Skip to main content
Log in

Hybridizing Moral Expressivism and Moral Error Theory

  • Published:
The Journal of Value Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. See Daniel Boisvert, “Expressive-Assertivism,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 89, no. 2 (2008); see also David Copp, “Realist Expressivism: A Neglected Option for Moral Realism,” Social Philosophy and Policy, vol. 18, no. 2 (2001); Michael Ridge, “Ecumenical Expressivism: Finessing Frege,” Ethics vol. 116, no. 2 (2006); Ridge, “Ecumenical Expressivism: The Best of Both Worlds?” in Rush Shafer-Landau, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (2007); Mark Schroeder, “Hybrid Expressivism: Virtues and Vices,” Ethics, vol. 119, no. 2 (2009).

  2. See A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic (Mineola, N.Y: Dover, 1952), pp. 102–114; see also Simon Blackburn, “Attitudes and Contents,” in Essays in Quasi-Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); Blackburn, Spreading the Word (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984); Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990).

  3. See Richard Joyce, The Myth of Morality (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 2002); see also J. L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (London: Penguin, 1977).

  4. Mackie, op. cit., p. 35.

  5. See Russ Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 23–24.

  6. See Blackburn, Ruling Passions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 75.

  7. Ibid., p. 79.

  8. See Paul Horwich, Truth (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998).

  9. See James Dreier, “Meta-ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism,” Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 18, no. 1 (2004).

  10. Ibid., pp. 27–28.

  11. See Peter Geach, “Imperative and Deontic Logic,” Analysis, vol. 18, no. 3 (1958); see also Geach, “Ascriptivism,” Philosophical Review, vol. 69, no. 2 (1960); Geach, “Assertion,” The Philosophical Review, vol. 74, no. 4 (1965); John Searle, “Meaning and Speech Acts,” Philosophical Review, vol. 71, no. 4 (1962).

  12. Geach, “Assertion,” p. 463.

  13. See ibid., p. 449.

  14. See Blackburn, Spreading the Word, pp. 189–196; see also Gibbard, Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2003).

  15. See Blackburn, Spreading the Word, p. 195.

  16. See ibid., pp. 195–196.

  17. Mackie, op. cit, p. 35.

  18. See David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton eds. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 266.

  19. See Shafer-Landau, op. cit., p. 125.

  20. Ibid.

  21. See ibid., pp. 125–127.

  22. See Mackie, op. cit, p. 35; see also Joyce, op. cit., p. 9.

  23. See Joyce, op. cit., p. 5.

  24. See Mackie, op. cit., pp. 42–46.

  25. See ibid., p. 43.

  26. I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers and the Editor-in-Chief of the Journal of Value Inquiry, Thomas Magnell, for offering very helpful comments on this article. I am indebted also to David Agler for providing careful and insightful commentary on an early draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toby Svoboda.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Svoboda, T. Hybridizing Moral Expressivism and Moral Error Theory. J Value Inquiry 45, 37–48 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-011-9259-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-011-9259-z

Keywords

Navigation