Descartes proseminar - second half breakdown Skepticism and its Legacy (first 1 1/2 weeks) i) Skepticism about the external world: Skepticism in some form or another is a philosophical perennial, but even so it is not unreasonable to suggest that with Descartes, skepticism of an entirely new form made its first appearance on stage. Descartes deployed a radical doubt about the external world, with methodical ambitions, and in doing so he might be taken to have raised the stakes for epistemology. What if the Cartesian response to Skepticism fails? Is our ordinary knowledge of the world impeached if we cannot refute the hypothesis that we are dreaming, or that we are the playthings of a malign demon? There is also a historical question: is Cartesian skepticism interestingly different from the Pyrrhonian and academic skepticism that was "in play" long before Descartes? Contemporary: Barry Stroud - The Significance of Philosophical Skepticism ch. 1,2 Ancient: Miles Burnyeat: "Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed " Thompson Clarke "The Legacy of Skepticism" Background and secondary reading: G. Rodis-Lewis "Doute Pratique et Doute Spéculatif chez Montaigne et Descartes" David Lewis "Elusive Knowledge" James Joyce "The Lasting Legacy of Skepticism" O.K. Bowsma "Descartes' Evil Genius" ii) Logical Skepticism and Circles: The Justification of Deduction In the first half we addressed various scholarly issues surrounding the interpretation of the "Cartesian Circle". The problem Descartes faces in justifying the reliance on clear and distinct ideas may be taken to be a specific manifestation what Henry Scheffer is said to have called "the logocentric predicament". On natural understandings of what "justification" consists in, it might seem to be impossible to give any noncircular justification of logical principles, since any justification at all seems to employ or presuppose the correctness of at least some of those principles. So what are justifications, and can we have justifications of logical principles? Does the Cartesian Circle point to a "Problem of Deduction" dual to Hume's "Problem of Induction"? This issue forms the background to a substantial body of work in recent scholarship on Frege, Russell, and the early Wittgenstein. Some attention will be devoted to charting this topic as it shows itself in this literature. Some contributions to this issue are: Susan Haack - "The Justification of Deduction" Lewis Carroll - "What the Tortoise said to Achilles" Michael Dummett: "The Justification of Deduction" and The Logical Basis of Metaphysics ch. 8, ch. 11-13 [Plus revisit the Frankfurt material discussed earlier] Secondary, and Background Readings: J. Tappenden: "Metatheory and Mathematical Practice in Frege" (plus another JT paper if it is ready) T. Ricketts "Objectivity and Objecthood: Frege's Metaphysics of Judgement", "Frege's 1906 Foray into Metatheory", "Logic and Truth in Frege" Christopher Peacocke: "Sense and Justification" Arthur Prior "Roundabout the Runabout Inference-Ticket" (known colloquially as "the Tonk paper") J.S. Mill on the Syllogism, from his "Logic" Paralogisms - personal identity, the mental (second 1 1/2 weeks) i) Kant's diagnosis of the (?) flaws in the Cogito argument There have been many attempts to defuse Descartes' conclusion that "I am, I exist" is certain. One of the most difficult and fascinating is Kant's analysis in the section of the first Critique entitled "Paralogisms of Pure Reason". In a nutshell, Kant's suggestion is that "I think" is in a certain sense ambiguous. One notion of "I think" expresses the existence of the self as a thinking thing that can be the object of inner experience - as a thing that exists in space and time, which is subject to the conditions on the possibility of experience. "I think" in this sense asserts the knowledge of the self as a thing with a property, but, Kant suggests, it is not certain and necessary. The other sense is more difficult to explain briefly, but it is approximately the following. "I think" does not predicate any property of a thing, but rather it corresponds to a unifying principle on possible experience. In order for us to have knowledge of the world, it must be that distinct experiences can be represented as parts of a single unified experience. Insofar as "I think" expresses this formal condition on possible experience, it is necessary, but it does not express knowledge of the existence of any thing, so "I exist" in the desired sense doesn't follow. P.F. Strawson has revived this analysis of the Cogito and has extended the basic insight to illuminate other philosophical problems of personal identity and self- knowledge. Kant - Paralogisms of Pure Reason (B version) from the Critique of Pure Reason P. F. Strawson The Bounds of Sense p. 162 - 174 John McDowell "Referring to Oneself" with Strawson's reply Secondary and Background Readings: L. Wittgenstein "The Blue and Brown Books" pp. 66-67 E. Anscombe: "The First Person" Strawson "Kant's Paralogisms: Self-Consciousness and the "Outside Observer" David Lewis: "Attitudes De Dicto and De Se" John Perry "The Essential Indexical" ii) Content and Self-Knowledge One of the topics that arises in Meditation II, and shows itself again unexpectedly in Meditation III is the connection between the content of our thoughts and the potential we have for ascertaining that content merely by introspective scrutiny. One legacy of the Meditations seems to be the idea that our conscious thought has the property of Cartesian Transparency: At least some of the properties of thoughts - their content, perhaps, or their logical properties - must be (at least in principle)accessible by reflection alone to the person thinking those thoughts. This assumption is in tension with the apparent conclusion of a cluster of arguments proposed by Burge, Putnam and Kripke, among others. These arguments suggest that the content of a belief, or of the sentences whose utterance can express a belief, could depend crucially on facts in the world that are independent of our state of mind. Similarly, it could be suggested that we might need empirical information in addition to ascertain some of the logical consequences of our beliefs. Core Readings: Tyler Burge "Individualism and the Mental" Robert Stalnaker "Narrow Content" Paul Boghossian "Content and Self-Knowledge" Saul Kripke "A Puzzle about Belief" Week 4 Cartesian Geometry and Cartesian Method Descartes contributions to geometry, and his attitudes to geometric practice, raise questions of method that are interesting both in connection with his philosophical methods, and in their own right. In the three upcoming meetings, three of these topics will be examined. First of all, one clear result of Cartesian innovations in geometry is that they deliver a natural unification of phenomena that might have otherwise seemed unconnected. This happens in several ways: entire theories are consolidated, and on a smaller scale, new classifications are devised which group together geometrical objects in a newly natural seeming way. What kind of advance in understanding does such an innovation represent? A second question pertains to what one might call the "fruitfulness" of methods. It counts in favor of a method of investigation that it is in some sense "easy to use". What is the metaphysical significance of a fact like that? Monday: Unification and Explanation Emily Grosholz "Descartes' Unification of Algebra and Geometry" Michael Friedman "Explanation and Scientific Understanding" Steven Gaukroger "The Nature of Abstract Reasoning: Philosophical Aspects of Descartes' Work in Algebra" (in Cambridge Companion to Descartes) [JT - Notes on Unification in mathematics] Optional Background and Secondary Reading: Humphries "Greater Unification Equals Greater Understanding?" P. Kitcher a section of "------" Wednesday: Analysis and Synthesis I) "context of discovery"/ "context of justification" Core Readings: Reread: Ed Curley "Analysis in the Meditations: The Quest for Clear and Distinct Ideas", plus "Spinoza as an Expositor of Descartes" and the Garber and Cohen riposte [these will have been read in the first half] Jaakko Hintikka and Uwe Remes: selections from The Method of Analysis "J. Tappenden "Extending Knowledge and 'Fruitful Concepts': Fregean Themes in the Philosophy of Mathematics" S. Gaukroger "Discovery and Proof" (Chapter 3 of Cartesian Logic) Arnauld and Nicole Logic or the Art of Thinking (The "Port- Royal Logic") Fourth Part "On Method" ch. 1 - ch. 11 Optional Background and Secondary Reading: G. Gigerenzer: "Where do New Ideas Come From?" Week 5 Monday: Analysis and Synthesis II: "Styles of Reasoning" The distinction of analysis and synthesis prompts us to ask what attitude we should take to situations where patterns of reasoning about a subject-matter are importantly different in key ways. Core Reading: Ian Hacking - "'Style' for Historians and Philosophers" Optional Background and Secondary Reading: J. Tappenden: "Proof Style and Axiom Choice in Mathematics" The Ontological Argument The Meditation V argument puts me in mind of Twain's remarks about Wagner's music: "It's better than it sounds." It seems evidently wrong, yet a diagnosis of just how it fails, or even a secure verdict that it fails, is hard to pin down. Many of the customary objections don't seem to hold water. (For example, JT and EC are in agreement that the old standby "Existence is not a property/predicate/perfection/ what have you)is a red herring. But it appears we are not completely of one mind as to why. That sort of thing happens a lot when this argument is taken seriously.) Some recent discussions of the argument show it to be bound up with quite delicate modal principles. Plantinga even maintains (reservedly) that the argument is sound. Wednesday - The argument revisited; the necessary elementary modal logic Notes from JT: all (or most, or at least some...) of the modal logic you need to know to puzzle out the ontological argument. Anselm: Prosologium selection and Gaunilon appendix David Lewis: "Anselm and Actuality" Plantinga: The Nature of Necessity Chapter 9 and 10 (though chapter 9 will only be relevant to Wednesday's meeting) J. Mackie Miracle of Theism ch. 3 Week 6 - Free Will and Responsibility In Meditation IV, Descartes has a brief, but striking characterization of free will. Its role in the overall meditations is to insulate the thesis that God is no deceiver from the undeniable fact that Descartes has erred on some occasions in the past. If Descartes' mistaken judgements were Free choices on his part, then Descartes, not God, should bear the responsibility for them. This reflects a broader, venerable debate about the extent to which a Creator would be untainted by responsibility for the evil freely done by the beings He created. Descartes' characterization of free will also prompts questions of a more basic sort like: "*That's* free will???" Which of course leads to the further question: "Well, if not that, what??" Wednesday's meeting will be devoted to some of the more penetrating recent ruminations on what Free will is and what difference having it could make. Monday - The Free Will Defense J. Mackie Miracle of Theism ch. 9 A. Plantinga Ch. 9 Background and secondary: J.L. Mackie "Evil and Omnipotence" Mind 1955 Wednesday - "Could have done otherwise?" - Determination and Freedom Harry Frankfurt "Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility" P.F. Strawson - "Freedom And Resentment" Susan Wolf - "The Importance of Free Will" Background and secondary: B. Williams: "Deciding to Believe" E. Curley: "Descartes, Spinoza and the Ethics of Belief" (reread)