Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T03:25:42.459Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Experience and Testimony in Hume's Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

The standard interpretation of Hume on testimony takes him to be a reductionist; justification of beliefs from testimony ultimately depends on one's own first-person experience. Yet Hume's main discussions of testimony in the Treatise and first Enquiry suggest a social account. Hume appeals to shared experience and develops norms of belief from testimony that are not reductionist. It is argued that the reductionist interpretation rests on an overly narrow view of Hume's theory of ideas. By attending to such mechanisms of the imagination as abstraction and fictions, it is shown that Hume's theory of ideas does not forestall a non-reductionist social epistemology.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1981. “Hume and Julius Caesar.” In From Parmenides to Wittgenstein: Collected Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Baier, Annette. 1991. A Progress of Sentiments: Re.ections on Hume's Treatise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 1992. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Flew, Anthony. 1961. Hume's Philosophy of Belief. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1991. “Epistemic Paternalism: Communication Control in Law and Society.” The Journal of Philosophy 88(3): 113–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 2002. Pathways to Knowledge: Public and Private. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David. 1739–40/2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Norton, D. F. and Norton, M. J. (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1748/1999. An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding. Beauchamp, T. L. (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, David. 1754–62/1983. The History of England. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1783/2004. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Hatfield, G. (ed.). Rev. ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2006. “Introduction.” In Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.), The Epistemology of Testimony. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maine, Henry. 1884. Ancient Law. New York: Holt and Company.Google Scholar
Passmore, John. 1980. Hume's Intentions. 3rd ed. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Reid, Thomas. 1970. An Inquiry into the Human Mind. Duggan, T. (ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Frederick. 1992. Knowledge and Belief. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid. 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Traiger, Saul. 1987. “Impressions, Ideas, and Fictions.” Hume Studies 13(2): 381–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Traiger, Saul. 1993. “Humean Testimony.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74(2): 135–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Traiger, Saul. 1994. “Beyond our Senses: Recasting Book I, Part III of Hume's Treatise.” Hume Studies 20(2): 241–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welbourne, Michael. 2001. Knowledge. Chesham: Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Fred. 2008. The External World and Our Knowledge of It: Hume's Critical Realism, an Exposition and a Defence. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar