Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T13:13:23.472Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

EUGENICS AND PRAGMATISM: F. C. S. SCHILLER'S PHILOSOPHICAL POLITICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 May 2015

ADMIR SKODO*
Affiliation:
Department of History, University of California, Berkeley E-mail: askodo@berkeley.edu

Abstract

The British philosopher F. C. S. Schiller (1864–1937) was a leading pragmatist in the early twentieth century. His critiques of formal logic and his attempts to construct a humanist logic, derived from an anti-foundationalist humanism, are recognized as lasting philosophical achievements. But scholars have failed to consider that Schiller was passionately committed to the British eugenics movement. This essay explores the relationship between Schiller's pragmatism and his eugenicism. It argues that Schiller represents the broad scope of pragmatism in the early twentieth century through his involvements not only with eugenics, but also with psychical research as well. Underneath Schiller's various undertakings lies a common theme: the self, conceived in voluntaristic, historicist, and concrete terms. By tracing the trajectory of this theme in Schiller's thought, this essay demonstrates that Schiller's eugenicism was confined to the presuppositions of his pragmatist logic, which steered Schiller's eugenicism toward a distinctively nondeterministic and non-social-Darwinist kind.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 White, Stephen Solomon, A Comparison of the Philosophies of F. C. S. Schiller and John Dewey (Chicago, 1940)Google Scholar; McDermid, Douglas, The Varieties of Pragmatism: Truth, Realism, and Knowledge from James to Rorty (London, 2006)Google Scholar; Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko, “Remarks on the Peirce–Schiller Correspondence,” in Oleksy, E. H. and Oleksy, W., eds., Transatlantic Encounters: Philosophy, Media, Politics (Frankfurt am Main, 2011), 6170 Google Scholar; Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America (New York, 2001), 350; Porrovecchio, Mark J., F. C. S. Schiller and the Dawn of Pragmatism (Lanham, MD, 2011).Google Scholar

2 Abel, Reuben, The Pragmatic Humanism of F. C. S. Schiller (New York, 1955), 74 Google Scholar; Putnam, Hilary, Pragmatism: An Open Question (Oxford, 1995), 63.Google Scholar

3 I am modifying the nineteenth-century turn of phrase das Adam Smith Problem, which saw a contradiction between Smith's The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and The Wealth of Nations (1776). Teichgraeber, Richard III, “Rethinking Das Adam Smith Problem,” Journal of British Studies, 20/2 (1981), 106–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Abel, The Pragmatic Humanism of F. C. S. Schiller, 147.

5 Searle, G. R., “Class and Eugenics,” in Webster, Charles, ed., Biology, Medicine and Society 1840–1940 (Cambridge, 1981), 217–43, at 239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Searle, G. R., Eugenics and Politics 1900–1914 (Leiden, 1976), 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S., 200 (1927), US Supreme Court Center, at http://supreme.justia.com/us/274/200/case.html#207, last accessed 1 March 2014.

8 Freeden, Michael, “Eugenics and Progressive Thought: A Study in Ideological Affinity,” Historical Journal, 22/3 (1979), 645–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

9 The Italian pragmatist Giovanni Papini distilled Schiller's contribution to thought in precisely these terms. Schiller's philosophy, wrote Papini, was apposite to the “new spiritual age,” since Schiller had discovered that Protagoras' famous saying—“man is the measure of all things”—alone can capture the logic underlying the radical shifts that society was undergoing in the modern era. Philosophy needed to provide a statement making sense of the fact that natural processes could be “sped up” by science, and that the natural order could be manipulated by the wills and desires of humans using scientific methods. Schiller, according to Papini, provided such a contemporary statement by revealing the “plasticity of speculative organisms,” and the character of truth as “changeable, plastic, dynamic.” See Giovanni Papini, “F. C. S. Schiller,” in Papini, Four and Twenty Minds: Essays by Giovanni Papini, selected and trans. by Ernest Hatch Wilkins (New York, 1922), 82–9, at 87–8, 86, 85.

10 Schiller quoted in Slosson, Edwin E., Six Major Prophets (Boston, 1917), 194.Google Scholar

11 My interpretation does not obviate the casting of pragmatism as a liberal-democratic political philosophy, which grew out of pragmatism's anti-foundationalism and its view of social and political life as an open-ended rational and public inquiry, but it does question the view that pragmatism is inherently liberal-democratic. For liberal-democratic readings of pragmatism, see Shalin, Dmitri N., Pragmatism and Democracy: Studies in History, Social Theory, and Progressive Politics (New Brunswick, 2011)Google Scholar; Dryzek, John, “Pragmatism and Democracy: In Search of Deliberative Publics,” Journal of Speculative Politics, 18/1 (2004), 72–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Knight, Jack and Johnson, James, The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism (Princeton, 2011)Google Scholar; Bernstein, Richard J., The Pragmatic Turn (Cambridge, 2010)Google Scholar; Anderson, Charles W., Pragmatic Liberalism (Chicago, 1994).Google Scholar

12 Noel Annan has shown that Jowett, who was one of the first dons to introduce Hegelian idealism to Britain, was a consummate eccentric. See Annan, Noel, The Dons: Mentors, Eccentrics and Geniuses (London, 1999).Google Scholar

13 I take this concept from the work of Ian Hunter, among others. See Condren, Conal, Gaukroger, Stephen, and Hunter, Ian, eds., The Philosopher in Early Modern Europe: The Nature of a Contested Identity (Cambridge, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 Russell, Bertrand, “Dr Schiller's Analysis of The Analysis of Mind ,” Journal of Philosophy, 19/24 (1922), 645–51Google Scholar, at 651.

15 Timbs, John, English Eccentrics and Eccentricities (London, 1875)Google Scholar—this book came out in new editions until the end of the nineteenth century.

16 Bluemel, Kristin, George Orwell and the Radical Eccentrics: Intermodernism in Literary London (New York, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Childs, Donald J., Modernism and Eugenics: Woolf, Eliot, Yeats, and the Culture of Degeneration (Cambridge, 2004)Google Scholar; Potter, Rachel, Modernism and Democracy: Literary Culture 1900–1930 (Cambridge, 2006)Google Scholar; Winkiel, Laura A., Modernism, Race, and Manifestos (Cambridge, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Skorupski, John quoted in Matar, Anat, Modernism and the Language of Philosophy (London and New York, 2006), 1.Google Scholar

19 Schiller, F. C. S., “Philosophy and the Scientific Investigation of a Future Life,” in Schiller, Humanism: Philosophical Essays (London, 1912), 351–74Google Scholar.

20 Ibid., 368, original emphasis.

21 Rainer Emig, in a study on Carlyle as an eccentric, usefully suggests that the eccentric ought to be understood as on the fringes of conventional society and intellectual traditions, while never transgressing their boundaries. Emig, Rainer, “Eccentricity Begins at Home: Carlyle's Centrality in Victorian Thought,” Textual Studies, 17/2 (2003), 379–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Eccentrics, in other words, were half-hearted in their attacks on conventions. They can thus be viewed as aspiring to save conventions by radically modifying them in light of modernity, rather than replacing them with entirely different kinds of conventions.

22 George J. Stack has made a compelling case for the Nietzschean influence on Schiller concerning this aspect, and indeed very many other aspects, such as an emphasis on the aesthetic, social, and psychic origins of seemingly pure scientific and logical concepts. See Stack, George J., “Nietzsche's Influence on Pragmatic Humanism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 20/4 (1982), 369406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Boucher, David and Vincent, Andrew, British Idealism and Political Theory (Edinburgh, 2000), 5.Google Scholar

24 Bengtsson, Jan-Olof, The Worldview of Personalism (Oxford, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sturt, Henry, ed., Personal Idealism: Philosophical Essays by Eight Members of the University of Oxford (London, 1902)Google Scholar; Howison, George H., The Limits of Evolution: And Other Essays Illustrating the Metaphysical Theory of Evolution, 2nd edn (London, 1904)Google Scholar; Sturt, Henry, The Principles of Understanding: An Introduction to Logic from the Standpoint of Personal Idealism (Cambridge, 1915).Google Scholar

25 Sturt, Henry, Idola Theatri: A Criticism of Oxford Thought and Thinkers from the Standpoint of Personal Idealism (London, 1906).Google Scholar

26 Schiller, F. C. S., “Axioms as Postulates,” in Sturt, Henry, ed., Personal Idealism: Philosophical Essays by Eight Members of the University of Oxford (London, 1902), 47134 Google Scholar.

27 Matar, Modernism, 1.

28 For an intellectual history of British socialism see Mark Bevir, The Making of British Socialism (New Haven, 2011).

29 Schiller, F. C. S., Cassandra or the Future of the British Empire (London, 1926), 34–5.Google Scholar

30 Ibid., 38–9.

31 Ibid., 65–66.

32 Ronald Hyam, “The British Empire in the Edwardian Era,” in Brown, Judith M. and Roger Louis, W. M., eds., The Oxford History of the British Empire , vol. 4, The Twentieth Century (Oxford, 1999), 4764, 48Google ScholarPubMed

33 Schiller, F. C. S., Eugenics and Politics: Essays by Ferdinand Canning Scott Schiller (London, 1926), 13.Google Scholar

34 See e.g. Freeden, Michael, Liberal Languages: Ideological Imaginations and Twentieth-Century Progressive Thought (New Haven, 2005)Google Scholar, especially chaps. 1 through 7.

35 There were many differences, even on the strictly scientific level: Donald Mackenzie, “Sociobiologies in Competition: The Biometrician–Mendelian Debate,” in Charles Webster, ed., Biology, Medicine and Society 1840–1940 (Cambridge, 1981), 243–89, at 262.

36 The “fit and unfit biological stocks” were, typically, conceptually rendered in an incoherent hierarchy comprising, from the bottom up, African, Asian, and European races. The European race, in turn, was typically divided into its own national hierarchy, where the nation to which the eugenicist who was constructing the hierarchy happened to belong came out on top: Britain if the eugenicist was British (and English if he was English), German if he was German, and so on. Within the nation, a hierarchy was constructed typically comprising, again from the bottom up, the physically “degenerate,” the “feeble-minded,” the urban working classes, the middle classes, and the aristocracy.

37 Searle, Eugenics, 27.

38 Schiller, F. C. S, Riddles of the Sphinx: A Study in the Philosophy of Humanism (London, 1910), 114 Google Scholar, see also 225.

39 Stone, Dan, “Race in British Eugenics,” European Quarterly History, 31/3 (2001), 397425.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

40 Searle, G. R., The Quest for National Efficiency: A Study in British Politics and Political Thought, 1899–1914 (Berkeley, 1971).Google Scholar

41 Stocker quoted in “Review of Social Idealism,” Eugenics Review, 2/4 (1911), 328.

42 See the essays in Charles Webster, ed., Biology, Medicine and Society 1840–1940 (Cambridge, 1981).

43 Schiller, Eugenics, 1.

44 Ibid., 207.

45 Fox, Evelyn, “The Mental Deficiency Act and Its Administration,” Eugenics Review, 10/1 (1918), 117.Google Scholar

46 Freeden, “Eugenics,” 666–7.

47 Schiller, F. C. S., “Preface,” in Murray, D. L., Pragmatism (London, 1912), viix, at vii–ix.Google Scholar

48 Schiller, Humanism, ix.

49 Abel, The Pragmatic Humanism of F. C. S. Schiller; McDermid, The Varieties of Pragmatism; Pietarinen, “Remarks”; Putnam, Pragmatism; John R. Shook, “F. C. S. Schiller and European Pragmatism,” in John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis, eds., A Companion to Pragmatism (Oxford, 2006), 44–54; Richard Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis, 1982).

50 Schiller, F. C. S., Formal Logic: A Scientific and Social Problem (London, 1912).Google Scholar

51 See e.g. Dewey, John, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (New York, 1939)Google Scholar. For a critical exposition of Dewey's logic see Thayer, H. S., The Logic of Pragmatism: An Examination of John Dewey's Logic (New York, 1952).Google Scholar

52 Passmore, John, A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London, 1966)Google Scholar, in particular chap. 7: “Some Critics of Formal Logic,” at 156–73.

53 For different meanings attached to humanism and pragmatism, and the connections between them, see the chapter entitled “Pragmatic Humanism” in Martin Halliwell and Andy Mousley, Critical Humanisms: Humanist/Anti-Humanist Dialogues (Edinburgh, 2003), 139–59. The term “humanism” entered the British lexicon in the early nineteenth century. By the early twentieth century, it had taken a broad range of meanings, with ties to various belief systems. For example, there were advocates of “Christian humanism” (e.g. J. H. Oldham), “scientific humanism” (e.g. Julian Huxley), and “classical humanism” (e.g. Gilbert Murray) reaching back to ancient Greek ideals and models.

54 Menand, The Metaphysical Club, 350. See also Porrovecchio, F. C. S. Schiller.

55 Schiller, Riddles of the Sphinx, 142.

56 Schiller, “Axioms as Postulates,” 57. Though I do not mention it in this article, advances in physics and biology were important in persuading Schiller to take this stance. Concepts such as “matter,” “force,” “causality,” “origin,” and “substance” took on whole new meanings in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries and these meanings allowed for a belief in the essential indetermination of entities such as facts or values. See especially Schiller, Riddles of the Sphinx.

57 Schiller, “Axioms as Postulates,” 61, original emphasis. For an intriguing theoretical–historical attempt to trace the overdetermined and contradictory structure of the subject of modernity see Cascardi, Anthony J., The Subject of Modernity (Cambridge, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

58 Schiller, F. C. S., “Are All Men Mortal?”, Mind, 44/174 (1935), 204–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

59 Ibid., 207.

60 Schiller, F. C. S., Logic for Use: An Introduction to the Voluntarist Theory of Knowledge (London, 1929), 99.Google Scholar

61 Ibid., 50.

62 Ibid., 54, original emphasis.

63 Ibid., 63, original emphasis.

64 Schiller, Riddles of the Sphinx, 132–133.

65 Schiller, “Are All Men Mortal?”, 207.

66 Mark. K. Porrovecchio, “The Curious Case of F.C.S Schiller,” Society for Psychical Research, at www.spr.ac.uk/main/article/curious-case-f-c-s-schiller, last accessed 8 March 2014.

67 Schiller, F. C. S., “The Progress of Psychical Research,” in Schiller, Studies in Humanism (London, 1907), 370–91Google Scholar.

68 Thakur, S. C., ed., Philosophy and Psychical Research (London, 1976)Google Scholar; Oppenheim, Janet, The Other World: Spiritualism and Psychical Research in England, 1850–1914 (Cambridge, 1985)Google Scholar; James, William, Essays in Psychical Research (Cambridge, 1986)Google Scholar; René Haynes, The Society for Psychical Research, 1882–1982: A History (London, 1982); Alex Owen, The Place of Enchantment: British Occultism and the Culture of the Modern (Chicago, 2004).

69 Schiller, “The Progress of Psychical Research,” 372–3, 387.

70 Ibid., 376.

71 Ibid., 376–7.

72 Ibid., 374.

73 H. Stuart Hughes, Consciousness and Society (New Brunswick, 2002); Michael Saler, As If: Modern Enchantment and the Literary Prehistory of Virtual Reality (New York, 2012).

74 Schiller, Formal Logic, all quotes from 397–8, original emphasis.

75 Schiller, F. C. S., “Review of German Philosophy and Politics ,” Mind, 25/98 (1916), 250–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 251.

76 Russell, “Dr Schiller's Analysis,” 651.

77 Diggins, John P., “Getting Hegel out of History: Max Eastman's Quarrel with Marxism,” American Historical Review, 79/1 (1974), 3871.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

78 Eastman, Max, “Mr. Schiller's Logic,” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 9/17 (1912), 463–68Google Scholar, at 464, 465, added emphasis.

79 For another example of the way in which ideology was at stake in a debate on logic and pragmatism see Ahti-Veiko Pietarinen, “The Place of Logic in Pragmatism,” Cognitio, 9/1 (2008), 247–60.

80 White, Morton, A Philosophy of Culture: The Scope of Holistic Pragmatism (Princeton, 2002), 2.Google Scholar

81 Schiller, F. C. S., Tantalus or the Future of Man (London, 1924), 47–8.Google Scholar

82 Schiller, Eugenics, 9.

83 Schiller, Logic for Use, 105–106.

84 Schiller, Riddles of the Sphinx, 231–2.

85 Schiller, F. C. S., Social Decay and Eugenical Reform (London, 1932), 34–5.Google Scholar

86 Ibid., 27.

87 For a good historical argument showcasing the paradoxical variety of British conservative ideology in the twentieth century see Green, E. H. H., Ideologies of Conservatism: Conservative Political Ideas in the Twentieth Century (Oxford, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

88 This was a common theme in European aristocratic revivalism, but justified in different, sometimes radically different, ways. One of these ways was that of Oscar Levy, a Jewish German intellectual who successfully introduced Nietzsche into England. See Dan Stone, Breeding Superman: Nietzsche, Race and Eugenics in Edwardian and Interwar Britain (Liverpool, 2002). Others include reactionary intellectuals of fin de siècle Vienna, who, in the words of Carl Schorske, “utilized aristocratic style, gesture, or pretension to mobilize a mass of followers still hungry for a leadership that based its authority on something older and deeper than the power of rational argument and empirical evidence.” Schorske quoted in Joseph Mali, Mythistory: The Making of Modern Historiography (Chicago, 2003), 17.

89 Schiller quoted in Slosson, Six Major Prophets, 226.

90 Schiller, Tantalus, 59.

91 Schiller, Eugenics, 60, original emphasis.

92 Schiller, F. C. S., “Review of Social Pathology ,” Eugenics Review, 4/3 (1912), 317–19Google Scholar, at 317–18, original emphasis.

93 Schiller, Eugenics, 29.

94 Freeden, “Eugenics.'” Eugenics, moreover, was a transnational movement, but one differentiated by national and disciplinary particularities. See Schuster, Edgar, “The First International Eugenics Congress,” Eugenics Review, 4/3 (1912), 223–56Google Scholar.

95 Judt, Tony, Postwar: A History of Europe since 1945 (London, 2005), 72 Google Scholar.

96 Zweiniger-Bargielowska, Ina, “Building a British Superman: Physical Culture in Interwar Britain,” Journal of Contemporary History, 41/4 (2006), 595610 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 596.

97 Webb, Sidney, “The Minority Report,” Eugenics Review, 2/3 (1910), 233–41.Google Scholar

98 Hanson, Clare, Eugenics, Literature, and Culture in Post-war Britain (New York, 2013)Google Scholar. For an account of eugenics as intimately related to European modernism, see Marius Turda, Modernism and Eugenics (New York, 2010).

99 A similar point is made by Freeden, Michael, The New Liberalism: An Ideology of Social Reform (Oxford, 1976), 11.Google Scholar

100 See, for example, Pettigrew, David and Raffoul, François, eds., French Interpretations of Heidegger: An Exceptional Reception (Albany, 2008)Google Scholar; and Müller, Jan-Werner, A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-war European Thought (New Haven, 2003).Google Scholar