Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Limits of Principlism and Recourse to Theory: The Example of Telecare

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Principlism is the approach promoted by Beauchamp and Childress for addressing the ethics of medical practice. Instead of evaluating clinical decisions by means of full-scale theories from moral philosophy, Beauchamp and Childress refer people to four principles—of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. Now it is one thing for principlism to be invoked in an academic literature dwelling on a stock topic of medical ethical writing: end-of-life decisions, for example. It is another when the topic lies further from the mainstream. In such cases the cost of reaching for the familiar Beauchamp and Childress framework, with its formulaic set of concerns, may be to miss something morally important. After discussing an example of the sort of academic literature I have in mind, I propose to distinguish the uses of the formulaic from the uses of the more unapologetically theoretical in applied ethics, and to suggest that the latter can make up for some of the limitations of the former. This is not to say that the more theoretical literature has no limitations of its own, or that it should take the place of the formulaic. On the contrary, there is room in applied ethics and a use in applied ethics for both. But there is a sense in which there is a greater dependence of principlism on theory than the other way round, and at the end I try to spell out the significance of this fact.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘principlism’ is sometimes associated with critics of Beauchamp and Childress, notably K Danner Clouser and Bernard Gert, in a series of articles and books from the 1990s. This paper is not associated with the point of view of Clouser and Gert. Beauchamp and Childress’s book has now gone through six editions, and its deployment of the four principles was already changing markedly in the fourth edition. (see Emmanuel 1995: 37–38). Whereas principlism was once associated with bringing hard cases under general principles and deriving the implications of principles in different situations of action, that does not seem to fit Beauchamp and Childress in its latest incarnation. The matter is discussed in chapter 10 of the Sixth Edition, op. cit. By ‘principlism’ I mean turning for diagnoses and solutions of problems of health care ethics to one or more of the four principles promoted by Beauchamp and Childress rather than any broader or more general moral theory, including a general moral theory formulated in academic philosophy. This approach may more properly associated with Raanon Gillon than Beauchamp and Childress. See the Festschrift issue for Gillon:2003).

  2. For some of the ethical issues connected with wandering, and useful references to its clinical side, see McShane et al. 1994: 1274.

  3. The book is a translation of J-D Bauby, Le scaphandre et le papillon (Paris; Editions Pocket, 1997).

  4. For more information on this syndrome, see the US National Institutes of Health web-page: http://www.ninds.nih.gov/disorders/lockedinsyndrome/lockedinsyndrome.htm

  5. See e.g., Cotrell and Shulz 1993: 205–211.

  6. “For example, A[ssistive ]T[echnology] &T[elecare] might be used to facilitate skill teaching. Similarly, independence(and the increased opportunities for choice making which go hand in hand with it) can be one consequence of the use of smart home technology if the presence of staff is reduced”.p. 82

  7. J Percival and J Hanson, ‘Big Brother or Brave New World? Telecare and its Implications for Older People’s Independence and Social Inclusion’ Critical Social Policy 26 (2006) 888–909, see esp. p. 898. L Robinson et al., (2007) ‘Balancing Rights and Risks: conflicting perspectives in the management of wandering in dementia’, Health, Risk and Society 9 (2007) pp. 389–406.

  8. P. 83

  9. http://www.hri.org/docs/ECHR50.html#C.Art8

  10. P.84

  11. P. 85

  12. Ibid.

  13. Ibid.

  14. This conjecture is perhaps contradicted by very recently published evidence. See M-A Bruno et al., ‘A survey on self-assessed well-being in a cohort of chronic locked-in syndrome patients: happy majority, miserable minority’ BMJ Open (Feb 2011) http://bmjopen.bmj.com/content/early/2011/02/16/bmjopen-2010-000039.full#

  15. Percival and Hanson 2006: 888–909, see esp. p. 898.

  16. Utilitarianism could give weight to the unpleasantness of loneliness, but it might imply that the associated disutility is more than compensated for by e.g. the pain relief afforded by the reduction in staff costs made possible by telecare.

  17. See my ‘Citizen-Patient/Citizen-Doctor’ Health Care Analysis 9 (2001) pp. 25–39

  18. For the importance of this in practice in the UK National Health service, see Ian Kennedy’s (2001) Report of the Bristol Royal Infirmary Inquiry (UK Dept. of Health CM5207 (I)) ch.22, §18.

References

  • (2003) Festschrift Special Issue in Honour of Raanan Gillon. J med. ethics 29

  • Barlow J (2007) A systematic review of the benefits of home telecare for frail elderly people and those with long-term conditions. J telemed telecare 13

  • Beauchamp TL, Childress JF (2009) Principles of biomedical ethics, Sixth edition. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotrell V and Shulz R (1993) The perspective of the patient with Alzheimer’s disease: a neglected dimension of dementia research. The Gerontologist 33 (2)

  • Dewing J (2002) From ritual to relationship: a person-centred approach to research with older people who have Dementia. Dement 1

  • Draper H and Sorell T (2002) Patients’ responsibilities in medical ethics. Bioethics 16

  • Emmanuel E (1995) The beginning of the end of principlism. Hastings Cent rep 25

  • Kennedy Ian (2001) Report of the Bristol Royal Infirmary Inquiry (UK Dept. of Health CM5207 (I))

  • McShane R, Hope T, and Wilkinson J (1994) Tracking patients who wander: ethics and technology. The Lancet 343

  • Percival J and Hanson J (2006) Big brother or brave new world? Telecare and its implications for older people’s independence and social inclusion. Crit soc policy 26

  • Perry, Beyer and Holm (2009) Assistive technology, telecare and people with intellectual disabilities: ethical considerations. J med ethics 35

  • Post S and P Whitehouse (1995) Fairhill guidelines on ethics of care of People with Alzheimer’s disease: a clinical summary. J Am Geriatr Soc 43

  • Robinson L et al. (2007) Balancing rights and risks: conflicting perspectives in the management of wandering in dementia. Health, risk soc 9

  • Scanlon T (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (1999) The singer solution to world poverty. The New York Times Magazine, September 5, 1999, pp 60–63

  • Sorell T (2001) Citizen-patient/citizen-doctor Health Care Analysis 9

  • Thomson Judith (1971) In defense of abortion. Philos. public aff 1

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Sorell.

Additional information

I am grateful to Prof. Heather Draper for discussion of some of the issues taken up here.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sorell, T. The Limits of Principlism and Recourse to Theory: The Example of Telecare. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 14, 369–382 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9292-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9292-9

Keywords

Navigation