tartaglia (1499/1500–1557) was an Italian mathematician famous for having been the first to translate Euclid and Archimedes into Italian as well as for his controversy with Cardano as to the solution of cubic equations.

  14. 14.

    Raphael Bombelli (1526–1572) was an Italian mathematician. He is Author on a treatise on algebra (1572) and gave important contributions in the understanding of imaginary numbers.

  15. 15.

    Cardano 2007.

  16. 16.

    Descartes 1954.

  17. 17.

    See Nahin 1998.

  18. 18.

    Leibniz 1684.

  19. 19.

    Berkeley 1948–57.

  20. 20.

    Bonaventura Cavalieri (1598–1647) was a pupil of Galileo. He developed Galileo’s thoughts into a geometrical method and published in 1635 a work on the subject: Geometria Indivisilibus Continuorum Nova quadam Ratione Promota.

  21. 21.

    Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) is one of the most representative figures in the Renaissance. He was strongly influenced by Copernicus and endorsed the Platonic conception that universe is ordered according to a pre-established mathematical plan. He his Author of many works, among them a Mysterium Cosmographicum (1596) and his Astronomia Nova (1609), in which we find him saying: “The chief aim of all investigations of the external world should be to discover the rational order and harmony which has been imposed on it by God and which He revealed to us in the language of mathematics” quoted after Pearcey & Thaxton 1994, 126.

  22. 22.

    See Mancosu 1996.

  23. 23.

    This comes out clearly in Leibniz’s practice of the calculus he invented, see Leibniz 1684 note 18.

  24. 24.

    Leibniz 1678, quoted after Ariew & Gaber 1989, 236.

  25. 25.

    See Belaval 1960.

  26. 26.

    Leibniz 1684. Henceforth quoted as MED. MED is Leibniz’s first mature philosophical publication. It appeared in November 1684 in the Leipzig Journal Acta Eruditorum as Leibniz’s contribution to the famous Arnauld-Malebranche controversy, triggered by the publication of Arnauld’s Des vrais et des fausses idées in 1683, an attack on Malebranches’s philosophy.

  27. 27.

    Henrich Scholz hypothesizes Trendelenburg as source. See Husserl’s and Scholz’s Anmerkungen in Frege’s 1964.

  28. 28.

    Husserl 1891a.

  29. 29.

    Husserl 1891b.

  30. 30.

    Hereto cp. Chap. 6 in this volume.

  31. 31.

    Husserl, Philosophie der Arithmetik. Mit ergänzenden Texten (1890–1901), HGW XII, 1–283. Henceforth cited as PdA. English translation cited as PoA.

  32. 32.

    Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen II/1 (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 19937). Henceforth cited as LU. English translation cited as LI.

  33. 33.

    Formal and Transcendental Logic [ed. 1929] (henceforth cited as FTL), 49 ff; Engl. transl. 56 ff.

  34. 34.

    Hereto see Centrone 2010b.

  35. 35.

    MED 585–586.

  36. 36.

    Talk of “notio” as well as “nominal definition” below indicates that Leibniz conceives of “notiones” as abstract objects. The question is controversial, for this is against his official position presented in the short essay Quid sit Idea? (Leibniz 1677a), in which he maintains that an idea is a certain power of the mind. With “idea“, he writes there, we mean “something that is in our mind (aliquid, quod in mente nostra est)”: “The idea is [...] not a certain mental act, but rather a power, and thus we say that we have the idea of an object even if we don’t actually think of it but have the ability to do so on any given occasion. (Idea [...] non in quodam cogitandi actu, sed facul- tate consistit, et ideam rei habere dicimur, etsi de ea non cogitemus, modo data occasione de ea cogitare possimus.)” (Ak VI.4B, 1.370).

  37. 37.

    MED 585.

  38. 38.

    The bearer has changed! It is no longer a cognitio!

  39. 39.

    The bearer has changed again!

  40. 40.

    MED 585.

  41. 41.

    MED 585–586 (our emphasis).

  42. 42.

    See e.g. LU I, §20; LI 304–306 (Thought without intuition and the ‘surrogative function’ of signs).

  43. 43.

    NE II, Ch. 9, §§ 8–10; and Ch. 29 that bears the title “Of Clear and Obscure, Distinct and Confused Ideas.”

  44. 44.

    PdA 339; PoA 357.

  45. 45.

    See also Husserl, Zur Logik der Zeichen (Semiotik), in: PdA 340–373. Here PdA p. 349f.

  46. 46.

    Cp. Willard 1984, 26.

  47. 47.

    “To [Brentano] I owe the deeper understanding of the vast significance of inauthentic presentations for our whole mental life; this is something which, so far as I can see, no one before him had grasped” (PdA 193; PoA 205). See also Husserl, Zur Logik der Zeichen (Semiotik): PdA, p. 340.

  48. 48.

    PdA 193; PoA 201–202.

  49. 49.

    LU IV, §45, 144; LI 785–786.

  50. 50.

    PdA 194; PoA 205;

  51. 51.

    PdA 193–194, 237–239; PoA 205–206, 247–240. See also Husserl, Zum Begriff der Operation (On the Concept of Operation), in: PdA 408–429. PoA, 385–408. Here: PdA, p. 418; PoA, p. 395.

  52. 52.

    Leibniz 1666, 5.

  53. 53.

    Leibniz 1677b, in: Ak. IV.4.A, 23–24. Also cp. Leibniz 1688?: “Characterem voco, notam visibilem cogitationes repraesentantem. Ars characteristica est ars ita formandi atque ordinandi characteres, ut referant cogitations, seu ut eam inter se habeant relationem, quam cogitationes inter se habent. Expressio est. aggregatum characterum rem quae exprimitur repraesentantium.”

  54. 54.

    Trendelenburg 1856, 39f.

  55. 55.

    Schröder 1890, 48; 49. Hereto cp. ch. 6, section 4 in this volume.

  56. 56.

    See da Silva 201x.

  57. 57.

    PdA 258; PoA 273 (italics in the original).

  58. 58.

    Husserl, Aufsätze und Rezensionen, 393.

  59. 59.

    loc. cit.

  60. 60.

    Cp. Aristotle, Metaphysics.∆ 5, 1015a 34–36: “We say that that which cannot be otherwise is necessarily as it is. And from this sense of ‘necessary’ all the others are somehow derived.” Cp. Leibniz, Confessio philosophi (Fall 1672-Winter 1672/73): “Impossibile, quod possibile non est. Necessarium cuius oppositum impossibile est., Contingens cuius oppositum possibile est” (Ak VI.3127).

  61. 61.

    Cp. e.g. Generales Inquisitiones de analysi notionum et veritatum (1686): “Necessaria autem proposition est […] cujus oppositam assumendo per resolutionem devenitur in contradictionem” (Ak VI.4A, 761).

  62. 62.

    In De Interpretation 13 he defines “possible” (“endekomenon”, “dunaton”) as “that which is not impossible”, In An. Pr. 13bis and 22 he takes “endekomenon” to mean “neither possible nor impossible”, that is the characterization we usually give nowadays of “contingent”.

  63. 63.

    Cp. Leibniz, Definitiones: ens, possibile, existens (1687–96?) (Ak VI.4A, 867). Also cp. Definitiones: terminus vel aliquid, nihil (1688–89) (Ak VI.4A, 936).

  64. 64.

    See Couturat 1901, 283–322.

  65. 65.

    PoA 277; PdA 262. Hereto cp. Centrone 2010a, 45ff.

  66. 66.

    PR 219–222 (§ 60 Anknüpfungen an Leibniz/ Links with Leibniz), Pre 138–141. Henceforth: PR = Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen I, Prolegomena zur reinen Logik, Tübingen 1993; PRe = English translation thereof, in: Logical Investigations, London 1970, Vol. I, 51–247.

  67. 67.

    loc. cit.

  68. 68.

    loc. cit.

  69. 69.

    LV ‘06/07, 54–55.

  70. 70.

    LV ‘06/07, 91.

  71. 71.

    LV ‘06/07, 104.

  72. 72.

    LV ‘06/07, 376.

  73. 73.

    Ideen I, §7, 16ff. (o.p.).

  74. 74.

    EU 1–2; Engl. transl. 11.

  75. 75.

    FTL 65; Engl. transl. 73–74.

  76. 76.

    FTL 122; Engl. transl. 138.

  77. 77.

    FTL 127; Engl. transl. 143.

  78. 78.

    FTL 123; Engl. transl. 138.

  79. 79.

    Krisis §9 g.

  80. 80.

    Husserl, Das Imaginäre in der Mathematik. I: Zu einem Vortrag in der mathematischen Gesellschaft in Göttingen 1901; in: PdA 430–451; PoA 409–452.

  81. 81.

    See also Drei Studien zur Definitheit und Erweiterung eines Axiomensystems, in: PdA 452–469, PoA 432–438 & 453–464.

  82. 82.

    PdA 430; PoA 409–410.

  83. 83.

    We borrow here terminology from Casari 2004.

  84. 84.

    Webb 1980, xii.

  85. 85.

    Hereto cp. Casari 2004.

  86. 86.

    LV 06/07, 55.

  87. 87.

    loc.cit. (quotation marks added).

  88. 88.

    loc.cit.

  89. 89.

    LV 06/07, 55 (quotation marks added).

  90. 90.

    Cp. LV 06/07, 59 ff.

References

  • Aristotle, The Complete Works, vol. I–II, ed. by J. Barnes (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1984)

    Google Scholar 

  • Y. Belaval, Leibniz Critique de Descartes (Gallimard, Paris, 1960)

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Berkeley, The analist; or a discourse addressed to an infidel mathematician (1734), in A.A. Luce, T.E. Jessop (eds.), The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne, vol. 4. (Nelson, London/Edinburgh, 1948–57), pp. 53–102

    Google Scholar 

  • B. Bolzano, Beyträge zu einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik. Erste Lieferung (Caspar Widtmann, Prague, 1810). Reprint: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt 1974. English translation in S. Russ (ed.), The Mathematical Works of Bernard Bolzano (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2004), pp. 82–137

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Cardano, The Rules of Algebra (Ars Magna) (Dover, Mineola, 2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Casari, Logic and the laws of possible being, in Logic and Metaphysics, ed. by M. Marsonet, M. Benzi (Name, Genova, 2004), pp. 16–43

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Centrone, Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics in the Early Husserl (Springer, Berlin, 2010a)

    Google Scholar 

  • S. Centrone, Bolzano und Leibniz über Klarheit und Deutlichkeit, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. 92(3), 256–289 (2010b)

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Couturat, La Logique de Leibniz: d’après des documents inédits (F. Alcan, Paris, 1901)

    Google Scholar 

  • L. Couturat, Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz (F. Alcan, Paris, 1903)

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Crapulli, Mathesis universalis. Genesi di un’idea nel XVI secolo (Edizioni dell’Ateneo, Roma, 1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • J.J. Da Silva, Away from the facts, symbolic knowledge in Husserl’s philosophy of mathematics, in Symbolic Knowledge from Leibniz to Husserl, Studies in Logic, vol. 41, ed. by A.L. Casanave (College Publications, London, 2012), pp. 115–136

    Google Scholar 

  • J.J. Da Silva, Beyond Leibniz, Husserl’s vindication of symbolic mathematics, in The Road Not Taken, On Husserl’s Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics, ed. by C.O. Hill, J.J. da Silva. (College Publications, London, 2013), pp. 61–80

    Google Scholar 

  • J.J. Da Silva, Husserl and Hilbert on completeness, still, Synthese 201x (online first 16/07/2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Dasypodius, Euclidis quindecim elementorum geometriae primum (C. Mylius, Strasburg, 1564a)

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Dasypodius, Euclidis quindecim elementorum geometriae secondum (C. Mylius, Strasburg, 1564b)

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Dasypodius, Euclidis elementorum liber primus (C. Mylius, Strasburg, 1571)

    Google Scholar 

  • C. Dasypodius, Protheoria Mathematica (Argentorati, Strasburg, 1593)

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Descartes, [AT.X] Oeuvres, vol. X, ed. by C. Adam, P. Tannery (Léopold Cerf, Paris, 1908)

    Google Scholar 

  • R. Descartes, The Geometry of René Descartes, ed. by D.E. Smith, M.L. Lathan (Dover, Mineola, 1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • G. Frege, Begriffsschrift und andere Aufsätze. Mit E. Husserls und H. Scholz’ Anmerkungen, ed. by I. Angelelli (Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt, 1964)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [Krisis] Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie (M. Nijhoof, The Hague, 1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Besprechung von: E. Schröder, Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik, I. Band, Leipzig 1890, Göttingsche gelehrte Anzeigen (1891a), pp. 243–270. English translation in Husserl (1994), pp. 52–91

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Das Folgerungskalkül und die Inhaltslogik, Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie. 15, 168–189 (1891b). English translation in Husserl (1994), pp. 92–114

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [FTL] Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft, Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung X (1929). Critical Edition: Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft, ed. by P. Jannsen, HGW XVII, 1975. English translation: Formal and Transcendental Logic, ed. by D. Cairns (Martinus Nijhoff, Den Haag, 1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, Bd I, [PR] Prolegomena zur reinen Logik, Max Niemeyer, Halle, 1900 (21913); Bd II, [LU] Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Max Niemeyer, Halle a.d.S., 1901 (21913–1921, 71993). English translation: [PRe/LI] Logical Investigations, ed. by J.N. Findlay (Routledge, New York, 1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [EU] Erfahrung und Urteil (Academia Verlagsbuchhandlung, Prag 1939). English translation: Experience and Judgement (Northwestern University Press, Evanston, 1973)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [Ideen] Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung I (1913) [as a separate volume: Niemeyer, Halle a.d.S. 1913; 21922; 31928]. Critical Edition: Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, ed. by K. Schuhmann, HGW III/1 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Aufsätze und Rezensionen (1890–1910), ed. by B. Rang, HGW XXII (1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Briefwechsel, ed. by K. Schuhmann, Husserliana Dokumente vol. III (Kluwer, Dordrecht/Boston/London, 1994a)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics (Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1994b)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, Philosophie der Arithmetik. Logische und psychologische Untersuchungen, Bd. I, Pfeffer, Halle a.d.S. 1891. Critical Edition: [PdA] Philosophie der Arithmetik. Mit ergänzenden Texten (1890–1901), ed. by L. Eley, HGW XII (1970). English translation: [PoA] Philosophy of Arithmetic, Psychological and Logical Investigations with Supplementary Texts from 1887–1901, ed. by D. Willard (Kluwer, Dordrecht, 2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [HGW] Husserliana, Gesammelte Werke, I–XXVI: Martinus Nijhoff, Den Haag, 1950–, XXVII–XXXVII: Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1989–; XXXVIII–, Springer, New York, 2005

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Husserl, [LV’06–07] Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie Vorlesungen 1906/07, ed. by U. Melle, HGW XXIV, 1985. English translation: Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge (Lectures 1906/1907), ed. by C.O. Hill (Springer, Dordrecht, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1666] Dissertatio de Arte Combinatoria, Akademieausgabe VI.1.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999a), pp. 163–230

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [MED] Meditationes de cognitione, veritate et ideis (1684), Akademieausgabe IV.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999b), pp. 585–592

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1672/73] Confessio Philosophi, Akademieausgabe VI.3 (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1981), pp. 115–149

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1677a] Quid sit Idea?, Akademieausgabe VI.4.B (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 1369–1371

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1677b] Dialogus, Akademieausgabe IV.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 20–25

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1678] Leibniz an die Pfalzgräfin Elizabeth (?), Akademieausgabe II.1.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1987), pp. 659–666. English translation: Letter to Countess Elizabeth. On God and Formal Logic, ed. by R. Ariew, D. Garber (Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis/Cambridge, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1683?] Elementa Nova Matheseos Universalis, Akademieausgabe IV.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 513–524

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1686] Generales inquisitiones de analysi notionum et veritatum, ed. by F. Schupp (Meiner, Hamburg, 1982)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1687a] Non inelegans specimen demonstrandi in abstractis, Akademieausgabe IV.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 845–855

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1687b/96?] Definitiones: ens, possibile, existens, Akademieausgabe VI.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 867–870

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1688a?] De Characteribus et de Arte Characteristica, Akademieausgabe IV.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), p. 916

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [1688b–89] Definitiones: terminus vel aliquid, nihil, Akademieausgabe VI.4.A (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1999), pp. 934–936

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, [NE] Nouveaux Essais sur l’entendement humain (1704), Akademieausgabe IV.6 (Akademie Verlag, Berlin, 1962)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, Nova Methodus (1684), ed. by D.J. Struik, A Source Book in Mathematics, 1200–1800 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, Logical Papers, ed. by G.H.R. Parkinson (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • G.W. Leibniz, Die Grundlagen des logischen Kalkuls, ed. by F. Schupp, S. Weber (Meiner, Hamburg, 2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • P. Mancosu, Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice in the Seventeenth Century (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • P.J. Nahin, An Imaginary Tale. The History of √-1 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • N.R. Pearcey, C.B. Thaxton, The Soul of Science (Crossway Books, Wheathon, 1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Piccolomini, Commentarius de certitudine mathematicarum (Antonio Baldum Asulanum, Roma, 1547)

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Schröder, Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik (Exakte Logik), Bd. I, (Teubner, Leipzig, 1890)

    Google Scholar 

  • F.A. Trendelenburg, Über Leibnizens Entwurf einer allgemeinen Charakteristik, Königl (Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin, 1856)

    Google Scholar 

  • A. Van Romen, Apologia pro Archimede (Fleischmann, Würzburg, 1597)

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Webb, Mechanism Mentalism and Metamathematics (Reidel, Dordrecht, 1980)

    Google Scholar 

  • D. Willard, Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge: A Study in Husserl’s Philosophy (Ohio University Press, Athens, 1984)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefania Centrone .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Centrone, S., Da Silva, J.J. (2017). Husserl and Leibniz: Notes on the Mathesis Universalis . In: Centrone, S. (eds) Essays on Husserl's Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol 384. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1132-4_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics