Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T01:48:09.540Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Philosophy of Normativity, or How to Try Clearing Things Up a Little

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 October 2011

Christine Tappolet
Affiliation:
Université de Montréal
Alan Voizard
Affiliation:
Université du Québec à Montréal

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 For evidence of this, here are the titles of an impressive number of works that make direct reference to it: Dancy 2000; Copp 2001; Tappolet & Weinstock 2001; Schaber 2004; Wallace 2005; Hattiangadi 2007; Wedgwood 2007; Cuneo 2007; Thomson 2008; Robertson 2009; Greco 2010; De Caro & Macarthur 2010; as well as Korsgaard 1996, which one could say started a trend.

2 The term “norm” is borrowed from the Latin term norma, which means set square, but also rule or law, and which itself is derived from the Greek, gnomon, which also means set square.

3 For the distinction between the evaluative and the deontic, see Ogien and Tappolet 2009 and Tappolet 2011.

4 Among those who subscribe to one form or another of internalism we find Hare 1952, Davidson 1986, Smith 1994, Korsgaard 1996 and Wedgwood 2007. On the externalist side, there is Railton 1986, Brink 1997, Copp 1997, Svavarsdottir 1999 and Shafer-Landau 2003.

5 Utilitarianism, 1963, chap. 3.

6 See, among others, Sidgwick 1907; Moore 1922; Hare 1952, and Smith 1994.

7 Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, 1739-1740.

8 Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785.