Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T22:13:13.277Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

My Song is Love Unknown: Liturgical Music and Rational Faith

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Gregory R. P. Stacey*
Affiliation:
Leeds Trinity University

Abstract

Whilst philosophers have argued that musical experience provides evidence for theism, their discussions often fail to consider the aesthetic properties which give musical experience its distinctive character, or ways in which musical experience might support the beliefs of particular religious traditions. This paper begins to remedy this omission by examining how attention to liturgical music can provide rational support for Christian faith. I first explore music's emotional nature and impact, and its ability to embody Christian narratives and doctrines. In light of this discussion, I then introduce two probabilistic arguments for the truth of Christian orthodoxy, arguing that liturgical music can provide distinctive evidence for their premises.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2021 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Wynn, Mark, Renewing the Senses: A Study of the Philosophy and Theology of the Spiritual Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013CrossRefGoogle Scholar); Cuneo, Terence, Ritualized Faith: Essays on the Philosophy of Liturgy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016CrossRefGoogle Scholar); Cottingham, John Philosophy of Religion: Towards a More Humane Approach (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2014CrossRefGoogle Scholar); Perlmutter, Julian, Sacred Music, Religious Desire and Knowledge of God (London: Bloomsbury, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Cottingham, John, ‘Transcending Science: Humane Models of Religious Understanding’ in Ellis, Fiona, ed., New Models of Religious Understanding (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), pp. 23-41Google Scholar (quotations from p. 29 and p. 41).

4 Following Plantinga, Alvin, Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Richard Viladesau, Theological Aesthetics: God in Imagination, Beauty and Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 120-40Google Scholar.

6 Plantinga, Alvin, ‘Two-Dozen or so Arguments for the Existence of God’ in Baker, Deane Peter, ed., Alvin Plantinga (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 226Google Scholar, and Tallon, Philip ‘The Mozart Argument and the Argument from Play’ in Walls, Jerry and Dougherty, Trent (eds.) Two-Dozen (or so) Argument for God: The Plantinga Project (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018), pp. 321-337Google Scholar.

7 Kreeft, Peter and Tacelli, Ronald, Handbook of Christian Apologetics (Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1994), p. 81Google Scholar.

8 Augustine, Confessions X.33. (trans. Pine-Coffin, R.S. (Penguin: Harmondsworth, 1961), p. 238Google Scholar).

9 Begbie, Jeremy, ‘Faithful Feelings: Music and Emotion in Worship’ in Begbie, Jeremy and Guthrie, Steven (eds.) Resonant Witness: Conversations Between Music and Theology, pp. 323-354 (p. 325)Google Scholar.

10 Robinson, Jenefer, ‘Emotional Responses to Music: What Are They? How Do They Work? And Are They Relevant to Aesthetic Appreciation?’ in Goldie, Peter, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 651-80 (pp. 652-3)Google Scholar.

11 Kivy, Peter, Sound Sentiment: An Essay on the Musical Emotions (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), pp. 12-17Google Scholar.

12 Zangwill, Nick, ‘Against Emotion: Hanslick was right about music’, British Journal of Aesthetics, 44.1 (2004), pp. 29�43 (pp. 30-2)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Ibid. pp. 33-40; Davies, Stephen, Musical Meaning and Expression (New York: Cornell University Press, 1994), 167-199CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Scruton, Roger The Aesthetics of Music (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999) pp. 144-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Davies, Musical Meaning, p. 109.

15 Ibid., pp. 152-4; p. 204.

16 Scruton, Aesthetics of Music, pp. 434-368.

17 Kivy, Sound Sentiment, pp. 46-83; Davies, Musical Meaning, pp. 221-243; Begbie, ‘Faithful Feelings’, pp. 338-349.

18 Scruton, Aesthetics of Music, pp .153-4; Madell, Geoffrey, Philosophy, Music and Emotion (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Davies, Musical Meaning, pp. 214-16; pp. 262-64.

20 Kivy, Sound Sentiment, pp. 210-33; Perlmutter, Sacred Music, pp. 64-7.

21 Ibid., pp. 71-3; Young, James, Critique of Pure Music (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), pp. 35-58CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 Davies, Musical Meaning, pp. 299-307; Young, Critique, pp. 59-79.

23 Davies, Musical Meaning, pp. 51-121; Scruton, Aesthetics of Music, pp. 118-139.

24 Wynn, Renewing the Senses, pp. 44-5.

25 Ibid., p. 47.

26 Exodus 15:1-18.

27 As summarised in e.g. the ‘Nicene’ creeds (of 325 and 381), and the ‘Athanasian Creed’. For an introductory treatment, see Emery, Giles, The Trinity: An Introduction to Catholic Doctrine on the Triune God (Washington DC: CUA Press, 2011Google Scholar).

28 Christian philosophers still debate Trinitarian metaphysics, contesting e.g whether the Persons are ‘centres of consciousness’, and the nature of their substantial unity. See Hasker, William, Metaphysics and the Tri-Personal God (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017Google Scholar).

29 Emery, The Trinity, p. 89.

30 Begbie, Jeremy, Resounding Truth (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2007Google Scholar), Broadhead, Bradley, ‘The Triune Triad: A Musical Analogy Concerning the Trinity and Humanity’, Imaginatio et Ratio 3 (2014), pp. 23-33Google Scholar, Bertolgio, Chiara, ‘A Perfect Chord: Trinity in Music, Music in the Trinity’, Religions 4 (2013), pp. 485�501Google Scholar.

31 Cunningham, David, These Three are One: The Practice of Trinitarian Theology (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 1998), p. 128Google Scholar.

32 Davies, Musical Meaning and Expression, pp. 367-9.

33 Bertoglio, ‘A Perfect Chord’, pp. 491-2.

34 Begbie, Resounding Truth, p. 293.

35 Broadhead, ‘The Trine Triad’, pp. 24-8 Bertoglio, ‘A Perfect Chord’, pp. 494-7.

36 Cuneo, Ritualized Faith, pp. 126-44.

37 Ibid., p. 138.

38 Ibid., pp. 142-3.

39 Newman, John Henry, Essays Critical and Historical Vol. I (London: Longmans, 1907), p. 23Google Scholar.

40 We can characterise ‘epistemic probability’ in AAC in terms of what Swinburne calls ‘logical probability’: roughly, the ‘objective’ probability relations between hypotheses and evidence which determine the credences of rational (Bayesian) observers. One can present (AAC2) in Bayesian terms: P(e│h & k) > P(e│∼h & k), where the evidence (e) is the aesthetic and moral attractiveness of Christian narratives and doctrines, the hypothesis (h) is Christianity's truth, and (k) is background knowledge. On logical probability and Bayesian arguments, see Swinburne, Richard, The Existence of God: 2nd Edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), pp. 13�22; 52-72CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 Readers might wonder what AAC means by calling doctrines and narratives (etc.) “beautiful”. Is this to ascribe some “objective” property to objects which renders them beautiful (e.g. ordered proportionality) or else are objects called beautiful because they provoke certain reactions in observers (e.g. disinterested pleasure)? I do not intend AAC to depend on any controversial general analysis of beauty. The latter would require lengthy defence, and narrow AAC's dialectical appeal. Accordingly, for the purposes of AAC, to say that an object is beautiful is just to say (with admitted vagueness) that a significant proportion of people would describe it as beautiful on reflection. This suggestion is compatible with the observation that aesthetic standards vary, and with the claim that ascriptions of beauty are normatively grounded in objects’ intrinsic properties. Indeed, I assume that some intrinsic features of objects (e.g. internal harmony or coherence) are commonly perceived as beautiful.

42 See Confessions VIII.12; Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief, p. 288.

43 Genesis 1: 31; Psalm 8:1, 19:1; Romans 1:20.

44 Viladesau, Theological Aesthetics, pp .105 - 118.

45 Wynn, Mark, ‘Musical Affects and the Life of Faith: Some Reflections on the Religious Potency of Music’, Faith and Philosophy 21.1 (2004), pp. 24-44Google Scholar.

46 Swinburne, Richard, The Christian God (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), pp. 177-80CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 Bacon, Hannah, What's Right with the Trinity? Conversations in Feminist Theology (Farnham: Ashgate, 2009)Google Scholar; LacCugna, Catherine Mowry, God for Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (San Francisco: Harper, 1991)Google Scholar.

48 Ibid., p.398.

49 Bacon, What's Right, pp. 183-7; pp. 190-3.

50 Ibid. pp. 138-9.

51 Ibid. p. 188.

52 See n. 28.

53 Bacon, What's Right, pp. 50-52.

54 Kilby, Karen, ‘Perichoresis and Projection: Problems with Social Doctrines of the Trinity’, New Blackfriars 81 (2000), pp. 432-55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

55 Kilby, Karen ‘Is an Apophatic Trinitarianism Possible?’, International Journal of Systematic Theology 12.1 (2010), pp. 65-77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 On early Trinitarian theology, see Emery, The Trinity, pp. 51-82 and Dünzl, Franz, A Brief History of the Doctrine of the Trinity in the Early Church (London: T&T Clark, 2007)Google Scholar.

57 This paper is written for the first birthday of Torquhil Colquhoun, who completes a triad. My thanks to Simon Hewitt, Tyler McNabb, and an anonymous reviewer for comments.