Skip to main content
Log in

On the Cardinality Argument Against Quidditism

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Robert Black argues against quidditism on the grounds that the quidditist is either committed to proper-class many possible worlds and proper-class many possible fundamental properties or must adopt an unacceptably arbitrary restriction on the number of possible fundamental properties. In this paper, I examine Black’s cardinality argument against quidditism and argue that quidditists and non-quidditists alike have reason to reject a key premise of that argument. While it may be the case that the quidditist is committed to nomically indiscernible possible worlds that mark distinctions that make no difference to the physicist, it does not appear that the cardinality of the class of possible worlds or the class of possible fundamental properties postulated by the quidditist is any more problematic than that postulated by the non-quidditist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Robert Black (2000, p. 92), Ann Whittle (2006, p. 463), Stephen Barker (2009, p. 242), Robert Schroer (2010, p. 833), and Dustin Locke (2012, p. 348) among others.

  2. See Locke (2012) and Deborah C. Smith (2016) for a variety of ways of interpreting quiddities.

  3. D.M. Armstrong (1997) is an explicit proponent of this sort of quidditism, and Alexander Bird (2007) similarly interprets quidditism in this manner.

  4. Prominent proponents of dispositionalism include Sydney Shoemaker (1980) and John Hawthorne (2001).

  5. For a nice overview of the debate between dispositionalists and quidditists, see Jennifer Wang (2016).

  6. Hawthorne (2001) argues against quidditism on the grounds that, in addition to properties, the quidditist must also postulate quiddities. Although we have empirical reasons to postulate properties (they are invoked in scientific theories), Hawthorne takes the postulation of quiddities to offend against the principle of parsimony. Locke (2012) makes a distinction between extreme and austere forms of quidditism. Austere forms of quidditism simply identify properties and quiddities and so escape Hawthorne’s objection. (Versions of quidditism according to which fundamental properties are barely, numerically different also escape this objection.) Neither Hawthorne’s objection nor Locke’s response trade on the possibility of mere quiddistic differences between worlds.

  7. Here, it is worth noting that, in Smith (2016), I distinguish between what I call “individuation quidditism” and what I call “recombinatorial quidditism.” Individuation quidditism is simply the view that fundamental properties are individuated by something other than their causal or nomological role. Recombinatorial quidditism is the view that fundamental properties can freely recombine while preserving possibility. I argue that recombinatorial quidditism entails individuation quidditism but that individuation quidditism does not entail recombinatorial quidditism. If that is correct, individuation quidditism is consistent with but does not entail the existence of possible worlds that differ merely quiddistically.

  8. See Black’s (2000) argument that quidditism is committed to an “implausible plethora of distinct possible worlds” and Bird’s (2007) argument that quidditism is inconsistent with (what he takes to be) a plausible principle of identity between structurally indistinguishable worlds.

  9. Lewis (2009) dubs this form of skepticism “Ramseyan Humility”.

  10. In Smith (2016), I articulate a version of quidditism that I dub “non-recombinatorial quidditism” in which the relation between a property and its nomological role is metaphysically necessary. Such a view is largely (though not wholly) immune from objections that trade on worlds exhibiting merely quiddistic differences. For various responses to the skeptical objection, see Lewis (2009), Rae Langton (2004), Locke (2009), Schaffer (2005), and Whittle (2006).

  11. Black explicitly uses this argument to motivate the rejection of Lewis’ concrete modal realism (see Lewis 1986) in favor of what he calls abstract modal realism. However, it seems clear that the thrust of the argument, if cogent, would tell against any version of quidditism (whether or not it is combined with modal realism) that allows for merely quiddistic differences between worlds. Black’s cardinality argument also plays a key role in Stephen Mumford’s argument against the external theory of laws (see Mumford 2004, p. 152).

  12. This specific formulation is my own, but each of its premises is either explicit or implicit in Black’s text.

  13. A property is alien to w if and only if it is not instantiated in w.

  14. Cantor’s theorem guarantees that the cardinality K of any set is such that 2K > K.

  15. A proper class is a class whose cardinality is not the cardinality of any set.

  16. Lewis (1986, p. 104) provides an argument in favor of this premise and Black (2000, pp. 97–99) further motivates it. In broad outline, the idea is this: if there are proper-class many possible worlds, then for any set of possible worlds (including the set of all possible worlds), there will be possible worlds that are not members of that set. But, possible worlds, unlike sets, are not generated or otherwise ordered in an iterative hierarchy. So, it is absurd to think that one could not initially collect them all together in a set.

  17. The adoption of non-recombinatorial quidditism (see Smith 2016) would allow one to reject premise 1 of this argument. While non-recombinatorial quidditism is consistent with the idea that distinct fundamental properties would share nomological roles and so consistent with worlds exhibiting merely quiddistic differences, it is not consistent with the free recombination of fundamental properties required by premise 1.

  18. Interestingly, Black’s abstract modal realism may entail that there are proper-class many possible worlds (see Black 2000, p. 99), and Black notes that, although Lewis initially argued that the class of possible worlds should be set-sized, he later seemed open to there being proper-class many possible worlds (ibid, p. 97). See also Daniel Nolan (1996) who argues that taking possible objects to form a proper class allows for an unrestricted principle of recombination that is simpler and more intuitive than that offered by Lewis (1986, p. 89). Although Nolan’s focus is explicitly on the cardinality of the class of possible objects and its implications for the maximal size of any possible world rather than on the cardinality of the class of possible worlds, the claim that there are proper-class many possible objects along with the unrestricted principle of combination together entails that there are proper-class many possible worlds.

  19. This is not a response that would be open to a proponent of Lewis’ concrete modal realism.

  20. Armstrong (1989) was once a notable exception. In that earlier work, Armstrong argued for a combinatorial theory of possibility according to which possible worlds are combinations of actual objects and properties. He also understood fundamental properties to be Aristotelian universals that are distinguished by having distinct intrinsic natures (quiddities). Given those commitments, he explicitly denied that there are any alien fundamental properties.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1989). A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. (2009). Dispositional monism, relational constitution, and quiddities. Analysis, 69(2), 242–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s Metaphysics. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, R. (2000). Against quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2001). Causal structuralism. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 361–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2004). Elusive knowledge of things in themselves. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Basil Blackwell Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mittchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism (pp. 203–222). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (2009). A partial defense of Ramseyan Humility. In D. Braddon-Mittchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism (pp. 223–241). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (2012). Quidditism without quiddities. Philosophical Studies, 160, 345–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in Nature. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1996). Recombination unbound. Philosophical Studies, 84, 239–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroer, R. (2010). Is there more than one categorical property? The Philosophical Quarterly, 60, 831–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 123, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sydney. (1980). Causality and properties. In Peter van Inwagen (Ed.) Time and Cause: Essays Presented to Richard Taylor. D. Reidel Publishing Company, 228–54.

  • Smith, D. C. (2016). Quid Quidditism Est? Erkenntnis, 81, 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J. (2016). The nature of properties: Causal essentialism and quidditism. Philosophical Compass, 11(3), 168–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A. (2006). On an argument for humility. Philosophical Studies, 130, 461–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Deborah C. Smith.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Smith, D.C. On the Cardinality Argument Against Quidditism. Acta Anal 38, 275–281 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00524-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00524-1

Keywords

Navigation