Skip to main content
Log in

Papineau’s Theoretical Rationality and the Anthropological Difference

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A common view in philosophy is that the way human beings reason is not only gradually better, but that our way of reasoning is fundamentally distinctive. Findings in the psychology of reasoning challenge the traditional view according to which human beings reason in accordance with the laws of logic and probability theory, but rather suggest that human reasoning consists in the application of domain specific rules of thumb similar to those that we ascribe to some intelligent non-human animals as well. However, this view on human reasoning is unable to explain human accomplishments like technological innovations or scientific progress. David Papineau offers a theory of human theoretical rationality that is consistent with the psychological view on human reasoning but that can also explain how humans sometimes are able to transcend the limitations of their biologically quick and dirty modes of thought and thereby reach a high level of accuracy. Papineau claims that the abilities that constitute theoretical rationality are unique to the human species and thus, that human reasoning is fundamentally distinctive after all. In this paper I am going to discuss to what extent these abilities in fact are unique to our species and whether this theoretical rationality can be called an anthropological difference.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is, of course, the logical possibility that an individual has knowledge about the nature of her own beliefs but fails to ascribe false beliefs to others. In this case, this individual would have the relevant understanding of truth and still fail the false-belief task, because the task only demonstrates whether a subject can ascribe false beliefs to others. I leave this possibility aside here, because I consider the possibility that all the members of a species have this knowledge regarding their own beliefs, but fail to transfer this knowledge to conspecifics a mere logical possibility that seems empirically highly unlikely.

References

  • Bugnyar, T., & Kotrschal, K. (2004). Leading a conspecific away from food in ravens (Corvus corax)? Animal Cognition, 7, 69–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bugnyar, T., & Heinrich, B. (2005). Ravens, Corvus corax, differentiate between knowledgeable and ignorant competitors. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 2005(272), 1641–1646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Science, 12, 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., Dally, J. N., & Emery, N. J. (2007). Social cognition by food-caching corvids. The western scrub-jay as a natural psychologist. Phil Trans R Soc B, 362, 507–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1998). Animal Consciousness. What Matters and Why. In D. C. Dennett (Ed.), Brainchildren. Essays on Designing Minds (pp. 337–350). Cambridge (Mass.): MIT Press.

  • Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2001). Effects of experience and social context on prospective caching strategies by scrub jays. Nature, 404, 443–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2004). The Mentality of Crows: Convergent Evolution of Intelligence in Corvids and Apes. Science, 306(5703), 1903–1907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flombaum, J. I., & Santos, L. R. (2005). Rhesus Monkeys Attribute Perceptions to Others. Current Biology, 15, 447–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2001). Bounded and Rational. In G. Gigerenzer & R. Selten (Eds.), Bounded Rationality: The adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Brighton, H. (2009). Homo Heuristicus: Why Biased Minds Make Better Inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 107–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe. Cognition, 109, 224–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. I., & Funder, D. C. (2004). Towards a balanced social psychology: Causes, consequences, and cures for the problemseeking approach to social behavior and cognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 313–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulkahy, N. J., & Call, J. (2006). How great apes perform on a modified trap-tube task. Animal Cognition, 9(3), 193–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., & Bartels, A. (2007). Animal Minds and the Possession of Concepts. Philosophical Psychology, 20(3), 283–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007a). The Evolution of Knowledge. In D. Papineau (Ed.), The Roots of Reason (pp. 39–82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007b). The Evolution of Means-End Reasoning. In D. Papineau (Ed.), The Roots of Reason (pp. 83–129). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., & Vonk, J. (2003). Chimpanzee minds: suspiciously human? Trends in Cognitive Science, 7, 157–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R., & Stich, S. (2004). Rationality and Psychology. In A. R. Mehle & P. Rawling (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality (pp. 279–300). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searl, J. R. (1994). Animal Minds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19, 206–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seed, A. M., Tebbich, S., Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2006). Investigating physical cognition in rooks, Corvus frugilegus. Current Biology, 16, 697–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tennie, C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2010). Evidence for emulation in chimpanzees in social settings using the floating peanut task. PLoS One, 5(5), p.e10544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999): The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.

  • Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2008). Why We Cooperate. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extension versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90(4), 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobias Starzak.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Starzak, T. Papineau’s Theoretical Rationality and the Anthropological Difference. Philosophia 40, 473–482 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9359-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9359-9

Keywords

Navigation