Skip to main content
Log in

Varieties of parity

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A central idea of developmental systems theory is ‘parity’ or ‘symmetry’ between genes and non-genetic factors of development. The precise content of this idea remains controversial, with different authors stressing different aspects and little explicit comparisons among the various interpretations. Here I characterise and assess several influential versions of parity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here are two quotes to this effect: “The theory does not deny that there are distinctions among developmental processes” (Griffiths and Gray 1994, p. 283). Oyama (2000, p. S342) wrote: “Nor does parity mean that in any particular analysis, all things are equally important or “the same,” that no distinctions can be made.”

  2. Weber objected against this form of parity that it ceases to be an empirical proposition. Its truth hinges on a general metaphysical claim about the nature of causation (section 8.4).

  3. Not all accept Millean parity. Paul Griffiths, for instance, accepts that templates are the only factors determining product sequences if mechanisms like RNA editing are absent (pers. comm.).

  4. In addition, Waters (2006) offers a methodological defence of ‘gene-centrism’, the phenomenon that genes are the focus of much research in the life sciences.

  5. Waters (2007) builds on Woodward’s (2003) manipulationist account of causation.

  6. I owe this point to Marcel Weber. See Northcott (2009) for a general objection against Waters (2007) account.

  7. This objection to Waters (2007) is not a criticism of Woodward’s (2003) analysis of causation.

  8. “If biologists were […] limited to considering the causal synthesis of a single polypeptide molecule, they would have no basis for saying that the polypeptide’s linear sequence was determined by DNA, and not by RNA polymerase. In fact, if restricted to considering a single instance (or a population of identical outcomes), it might appear that DNA was merely scaffolding for the synthesis of RNA. The causal distinctiveness of DNA is in the population. It is only in the context where polypeptide molecules with different amino acid sequences are being synthesized that it makes sense for biologist to say that DNA is not on a causal par with many of the other molecules that play causally necessary roles in the synthesis of RNA and polypeptides” (Waters 2007, p. 579).

  9. For instance, Nishimura et al. (1965) produced polypeptides containing serine and leucine in alternating order from poly-UC, describing the latter as “directing” polypeptide synthesis (pp. 314, 323).

  10. Examples are the production of polyadenylate RNA fragments from polythymidilate DNA (Falaschi et al. 1963) and of poly-UC RNA molecules from poly-TG DNA sections (Nishimura et al. 1965). The DNA fragments were regarded as “templates” for synthesising the RNA fragments (e.g. Falaschi et al. 1963, p. 3084; Nishimura et al. 1965, p. 322), whose function is to determine RNA sequences (Falaschi et al. 1963, p. 3080).

  11. Many thanks to Marcel Weber for pressing me on this point. In fact, both Judson’s (1996) account of this historical episode and the structure of Nirenberg and Matthaei’s (1961, p. 1601) paper suggest that they considered the wider set of trials as decisive for their conclusion.

  12. For instance, polyadenylic acid (poly-A) and polycytidylic acid (poly-C); table 6, ‘experiment no. 1’ in Nirenberg and Matthaei (1961, p. 1601).

  13. Poly-U served as the template. See table 8, as well as text on p. 1596, in Nirenberg and Matthaei (1961).

  14. Effects of niche construction will complicate the picture.

References

  • Bergstrom CT, Rosvall M (2011) The transmission sense of information. Biol Philos 26:159–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubas P, Vincent C, Coen E (1999) An epigenetic mutation responsible for natural variation in floral symmetry. Nature 401:157–161

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Falaschi A, Adler J, Khorana HG (1963) Chemically synthesized deoxypolynucleotides as templates for ribonucleic acid polymerase. J Biol Chem 238:3080–3085

    Google Scholar 

  • Feil R, Fraga MF (2012) Epigenetics and the environment: emerging patterns and implications. Nat Rev Genet 13:97–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Gannett L (1999) What’s in a cause? The pragmatic dimensions of genetic explanations. Biol Philos 14:349–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehring WJ (1998) Master control genes in development and evolution: the homeobox story. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2000a) On the theoretical role of “Genetic Coding”. Phil Sci 67:26–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2000b) Explanatory symmetries, preformation, and developmental systems theory. Philos Sci 67 (Proceedings):S322–S331

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1957) Meaning. Philos Rev 66:377–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2001) Genetic information: a metaphor in search of a theory. Phil Sci 68:394–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray R (1994) Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. J Phil 91:277–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD (2005) Discussion: three ways to misunderstand developmental systems theory. Biol Philos 20:417–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Knight RD (1998) What is the developmentalist challenge? Philos Sci 65:253–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judson HF (1996) The eighth day of creation. CSHL Press, Plainview

  • Kitcher PS (2001) Battling the undead: how and how not to resist genetic determinism. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB, Paul DB, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution: historical, philosophical, and political perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 396–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (2000) The concept of information in biology. Phil Sci 67:177–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (2004) The varieties of meaning. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan HD, Sutherland HG, Martin DI, Whitelaw E (1999) Epigenetic inheritance at the agouti locus in the mouse. Nat Genet 23:314–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss L (1992) A kernel of truth? On the reality of the genetic program. PSA 1992: Philos Sci Assoc (Proceedings) 1:335–348

  • Moss L (2003) What genes can’t do. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nirenberg MW, Matthaei HJ (1961) The dependence of cell-free protein synthesis in E. coli upon naturally occurring or synthetic polyribonucleotides. Proc Nat Acad Sci 47:1588–1602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nishimura S, Jones DS, Khorana HG (1965) Studies on Polynucleotides. XLVIII. The in vitro synthesis of a co-polypeptide containing two amino acids in alternating sequence dependent upon a DNA-like polymer containing two nucleotides in alternating sequence. J Mol Biol 13:302–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northcott R (2009) Is actual difference making actually different? J Philos 106:629–634

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (1985) The ontogeny of information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (2000) Causal democracy and causal contributions in developmental systems theory. Philos Sci 67 (Proceedings):S332–S347

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert JS (2004) Embryology, epigenesis, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2003) Genes encode information for phenotypic traits. In: Hitchcock C (ed) Contemporary debates in philosophy of science. Blackwell, London, pp 259–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino A, Piccinini G (2010) Information without truth. Metaphilosophy 41:313–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner K (1998) Genes, behavior, and developmental emergentism: one process, indivisible? Philos Sci 65:209–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seong K, Li D, Shimizu H, Nakamura R, Ishii S (2011) Inheritance of stress-induced, ATF-2-Dependent epigenetic change. Cell 145:1049–1061

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007a) Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems. Biol Philos 22:313–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007b) Consumers need information: supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Res 75:404–435

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2011) Developmental systems theory formulated as a claim about inherited information. Philos Sci 78:60–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann UE (2005) Genetic information as instructional content. Phil Sci 72:425–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann UE (2009) DNA, inference and information. Brit J Phil Sci 60:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann UE (2012) Causal control and genetic causation. Noûs. [Online First doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2012.00867.x]

  • Sterelny K (2000) The “Genetic Program” program: a commentary on Maynard Smith on Information in biology. Phil Sci 67:195–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Griffiths PE (1999) Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Smith K, Dickison M (1996) The extended replicator. Biol Phil 11:377–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz K (2006) With ‘genes’ like that, who needs an environment? Postgenomics’s argument for the ‘ontogeny of information’. Philos Sci 73:905–917

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters CK (2006) The pluralist stance. Minn Stud Philos Sci 19:7–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters CK (2007) Causes that make a difference. J Philos 104:551–579

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2005a) Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2005b) Genes, causation and intentionality. Hist Phil Life Sci 27:399–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (forthcoming) Causal selection vs causal parity in biology: relevant counterfactuals and biologically normal interventions. Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2010) Causation in biology: stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biol Philos 25:287–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Marcel Weber and Paul Griffiths for their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ulrich E. Stegmann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stegmann, U.E. Varieties of parity. Biol Philos 27, 903–918 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9331-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9331-5

Keywords

Navigation