Skip to main content

A Note on Stumpf’s History of Active Intellection

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 186 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 23))

Abstract

Carl Stumpf, in his Spinozastudien, presents the Aristotelico-Scholastic thesis of the “parallelism” between mental acts and contents, i.e., the thesis that “the essential differences and divisions of the acts run in parallel to those of the contents, since they are determined in their specificity by the latter.” In his paper, Stumpf also distinguishes between passive and active accounts of intellection in the history of philosophy. Now, Stumpf, in his own theory of intentionality, has rather an active account of intellection: he holds that the contents of abstract presentations and judgments are “products” of these acts. Stumpf does not explicitly give a historical precedent for his position. In this note, I would like to discuss Stumpf’s historical narrative concerning the active accounts of intellection, as well as to complete this narrative with information about some prior philosophical positions resembling Stumpf’s own views on psychic products.

I am grateful to V´eronique Decaix for her comments on a previous version of this paper and I thank Nicole Osborne for having checked my English.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an overview of the so-called “School of Brentano”, see Dewalque (2013).

  2. 2.

    On these questions, see Fisette and Martinelli (2015) and Martinelli (2011).

  3. 3.

    For more on Stumpf’s life, see the autobiographical information in Stumpf (1919a, 1924).

  4. 4.

    Stumpf (1906, 1907).

  5. 5.

    On the fact that Stumpf’s “states of affairs”, despite their name, are rather mental contents, see Chrudzimski (2015).

  6. 6.

    See Stumpf (1906, 24–26, 28–33; 1907, 6–10). Note that for Stumpf, besides concepts and propositions, there are other kinds of products, namely “aggregates” (Inbegriffe), i.e., results of synthesis, and “values”.

  7. 7.

    See notably the unpublished text of Pfänder quoted in Fr´echette (2015a, 151) and Reinach (1989, 526, n.1), the unpublished texts of Daubert quoted in Schuhmann (1987, 235–236), Ingarden (1931, 107–108, n.2), and Husserl (1974).

  8. 8.

    See Witasek (1908, 222–246), quoted in Twardowski (1996, 164, n.5).

  9. 9.

    Twardowski (1996).

  10. 10.

    See Bühler (1908a,b, 1933), quoted in Fisette (2014, 125–126). For Bühler’s relation to the School of Brentano, see Cesalli and Friedrich (2014).

  11. 11.

    On the notion of “product” in Stumpf, but also in Twardowski and the late Husserl, see Taieb (2018). For more on Stumpf’s influences on his contemporaries, see the relevant texts in Fisette and Martinelli (2015).

  12. 12.

    Brentano (2013, 468), quoted in Fr´echette (2015b, 278).

  13. 13.

    Martinelli (2011, 53).

  14. 14.

    Stumpf (1919b, 10) and, for a presentation of Stumpf’s text, Martinelli (2011). On the question of the adequacy of Stumpf’s interpretation of Spinoza, see Martinelli (2001), referred to in Martinelli (2011, 51, n.1).

  15. 15.

    See the references to Plato’s Republic and Theaetetus in Stumpf (1919b, 10–11).

  16. 16.

    See Stumpf (1919b, 11) where the claim is also widened to emotions in Aristotle.

  17. 17.

    On all this, see Stumpf (1919b, 12–16, 23), and the references given there.

  18. 18.

    See Stumpf (1919b, 17–18; 1939–1940, 196), the latter quoted in Martinelli (2011, 62).

  19. 19.

    See Stumpf (1919b, 11 and 20).

  20. 20.

    Strikingly, Brentano says that the images or phantasms contain “concepts” (Begriffe), and that the possible intellect is “the possibility for all concepts” (die Möglichkeit für alle Begriffe).

  21. 21.

    See Brentano (1867, especially 163–229), as well as the shorter presentations in Brentano (1986, 139–146, 151–153, 352–353).

  22. 22.

    See Stumpf (1919a, 89–91; 1924, 5; 1869, 108, n.1); and, for information on the lectures on history of philosophy given by Brentano in Würzburg, Hedwig (1980, XXIV, n.3).

  23. 23.

    See Stumpf (1919b, 20) discussing Ethics II, def. III.

  24. 24.

    Francisco Su´arez, In De anima, III, ch. 4 (ed. S. Castellote, vol. 2, d. 5, q. 4).

  25. 25.

    See mainly Duns Scotus, Ordinatio, I, d.3, p.3, q.2 (referred to by Su´arez as “d.3, q.7”, this question indeed being the seventh if the parts of the distinction are ignored) and Quod., XV. On these questions, see Cross (2014, above all 138–149) and Pini (2015, especially 96, n. 47).

  26. 26.

    Francisco Su´arez, In De anima, III, ch. 4 (ed. S. Castellote, vol. 2, d. 5, q. 4). On these questions, see Aho (2007, especially 199–203). Besides, as pointed out by Aho (2007, 193–194), Su´arez, in his commentary on the De anima, holds that the agent intellect and the possible intellect are one and the same power.

  27. 27.

    Stumpf (1919b, 21, n.1).

  28. 28.

    See Stumpf (1919b, 15, n.1).

  29. 29.

    See Aristotle, Met. IX.6.1048b18–36 and IX.8.1050a23–1050b2.

  30. 30.

    On these questions, see Duns Scotus, Quod., XIII, a.3 and Pini (2015).

  31. 31.

    Francisco Su´arez, In De anima, II, ch. 2, Opera III, n15, quoted in Stumpf (1919b, 15–16, n.2). Cf. ed. S. Castellote, vol. 2, d. 3, q. 2, where the text is slightly different, but the idea is the same.

  32. 32.

    See the presentation of these questions in Burns (1964) and Lec´on (2013), as well as the passages of Su´arez, Disputationes metaphysicae 42, 43, 48, quoted there. For an earlier account of immanent acts and actions, see Francisco Su´arez, In De anima, II, ch. 2 (ed. S. Castellote, vol. 2, d. 3, q. 2), quoted above, as well as In De anima, III, ch. 5 (ed. S. Castellote, vol. 2, d. 5, q. 5). On the fact that the commentary on the De anima precedes the Disputationes metaphysicae, and on Su´arez’s project to rewrite the commentary, see Aho (2007, 181–182).

  33. 33.

    For Augustine, see De Trinitate, XI, II, 2 and Caston (2001). More broadly on the notion of “intention”, see Sol`ere (2007). On Scotus’ claim that “attention” belongs to the will, not to the cognitive powers, and thus that it is unable to render cognition itself active, see Ordinatio, I, d.3, p.3, q.2, Vat. III, n470. For the relation between “intention” and “attention” in Su´arez, see Aho (2007, 201–203). See Stumpf (1919b, 48), for a brief mention of the Scholastic notion of “intention”, a notion, however, that Stumpf seems to apply to “intentional” acts in general, i.e., independently of their active or passive character.

  34. 34.

    Stumpf refers to Jacob Martini, but the most famous passage on this distinction is in Su´arez, Disputationes metaphysicae (see disp. 2, sec. 1, n.1).

  35. 35.

    Stumpf (1919b, 20, n.2), quoting Thomas Aquinas, “Declaratio quorundam articulorum contra Graecos etc.”; cf. in the Leonina edition De rationibus fidei ad Cantorem Antiochenum, 3.

  36. 36.

    See notably Thomas Aquinas, Contra gentiles, I, 53; De potentia, q.8, a.1, resp.; ST, Ia, q.85, a.2.

  37. 37.

    Thomas Aquinas, De potentia, q.8, a.1, resp.; ST, Ia, q.27, a.1. On these questions, see again Pini (2015).

  38. 38.

    Thomas Aquinas, ST, Ia, q.85, a.2. On these two kinds of intellection, and on the third one, “reasoning”, i.e. the logical combination of judgments, see Perler (2002, 61) and Thomas Aquinas, In De interpretatione.

  39. 39.

    See Augustine, De Trinitate XV, XII, 2 and Lonergan (1967).

  40. 40.

    Stöckl (1865, 463–464). Stöckl (1865) is quoted in Stumpf (1919b, 15 n.1).

  41. 41.

    Brentano (1980, 57–58). For the date of the lecture notes, see Hedwig (1980, XXIV, n.3).

  42. 42.

    See Stumpf (1919a, 87–110; 1924, 6).

  43. 43.

    Brentano (1924, 125, n.1).

  44. 44.

    There is a brief reference to Augustine in Stumpf (1919b, 13), but not to the notion of “word”.

  45. 45.

    See Brentano (1982).

References

  • Aho, T. (2007). Suarez on cognitive intentions. In P. J. J. Bakker & H. Thijssen (Eds.), Mind, perception, and cognition. The commentary tradition of Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 179–203). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine (1968). In W. J. Mountain (Ed.), De Trinitate libri XV. Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1867). Die Psychologie des Aristoteles, insbesondere seine Lehre vom NOUS POIETICOS. Mainz: Franz Kirchheim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1924). In O. Kraus (Ed.), Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (Vol. 1). Leipzig: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1980). In K. Hedwig (Ed.), Geschichte der mittelalterlichen Philosophie im christlichen Abendland. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1982). In R. M. Chisholm & W. Baumgartner (Eds.), Deskriptive psychologie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1986). In R. George (Ed.), Über Aristoteles. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (2013). In G. Fr´echette (Ed.), Abstraction und Relation; In D. Fisette & G. Fr´echette (Eds.), Themes from Brentano (pp. 465–482). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1908a). [Beschprechung von] C. Stumpf, Erscheinungen und psychische Funktionen. Abh. der Berl. Akad., phil-hist. Kl. 1906. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 11 (Literaturbericht), 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1908b). Antwort auf die von W. Wundt erhobenen Einwände gegen die Methode der Selbstbeobachtung an experimentell erzeugten Erlebnissen. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 12, 93–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1933). Die Axiomatik der Sprachwissenschaften. Kant-Studien, 38, 19–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burns, J. P. (1964). Action in Su´arez. The New Scholasticism, 38, 453–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2001). Augustine and the Greeks on intentionality. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 23–48). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cesalli, L. & Friedrich, J. (Eds.). (2014). Anton Marty and Karl Bühler. Between mind and language. Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrudzimski, A. (2015). Carl Stumpf über Sachverhalte. In D. Fisette & R. Martinelli (Eds.), Philosophy from an empirical standpoint. Essays on Carl Stumpf (pp. 173–202). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, R. (2014). Duns Scotus’s theory of cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewalque, A. (2013). Schema of the Brentano School intellectual progeny. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12, 445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duns Scotus, J. (1950). In Commissio Scotistica (Ed.), Opera omnia (20 vol.). Civitas Vaticana: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duns Scotus, J. (1968). In F. Alluntis (Ed.), Cuestiones cuodlibetales. Madrid: La Editorial Cat´olica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisette, D. (2014). Ph´enom`enes sensibles et fonctions psychiques: Karl Bühler et le programme de Stumpf. In L. Cesalli & J. Friedrich (Eds.), Anton Marty and Karl Bühler. Between mind and language (pp. 103–140). Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisette, D. & Martinelli, R. (Eds.). (2015). Philosophy from an empirical standpoint. Essays on Carl Stumpf. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fr´echette, G. (2015a). Essential laws. On ideal objects and their properties in early phenomenology. In B. Leclercq, S. Richard, & D. Seron (Eds.), Objects and pseudo-objects. Ontological deserts and jungles from Brentano to Carnap (pp. 143–166). Berlin-Boston: De Gruyter-Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fr´echette, G. (2015b). Stumpf on abstraction. In D. Fisette & R. Martinelli (Eds.), Philosophy from an empirical standpoint. Essays on Carl Stumpf (pp. 263–292). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedwig, K. (1980). Zur Textgestaltung der Ausgabe. In K. Hedwig (Ed.), Franz Brentano. Geschichte der mittelalterlichen Philosophie im christlichen Abendland (pp. XXII–XXIV). Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1974). In P. Janssen (Ed.), Formale and transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft (Husserliana XVII). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1931). Das literarische Kunstwerk. Eine Untersuchung aus dem Grenzgebiet der Ontologie, Logik und Literaturwissenschaft. Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lec´on, M. (2013). Francis Su´arez on the efficiency of substantial forms. Review of Metaphysics, 67, 107–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lonergan, B. (1967). In D. B. Burrell (Ed.), Verbum: Word and idea in Aquinas. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press; Re-edition in: B. J. F. Lonergan. In F.E. Crowe & R.M. Doran (Eds.), Collected works of Bernard Lonergan. Vol. 2. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinelli, R. (2001). Intenzionalit`a della sostanza. Carl Stumpf interprete di Spinoza. Discipline Filosofiche, 11, 399–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinelli, R. (2011). Intentionality and God’s mind: Stumpf on Spinoza. In G.-J. Boudewijnse & S. Bonacchi (Eds.), Carl Stumpf. From philosophical reflection to interdisciplinary scientific investigation (pp. 51–67). Wien: Krammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perler, D. (2002). Theorien der Intentionalität im Mittelalter. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato (1900–1907), In J. Burnet (Ed.), Opera (4 vol.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pini, G. (2015). Two models of thinking. Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus on occurrent thoughts. In G. Klima (Ed.), Intentionality, cognition and mental representation in medieval philosophy (pp. 81–103). New York: Fordham University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1989). Zum Begriff der Zahl (1913/1914). In K. Schuhmann & B. Smith (Eds.), Sämtliche Werke. Textkritische Ausgabe (Vol. 1, pp. 515–527). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuhmann, K. (1987). Johannes Dauberts Kritik der ‘Theorie des negativen Urteils’ von Adolf Reinach. In K. Mulligan (Ed.), Speech act and Sachverhalt. Reinach and the foundations of realist phenomenology (pp. 227–238). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sol`ere, J.-L. (2007). Tension et intention. Esquisse de l’histoire d’une notion. In L. Couloubaritsis & A. Mazz`u (Eds.), Questions sur l’intentionnalitˊe (pp. 59–124). Bruxelles: Ousia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza (1925–1987). In C. Gebhardt (Ed.), Opera (5 vol.). Heidelberg: Carl Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöckl, A. (1865). Geschichte der Philosophie Des Mittelalters (3 vol.). Mainz: Franz Kirchheim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1869). Verhältnis des platonischen Gottes zur Idee des Guten. Halle: C.E.M. Pfeffer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1883–1890). Tonpsychologie (2 vol.). Leipzig: S. Hirzel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1902). Über Abstraction und Generalisation. Sitzungsberichte der königlich-preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, XXVII, 593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1906). Erscheinungen und psychische Funktionen. Abhandlungen der königlich-preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (pp. 3–40). Berlin: Verlag der königlich Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1907). Zur Einteilung der Wissenschaften. Abhandlungen der königlich-preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (pp. 1–94). Berlin: Verlag der königlich Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1919a). Erinnerungen an Franz Brentano. In O. Kraus (Ed.), Franz Brentano. Zur Kenntnis seines Lebens und seiner Lehre (pp. 87–149). München: C. H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1919b). Spinozastudien. Abhandlungen der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Philosophisch-historische Klasse, 4, 1–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1924). Carl Stumpf. In R. Schmidt (Ed.), Die Philosophie der Gegenwart in Selbstdarstellung (Vol. 5, pp. 1–61). Leipzig: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. (1939–1940). Erkenntnislehre (2 vol.). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taieb, H. (2018). Building objective thoughts: Stumpf, Twardowski and the late Husserl on psychic products. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 100, 336–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski, K. (1996). In J. Brandl (Ed.), Funktionen und Gebilde. Conceptus, 39, 157–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witasek, S. (1908). Grundlinien der Psychologie. Leipzig: Verlag der Dürr’schen Buchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hamid Taieb .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Taieb, H. (2020). A Note on Stumpf’s History of Active Intellection. In: Decaix, V., Mora-Márquez, A. (eds) Active Cognition. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-35304-9_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics