Skip to main content
Log in

Quantum metametaphysics

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Say that metaphysical indeterminacy occurs just when there is a fact such that neither it nor its negation obtains. The aim of this work is to shed light on the issue of whether orthodox quantum mechanics provides any evidence of metaphysical indeterminacy by discussing the logical, semantic, and broadly methodological presuppositions of the debate. I argue that the dispute amounts to a verbal disagreement between classical and quantum logicians, given Eli Hirsch’s account of substantivity; but that it need not be so if Ted Sider’s naturalness-based account of substantivity is adopted instead. Given the latter approach, can anything be said in order to tip the balance of the dispute either way? Some prima facie reasonable constraints on naturalness entail that the classicist is right, and the quantum world is therefore determinate. Nevertheless, there are reasons for weakening those constraints, to the effect that the dispute remains very much open. Finally, I discuss alternative accounts of metaphysical indeterminacy, and argue that they are unsuitable for framing the quantum indeterminacy debate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Representational indeterminacy is usually construed along semantic or epistemic lines. The locus classicus for a semantic treatment of representational indeterminacy is Fine (1975). The alternative, epistemic account dates back to Williamson (1994).

  2. Among the proposed accounts of metaphysical indeterminacy are Akiba (2004), Barnes and Williams (2011), Torza (2020a), Williams (2008b), Williamson (2003) and Wilson (2013).

  3. For an overview of the state of the art on quantum indeterminacy, see Calosi and Mariani (2021).

  4. The issue is illustrated by the characterization of MI put forward in Torza (2020a), according to which MI occurs just when (roughly) there is a sentence in a semantically nondefective language \(\mathcal {L}\) which is neither true nor false. As Torza points out, his characterization runs into false positives of MI unless one assumes (i) a Russellian account of definite descriptions, and (ii) either a negative or a positive free semantics for \(\mathcal {L}\).

  5. Although facts can be taken to be metaphysically fundamental (Rayo 2017; Turner 2016), I will refrain from taking sides on such matters, which are orthogonal to the present concerns.

  6. Note that in ind by ‘negation’ I mean an objective, worldly operation in logical space mapping facts to facts, and not a linguistic, representational operator mapping formulas to formulas.

  7. It goes without saying that this way of modeling logical space does not commit one to full-blown modal realism, or to any substantive thesis typically associated with Lewisean metaphysics, since in the present context ‘world’ is being used merely as an umbrella term compatible with alternative views about the foundations of modality.

  8. Although the orthodox interpretation is often paired with an instrumentalist attitude toward quantum theory, it seems to me that a realist reading is more natural. Indeed, the eigenstate-eigenvalue link, which establishes a connection between formalism and physical properties, is incompatible with some of the main available realist interpretations. (Similar considerations carry over to the Criterion of Reality discussed later in this section.) Cf. Bokulich (2014, p. 460 fn. 14) for a defense of a realist attitude toward the orthodox interpretation.

  9. A Hilbert space is defined as a complete vector space with an inner product. Hilbert spaces can be finitely or infinitely dimensional. Although I will restrict my attention to the finite case, the metaphysical moral discussed here carries over to infinitely dimensional spaces.

  10. But see Glick (2017) for a dissenting voice.

  11. Could one accept the Criterion of Reality while denying cr on the grounds that the ‘element of physical reality’ need not be the predicted property itself? That is certainly an admissible view, but not the intended one in the EPR paper: “in the state given by [\(\psi =e^{(2\pi i/h)}p_{0}x\)], the momentum has certainly the value \(p_{0}\). It thus has meaning to say that the momentum of the particle in the state given by [that equation] is real” Einstein et al. (1935, p. 778, my emphasis).

  12. Proof: The Born rule, which specifies the probabilities of quantum experiments, tells us that if \(|\psi \rangle =\alpha _{1}|\psi _{1}\rangle +\ldots +\alpha _{n}|\psi _{n}\rangle \) and S obtains at \(|\psi _{i}\rangle \) then \(\mathrm {Pr}(S,|\psi \rangle )=|\alpha _{i}|^{2}\), where \(|\alpha _{1}|^{2}+\ldots +|\alpha _{n}|^{2}=1\). Since S is assumed to obtain at \(|\psi _{i}\rangle \), for each \(i\le n\), then \(\mathrm {Pr}(S,|\psi \rangle )=1\). By cr, we can conclude that S obtains at \(|\psi \rangle \).

  13. Putnam (1968) argued that quantum logic is the one true logic; and that the paradoxes of quantum mechanics, especially the measurement problem, are solved by adopting quantum logic (cf. Bacciagaluppi 2009). What I have said so far does not entail either of Putnam’s theses. Indeed, quantum logic’s being the correct logic for modeling reasoning about quantum systems is compatible with both quantum logic’s not being the one true logic, and with the measurement problem’s not being solvable by appealing to quantum logic. Nevertheless, the question whether classical or quantum logic is the the one true logic is relevant to the present debate, and I will return to it in Sect. 5.

  14. It is worth noting that MI is prima facie compatible with conservatism about logic. Indeed, the account of MI due to Wilson (2013) is formulated against the backdrop of a classical and bivalent logic (but see Sect. 7 for criticism). Likewise, the model theory of MI developed by Barnes and Williams (2011) validates all classical schemas and inference rules, and makes every (semantically precise) statement either true or false. However, the Barnes–Williams strategy is precisificational and, as I explain in Sect. 7, precisificational approaches have proven unsuitable to modeling quantum indeterminacy. Moreover, the Barnes–Williams model recovers bivalence by driving a wedge between truth and determinacy, insofar as it does not validate the inference from p to Dp (where D is an object-language metaphysical determinacy operator), while failing to explain what it means for the world to contain a truthmaker for the former but not the latter. Cameron (2011) suggests that it amounts to p’s truthmaker to exist but not definitely so, which merely pushes the bump under the rug.)

  15. This inference assumes the eigenstate-eigenvalue link: a quantum system has property O with value \(\lambda \) iff the quantum state of the system is in an eigenstate of the associated operator \(\hat{O}\) with eigenvalue \(\lambda \). The eigenstate-eigenvalue link is a tenet of the orthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics (Sect. 3.2). It is worth noting however that David Wallace has argued that the eigenstate-eigenvalue link has never belonged to the orthodox interpretation (Wallace 2012), and that it is false (Wallace 2019). See Gilton (2016) for a defense of the eigenstate-eigenvalue link as a traditional component of the orthodox interpretation. Whether the link is indeed correct is a question that lies beyond the scope of this work.

  16. I will be assuming that sentences such as ‘t is in region R’ or ‘t has z-spin’ are covert compound categorical sentences analyzable as ‘t has location \(x_{1}\) or...or \(x_{n}\) (and R is the fusion of \(x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n}\))’ and ‘t has z-spin up or z-spin down’, respectively. In Sect. 7, I will consider—and ultimately reject—an alternative interpretation, due to Jessica Wilson, to the effect that an expression like ‘...has z-spin’ does not ascribe a disjunctive property of z-spin determinates, but rather a nondisjunctive z-spin determinable property.

  17. In fact, probability talk is dispensable in the atomic case, as the two parties assign the same interpretation to the primitive physical vocabulary. For sake of uniformity, however, I will deploy a probabilistic paraphrase throughout.

  18. For an assessment of the metaphysical underpinnings of logical realism see McSweeney (2019).

  19. In fact, Sider’s own formulation of naturalness is quasi-syntactical, insofar as it employs a primitive ‘structural’ operator applying to linguistic items (predicates, operators etc), rather than worldly items (properties, operations etc). Although Sider’s formulation enjoys greater generality, as it does not presuppose any particular metaphysics of higher-order entities, due to my concern with MI I will stick to a worldly formulation in accordance with the Lewisean spirit.

  20. For an alternative way of implementing I and II in a definition of verbal disagreement, see Torza (2020b).

  21. This formulation of the criterion presupposes that the Best System is unique, which is highly unlikely. I am setting aside this complication, although the interested reader can see Donaldson (2014), Torza (2020b), sec. 3 for discussion and alternative formulations of indispensability.

  22. Cf. (Sider 2011, sec. 9.6.2) for a parallel argument to the effect that classical first-order quantification is natural.

  23. Barnes (2010) discusses an alternative definition of MI to the effect that, roughly, MI occurs just in case there is a sentence p and a fact F such that F is a truthmaker for p, and it is indeterminate whether F exists in actuality. Since the definition quantifies over sentences, it also fails to satisfy my constraint.

  24. A variation on the BW approach that restores the possibility of quantum MI by rejecting the precisificational account while retaining the machinery of ersatz worlds is put forward in Torza (2020a). For further discussion of the BW approach vis-à-vis quantum MI, see Calosi and Wilson (2019). Darby and Pickup (2021) have tried to save the precisificational view by appealing to situation semantics; but see Corti (2021) for a critique of the situation-theoretic approach.

  25. “Determinables are not analyzable as disjunctions (or indeed, as any construction of maximal determinates); and [...] it is core to a determinable-based approach to MI that determinables are not so reducible” (Calosi and Wilson 2021).

  26. That a determinable-involving fact such as P is necessary for the system at hand is not uncontroversial. Indeed, some have argued that, say, z-spin talk is simply unintelligible when e’s z-spin value is indeterminate (cf. Albert 2009, p. 38).

  27. I would like to thank Samuel Fletcher, David Glick, Peter Lewis, Elias Okon and the UNAM Metaphysics Seminar for their helpful feedback, as well as audiences at the Quantum Indeterminacy workshop at Dartmouth College, and the 2020 Meeting of the APA Central in Chicago. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees for their thoughtful and generous comments. This work was supported by a PASPA-dgapa sabbatical fellowship which allowed me to spend two semesters at Rutgers University.

References

  • Akiba, K. (2004). Vagueness in the world. Noûs, 38, 407–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. Z. (2009). Quantum mechanics and experience. Harvard University Press.

  • Bacciagaluppi, G. (2009). Is logic empirical? In K. Engesser, D. Gabbay, & D. Lehmann (Eds.), Handbook of quantum logic and quantum structures: Quantum logic (pp. 49–78). Elsevier.

  • Barnes, E. (2010). Ontic Vagueness: A guide for the perplexed. Noûs, 44(4), 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E., & Williams, J. R. G. (2011). A Theory of Metaphysical Indeterminacy. In D. Zimmerman & K. Bennett (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Vol. 6, pp. 103–48). Oxford University Press.

  • Birkhoff, G., & von Neumann, J. (1936). The logic of quantum mechanics. The Annals of Mathematics, 37(4), 823–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2014). Metaphysical indeterminacy, properties, and quantum theory. Research Philosophica, 91(3), 449–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Mariani, C. (2021). Quantum indeterminacy. Philosophy Compass.

  • Calosi, C., & Wilson, J. M. (2019). Quantum metaphysical indeterminacy. Philosophical Studies, 176, 2599–2627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Wilson, J. M. (2021). Quantum indeterminacy and the double-slit experiment. Philosophical Studies.

  • Cameron, R. (2011). Truthmaking for presentists. In D. Zimmerman & K. Bennett (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6, pp. 55–100). Oxford University Press.

  • Chen, E. K. (forthcoming). Fundamental nomic vagueness. Philosophical Review.

  • Corti, A. (2021). Yet again, quantum indeterminacy is not worldly indecision. Synthese.

  • Darby, G. (2010). Quantum mechanics and metaphysical indeterminacy. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88(2), 227–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darby, G., & Pickup, M. (2021). Modelling deep indeterminacy. Synthese, 198, 1685–1710.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). On the plurality of grounds. Philosophers’ Imprint 14.

  • Donaldson, T. (2014). Reading the book of the world. Philosophical Studies, 172(4), 1051–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47(10), 777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, M. (2011). Being metaphysically unsettled: Barnes and Williams on metaphysical indeterminacy and vagueness. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford Studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6). Oxford University Press.

  • Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30(3–4), 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, D. (2017). Against quantum indeterminacy. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 6(3), 204–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2009). Ontology and alternative languages. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics. Oxford University Press.

  • Hirsch, E. (2011). Quantifier variance and realism: essays in Metaontology. Oxford University Press.

  • Gilton, M. J. R. (2016). Whence the eigenstate-eigenvalue link? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 55, 92–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Blackwell.

  • Lewis, D. K. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1984). Putnam’s paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62(3), 221–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Lewis, P. J. (2016). Quantum ontology: A guide to the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford University Press.

  • Lowe, E. J. (1994). Vague Identity and quantum indeterminacy. Analysis, 54(2), 110–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1999). Vague identity and quantum indeterminacy: Further reflections. Analysis, 59(264), 328–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2014). What Bell did. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical, 47(42), 424010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McSweeney, M. M. (2019). Logical realism and the metaphysics of logic. Philosophy Compass, 14(1), e12563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, G. H. (1980). The model-theoretic argument against realism. Philosophy of Science, 47(1), 69–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H. W. (1995). E. J. Lowe on vague identity and quantum indeterminacy. Analysis, 55(1), 14–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1968). Is logic empirical? In R. Cohen & M. Wartofsky (Eds.), Boston studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 5, pp. 216–241). Reidel.

  • Rayo, A. (2017). The world is the totality of facts. Not of things. Philosophical Issues, 27(1), 250–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford University Press.

  • Skow, B. (2010). Deep metaphysical indeterminacy. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(241), 851–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torza, A. (2020). Quantum metaphysical indeterminacy and worldly incompleteness. Synthese, 197, 4251–4264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torza, A. (2020). Structural indeterminacy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 101(2), 365–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. (2016). The facts in logical space: A tractarian ontology. Oxford University Press.

  • Wallace, D. (2012). Decoherence and its role in the modern measurement problem. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 370(1975), 4576–4593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2019). What is orthodox quantum mechanics? In A. Cordero (Ed.), Philosophers look at quantum mechanics. Springer.

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2008). Ontic vagueness and metaphysical indeterminacy. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 763–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2008). Multiple actualities and ontically vague identity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(230), 134–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. Routledge.

  • Williamson, T. (2003). Vagueness in reality. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

  • Wilson, J. M. (2012). Fundamental determinables. Philosophers’ Imprint 12.

  • Wilson, J. M. (2013). A determinable-based account of metaphysical indeterminacy. Inquiry, 56(4), 359–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandro Torza.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article is part of the topical collection ”Indeterminacy and Underdetermination”, edited by Mark Bowker and Maria Baghramian.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 The paraphrase \(\mathbf { f}\)

It needs to be proven that the function f from Sect. 4, which maps categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentences to \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) sentences, preserves coarse-grained content. The proof is by induction on the syntactical complexity of categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentences. (I will explicitly state the justification of a step only when the step requires appealing to a new principle.)

(At\(_{Q}\)):

We need to show that for any atomic categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentence p, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

p is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([p]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

Proof: p is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([p]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) (by definition of \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-truth), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([p]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (by cr together with its converse, which is trivial), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([p]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (since \([p]_{C}=[p]_{Q}\) for atomic p), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([p]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true (since C assigns the correct probabilities to classical facts).

(\(\lnot _{Q}\)):

We need to show that, for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentence P, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(\lnot P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

Proof: \(\lnot P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([\lnot P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}(-_{Q}[P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}(-_{Q}[P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}(-_{Q}[\mathbf {f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (by inductive hypothesis), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf {f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf {f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

(\(\wedge _{Q}\)):

We need to show that, for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentences SP and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(S\wedge P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff both \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(S)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) and \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) are \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

Proof: \(S\wedge P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([S\wedge P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([S]_{Q}\sqcap _{Q} [P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([S]_{Q}\sqcap _{Q} [P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(S)]_{C}\sqcap _{Q} [\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (by inductive hypothesis), iff \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(S)]_{C}\sqcap _{C} [\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (because \(\sqcap _{C}=\sqcap _{Q}\)), iff both \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(S)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) and \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\), iff both \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(S)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) and \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) are \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

1.2 The paraphrase \(\mathbf { g}\)

It needs to be proven that the function g from Sect. 4, which maps categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentences to \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) sentences, preserves coarse-grained content. The proof is by induction on the syntactical complexity of categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentences. (Once again, I will explicitly state the justification of a step only when a new principle is appealed to.)

(At\(_{C}\)):

We need to show that for any atomic categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentence p, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

p is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff \(\mathcal {T}(p)\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true.

Proof: p is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff \(\mathrm {T}_{C}([p]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) (by definition of \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-truth), iff \(\mathrm {T}_{C}([p]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) (since \([p]_{C}=[p]_{Q}\) for atomic p), iff \(\mathcal {T}(p)\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true (by definition of \(\mathcal {T}\)).

(\(\lnot _{C}\)):

We need to show that, for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentence P, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(\lnot P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff \(\sim \mathbf {g}(P)\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true.

Proof: \(\lnot P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff \(\mathrm {T}_{C}([\lnot P]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff \(\mathrm {T}_{C}(-_{C}[P]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff not \(\mathrm {T}_{C}([P]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff not \(\mathrm {T}_{C}([\mathbf { g}(P)]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) (by inductive hypothesis), iff \(\mathbf {g}(P)\) is not \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true, iff \(\sim \mathbf {g}(P)\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true (by definition of \(\sim \)).

(\(\wedge _{C}\)):

We need to show that, for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentences SP and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(S\wedge P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff \( \mathbf { g}(S) \& \mathbf { g}(P)\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true.

Proof: analogous to the case of (\(\lnot _{C}\)).

1.3 Verbal disagreement about MI

We want to show that the dispute between classicists (\(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-speakers) and quantum logicians (\(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-speakers) about whether quantum mechanics leads to MI is verbal in Hirsch’s sense (Sect. 4). A rigorous proof that the dispute is verbal will require (i) introducing an indeterminacy operator in both object languages; (ii) extending the paraphrase schemes \(\mathbf { f}\), \(\mathbf { g}\) in order to account for statements of indeterminacy; (iii) showing that, for some categorical sentence p, ‘it is metaphysically indeterminate whether p’ is true-in-\(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) iff it is not true-in-\(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\).

Let us start by expanding both \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) and \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) with a sentential operator \(\nabla \) with the intended meaning ‘it is metaphysically indeterminate whether’ as defined by ind. We then extend \(\mathbf { f}\) to a mapping \(\mathbf { f}^{*}\) from categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentences to \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) sentences such that:

(\(\nabla _{Q}\)):

If P is a categorical sentence of \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\), then \(\mathbf { f}^{*}(\nabla P)\) is \(\lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) \(=1\wedge \lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\)

whereas \(\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)=\mathbf { f}(P)\) if P is atomic, negated, or conjunctive. We need to show that for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-sentence P, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(\nabla P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff \(\lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) \(=1\wedge \lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

Proof: \(\nabla P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true iff not \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) and not \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([\lnot P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff not \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}([P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) and not \(\mathrm {T}_{Q}(-_{Q}[P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\), iff not \(\mathbf {Pr}([P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) and not \(\mathbf {Pr}(-_{Q}[P]_{Q},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\), iff not \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) and not \(\mathbf {Pr}(-_{Q}[\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=1\) (by inductive hypothesis), iff not \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) \(=1\) and not \(\mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\), iff \(\lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )\) \(=1\wedge \lnot \mathbf {Pr}([\mathbf { f}^{*}(P)]_{C},|\psi _{@}\rangle )=0\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true.

We now extend \(\mathbf { g}\) to a mapping \(\mathbf { g}^{*}\) from categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentences to \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) sentences such that

(\(\nabla _{C}\)):

If P is a categorical sentence of \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\), then \(\mathbf { g}^{*}(\nabla P)\) is \(0=1\)

whereas \(\mathbf { g}^{*}(P)=\mathbf { g}(P)\) if P is atomic, negated, or conjunctive. We need to show that for any categorical \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-sentence P, and any choice of \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \):

\(\nabla P\) is \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\)-true iff 0=1 is \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\)-true.

Since \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) is bivalent, the proof is trivial. This concludes the proof that there is a two-way paraphrase between expanded \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) and expanded \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\).

The final step is to find a categorical sentence p in the common fragment of \(\mathcal {L}_{C}\) and \(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) such that \(\nabla p\) is true-in-\(\mathcal {L}_{Q}\) and not true-in-\(\mathcal {L}_{C}\). Relative to a single-electron system in a superposition of z-spin up and z-spin down, one such sentence is ‘e is z-spin up.’ This suffices to show that the disagreement between C and Q concerning quantum MI is verbal in Hirsch’s sense.

1.4 Collective completeness of \(\mathcal {Q}\) relative to \(\mathcal {C}\)

Let \(\mathcal {C},\mathcal {Q}\) be classical and quantum logical spaces, respectively, on a set of quantum states W. We need to show that \(\mathcal {Q}\) is collectively complete relative to \(\mathcal {C}\), which is to say, that the collection of all classical facts obtaining at \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \) is collectively empirically equivalent to the singleton of the quantum fact which corresponds to the closed set having as members all vectors indistinguishable from \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \). The proof is as follows.

In quantum mechanics, states differing by a scalar verify the same experimental facts. Therefore, quantum states are indistinguishable just in case they differ by a scalar. Let \(\mathbf {P}\) be the set of facts obtaining at \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \) in \(\mathcal {C}\). Consider now the set of facts \(\mathbf {Q}=\{Q\}\) in \(\mathcal {Q}\), where Q is the set of unitary vectors indistinguishable from \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \). If Q obtains at some state indistinguishable from a state \(|\psi \rangle \), then \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \) and \(|\psi \rangle \) are indistinguishable. Therefore, every \(P\in \mathbf {P}\) obtains at some state, namely \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \), which is indistinguishable from \(|\psi \rangle \). Conversely, let every \(P\in \mathbf {P}\) obtain at some state indistinguishable from a state \(|\psi \rangle \). Since \(Q\in \mathbf {P}\), \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \) and \(|\psi \rangle \) are indistinguishable. Therefore, Q obtains at some state, namely \(|\psi _{@}\rangle \), which is indistinguishable from \(|\psi \rangle \). QED.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Torza, A. Quantum metametaphysics. Synthese 199, 9809–9833 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03226-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03226-0

Keywords

Navigation