Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Natality and mortality: rethinking death with Cavarero

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article I rethink death and mortality on the basis of birth and natality, drawing on the work of the Italian feminist philosopher Adriana Cavarero. She understands birth to be the corporeal event whereby a unique person emerges from the mother’s body into the common world. On this basis Cavarero reconceives death as consisting in bodily dissolution and re-integration into cosmic life. This impersonal conception of death coheres badly with her view that birth is never exclusively material but always has ontological significance as the appearance of someone new and singular in the world of relations with others. This view of birth calls for a relational conception of death, which I develop in this article. On this conception, death is always collective, affecting all those with whom the one who dies has maintained relations: As such, our different deaths shade into one another. Moreover, because each person is unique in virtue of consisting of a unique web of relations with others, death always happens to persons as webs of relations. Death is relational in this way as a corporeal, and specifically biological, phenomenon, to which we are subject as bodily beings and as interdependent living organisms. I explore this with reference to Simone de Beauvoir’s memoir of her mother’s death from cancer. Finally I argue that, on this relational conception, death is something to be feared.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. They include Battersby (1998), Guenther (2006, 2008), Irigaray (1991), Kristeva (1986), Mullin (2005). This list is far from exhaustive.

  2. Cavarero (2008, p. 148).

  3. Arendt (1958, p. 211).

  4. Arendt (1958, p. 211).

  5. Arendt (1958, p. 178).

  6. See Birmingham (2005).

  7. See inter alia Honig (1995). The contributors to this volume discuss this feminist criticism of Arendt, but they also complicate it and put forward productive feminist rereadings of Arendt’s work.

  8. Cavarero (1995, p. 6).

  9. Cavarero (2005, p. 2).

  10. Cavarero (2008, p. 137).

  11. Guenther (2006).

  12. See for instance Baraitser (2009).

  13. Cavarero (1995, p. 60).

  14. Cavarero (1995, p. 59).

  15. I lack space to ask how this picture accommodates genealogies that are social rather than biological—adoptive families, surrogacy, sperm donation—where the biological and social parents come apart. We might ask, too, why Cavarero assigns ontological significance to birth (thus mothers primarily) and not conception (thus mothers and fathers). This is, I think, because birth marks the entrance into the common world alongside plural others. One might object that the developing foetus already begins to participate in this world in a form mediated by the mother—hearing sounds, tasting tastes, detecting changes in light. But perhaps we only understand this to be participation in a shared world by extrapolating from the existing-in-common with which we are familiar post-natally, so that such understandings of pre-natal existence would already presuppose the ontological centrality of birth.

  16. Cavarero (1995, p. 114).

  17. Cavarero (1995, pp. 115–117).

  18. Lispector (1988, p. 57).

  19. Cavarero (1995, p. 116).

  20. Cavarero (1995, pp. 99–100, 105).

  21. Cavarero (1995, pp. 114, 119).

  22. Lispector (1988, p. 59).

  23. Cavarero (2009, p. 12; my emphasis).

  24. Heidegger (1962, p. 308).

  25. Moreover, Cavarero’s philosophy of birth conflicts with Heidegger’s philosophical privileging of Dasein’s being-towards-death as the ground of its orientation towards its birth. See Heidegger (1962, pp. 425–427, 442–443). Whereas Heidegger makes mortality the ground of natality, Cavarero (following Arendt) reverses this ordering.

  26. Cavarero (2000, p. 43).

  27. Cavarero (2000, p. 38).

  28. Cavarero (2000, p. 73).

  29. Cavarero (2000, pp. 38–39).

  30. Cavarero (2000, p. 21).

  31. Cavarero (2000, p. 34).

  32. Cavarero (2000, p. 90; my emphasis).

  33. For a similar strongly relational reading of Cavarero, see Perpich (2003).

  34. Heidegger (1962, p. 308; my emphasis).

  35. Cavarero (2000, p. 36).

  36. Cavarero (2000, p. 28).

  37. Cavarero (2000, p. 38).

  38. For Heidegger, in contrast, it makes no sense to say that a bereaved person exists less than they did. Rather, for Heidegger, the bereaved person is still in the world, but as a world from which the other has gone, or in which the bereaved is with that dead other only as-dead. But the bereaved person has not herself died at all; she hasn’t died with the dead person, who necessarily died alone. Heidegger’s views here reflect the ultimate priority that he gives to (individual) being-there over being-with: After all, for him, ‘The world of Dasein is a with-world’ (1962, p. 155; my emphasis)—the world is primarily of Dasein. Having said this, there is a question about how it is possible for someone bereaved to exist less than they did before. I address this in Sects. 5 and 6.

  39. Freud (1984, p. 368).

  40. Derrida (1993, p. 76). Derrida says this partly with reference to Freud’s view of the personality as a precipitate of relations with others. But Derrida also means that I can only anticipate my death (from within my life) as an occurrence of the order of the deaths of others. This is because, necessarily, my death as my constitutive limit is not something I can anticipate or bring within my compass at all. Thus here Derrida wishes to turn Heidegger’s distinction between my own death and those of others against his account of anticipatory resoluteness and authenticity. In doing so, though, Derrida still operates within Heidegger’s conceptual framework, whereas Cavarero follows Arendt in building a positive philosophical alternative to Heidegger, an alternative that prioritizes natality and sociality over mortality and individuation.

  41. For a version of this argument see Guenther (2008).

  42. de Beauvoir (2004, p. 114).

  43. In Pyrrhus and Cineas Beauvoir does not reject that distinction as such (indeed, she does not mention it). Rather, what she rejects in Heidegger’s account of death is his view that authenticity must be grounded in the assumption of one’s mortality, for (anticipating Derrida) she denies that one can have any anticipatory relation to one’s death as such. She instead grounds the possibility of authenticity in our ambiguous transcendence. See de Beauvoir (2004, pp. 113–115).

  44. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 87).

  45. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 10).

  46. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 50).

  47. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 89).

  48. de Beauvoir (1966, pp. 14, 17).

  49. de Beauvoir (1966, pp. 71, 73).

  50. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 91).

  51. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 28).

  52. Butler says: ‘We’re undone by each other’ when we lose one another to death (2004, p. 23). Cavarero (2009, p. 8) tells us that to ‘undo’ formerly meant to viscerally disfigure or dismember.

  53. de Beauvoir (1988, pp. 66–67).

  54. de Beauvoir (1966, p. 91).

  55. I say ‘fear’ (contrary to Heidegger’s distinction of fear from anxiety) because from my perspective, it is death as a phenomenon with corporeal and biological dimensions that we as living beings have reason to fear.

  56. I thank the anonymous referees for their extremely helpful comments and suggestions, and those (including Rachel Jones, Beth Lord, John Mullarkey, and James Williams) who responded to this paper at the University of Dundee Philosophy Research Seminar.

References

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baraitser, Lisa. 2009. Maternal encounters: The ethics of interruption. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battersby, Christine. 1998. The phenomenal woman: Feminist metaphysics and the patterns of identity. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birmingham, Peg. 2005. Political affections: Kristeva and Arendt on violence and gratitude. In Revolt, affect, collectivity: The unstable boundaries of Kristeva’s polis, ed. Tina Chanter and Ewa Plonowska Ziarek, 127–145. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2004. Precarious life: The powers of mourning and violence. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavarero, Adriana. 2008. Ontology and sexual difference: An interview with Italian feminist philosopher Adriana Cavarero. Interview with Elisabetta Bertolino. Differences 19(1): 129–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavarero, Adriana. 1995. In spite of Plato: A feminist rewriting of ancient philosophy (trans: Anderlini-d’Onofrio, S., and O’Healy, A.). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

  • Cavarero, Adriana. 2000. Relating narratives (trans: Kottman, P.A.). London and New York: Routledge.

  • Cavarero, Adriana. 2005. For more than one voice: Toward a philosophy of vocal expression (trans: Kottman, P.A.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Cavarero, Adriana. 2009. Horrorism: Naming contemporary violence (trans: McCuaig, W.). New York: Columbia University Press.

  • de Beauvoir, Simone. 1966. A very easy death (trans: O’Brian, P.). Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • de Beauvoir, Simone. 1988. The second sex (trans: Parshley, H.M.). London: Picador.

  • de Beauvoir, Simone. 2004. Philosophical writings, ed. M.A. Simons. Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1993. Aporias (trans: Dutoit, T.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1984. On metapsychology, ed. A. Richards. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • Guenther, Lisa. 2006. The gift of the other: Levinas and the politics of reproduction. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guenther, Lisa. 2008. Being-from-others: Reading Heidegger after Cavarero. Hypatia 23(1): 99–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time (trans: Macquarrie, J., and Robinson, E.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Honig, Bonnie (ed.). 1995. Feminist interpretations of Hannah Arendt. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1991. The Irigaray reader, ed. M. Whitford. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1986. Stabat mater. In The Kristeva reader, ed. Toril Moi, 160–186. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lispector, Clarice. 1988. The passion according to G. H. (trans: Sousa, R.W.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Mullin, Amy. 2005. Reconceiving pregnancy and childcare. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perpich, Diane. 2003. Subjectivity and sexual difference: New figures of the feminine in Irigaray and Cavarero. Continental Philosophy Review 36: 391–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alison Stone.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stone, A. Natality and mortality: rethinking death with Cavarero. Cont Philos Rev 43, 353–372 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-010-9148-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-010-9148-3

Keywords

Navigation