Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-06T17:45:57.202Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Biomedical Moral Enhancement in the Face of Moral Particularism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 October 2018

Pei-Hua Huang
Affiliation:
Monash University
Peter Shiu-Hwa Tsu*
Affiliation:
Chung Cheng University

Abstract

Biomedical moral enhancement, or BME for short, aims to improve people's moral behaviour through augmenting, via biomedical means, their virtuous dispositions such as sympathy, honesty, courage, or generosity. Recently, however, it has been challenged, on particularist grounds, that the manifestations of virtuous dispositions can be morally wrong. For instance, being generous in terrorist financing is one such case. If so, biomedical moral enhancement, by enhancing people's virtues, might turn out to be counterproductive in terms of people's moral behaviour. In this chapter, we argue, via a comparison with moral education, that the case for the practice of biomedical moral enhancement is not weakened by the particularists’ stress on the variable moral statuses of the manifestations of our virtues. The real challenge from the particularists, we argue, lies elsewhere. It is that practical wisdom, being essentially context-sensitive, cannot be enhanced via biomedical means. On the basis of this, we further argue that BME ought to be used with great caution, for it may wrongly enhance, for instance, a terrorist financier's generosity, a robber's courage, or an undercover detective's honesty. Finally, we sketch how boundaries can be set on the use of BME, and address some potential objections to our position.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See Persson, Ingmar and Savulescu, Julian, ‘The Perils of Cognitive Enhancement and the Urgent Imperative to Enhance the Moral Character of Humanity’, Journal of Applied Philosophy 25:3 (2008), 162177CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Persson, and Savulescu, , Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Persson and Savulescu, ‘The Duty to be Morally Enhanced’, Topoi (2017), https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9475-7.

2 For a more detailed review of pharmaceuticals that are known to be effective in modulating moral behaviours, see Levy, Neil, et al. , ‘Are You Morally Modified? The Moral Effects of Widely Used Pharmaceuticals’, Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 21:2 (2014), 111125CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 It is to be noted that although according to Aristotle self-control is not a virtue, Aristotle certainly would not deny its importance for the production of morally right behaviour on many occasions. For instance, it is certainly required for the ethical behaviour of a man who lusts for his friend's wife.

4 Persson and Savulescu, ‘The Perils of Cognitive Enhancement and the Urgent Imperative to Enhance the Moral Character of Humanity’; Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement; Douglas, Thomas, ‘Moral Enhancement’, Journal of Applied Philosophy 25:3 (2008), 228245CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 See Persson and Savulescu, ‘The Perils of Cognitive Enhancement and the Urgent Imperative to Enhance the Moral Character of Humanity’, and Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement, for instance.

6 See Dreu, Carsten De, et al. , ‘Oxytocin Promotes Human Ethnocentrism’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 108:4 (2011), 1262–66CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. Recently it has even been argued that tinkering with some dispositions via biomedical means might actually lead to adverse effects on others. See Handfield, Toby, Huang, Pei-Hua, and Simpson, Robert Mark, ‘Climate Change, Cooperation, and Moral Bioenhancement’, Journal of Medical Ethics 42:11 (2016), 742747CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Lane, Anthony, et al. , ‘Failed Replication of Oxytocin Effects on Trust: The Envelope Task Case’, PLoS One 10:9 (2015), e0137000CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 See, for example, Ahmann, Peter, et al. , ‘Placebo-Controlled Evaluation of Ritalin Side Effects’, Pediatrics 91:6 (1993), 11011106Google ScholarPubMed.

9 Agar, Nicholas, ‘Why is it Possible to Enhance Moral Status and Why is Doing So Wrong?’, Journal of Medical Ethics 39:2 (2013), 6774CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Buchanan, Allen, ‘Moral Status and Human Enhancement’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 37:4 (2009), 346381CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Harris, John, ‘Moral Enhancement and Freedom’, Bioethics 25:2 (2011), 102–11CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Sparrow, Robert, ‘Better Living through Chemistry? A Reply to Savulescu and Persson on “Moral Enhancement”’, Journal of Applied Philosophy 31:1 (2014), 2332CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 A phrase used in John Milton's Paradise Lost. See Harris, ‘Moral Enhancement and Freedom’.

12 See Kane, Robert, A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 3Google Scholar.

13 For an in-depth review of moral enhancement see Specker, Jona, et al. , ‘The Ethical Desirability of Moral Bioenhancement: A Review of Reasons’, BMC Medical Ethics 15:67 (2014)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed: https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-15-67.

14 See especially Sparrow, ‘Better Living Through Chemistry? A Reply to Savulescu and Persson on “Moral Enhancement”’, 5; Sparrow, Robert, ‘Egalitarianism and Moral Bioenhancement’, American Journal of Bioethics 14:4 (2014), 20, 21CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also, Douglas, Thomas, ‘Moral Enhancement’, in Savulescu, Julian, Muelen, Ruud ter, and Kahane, Guy (eds), Enhancing Human Capacities (Blackwell: Oxford, 2011), 467485Google Scholar. It is worth mentioning that although Douglas, a supporter of BME, acknowledges this line of objection, he does not really address it but merely sets it aside.

15 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI.

16 The passage from the beginning of this section is adapted from Tsu, Peter Shiu-Hwa, ‘Particularism in Ethics’, in Pritchard, Duncan (ed.), Oxford Bibliographies Online (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018)Google Scholar: https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0367.xml.

17 We use “moral values” broadly to refer to not only goodness and badness but rightness and wrongness as well.

18 Jonathan Dancy, “Moral Particularism”, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/moral-particularism/.

19 See for instance Hooker, Brad, ‘Moral Particularism: Wrong and Bad’, in Hooker, Brad and Little, Margaret (eds), Moral Particularism, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 8Google Scholar.

20 Hooker, ‘Moral Particularism: Wrong and Bad’; Hooker, Brad, ‘Moral Particularism and the Real World’, in Strahovnik, Vojko, Lance, Mark, and Potrc, Matjaž (eds), Challenging Moral Particularism (New York: Routledge, 2008), 1230Google Scholar; Crisp, Roger, ‘Particularizing Particularism’, in Hooker, Brad and Little, Margaret (eds), Moral Particularism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 2347Google Scholar; McNaughton, David and Rawling, Piers, ‘Unprincipled Ethics’, in Hooker, Brad and Little, Margaret (eds), Moral Particularism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 256275Google Scholar; Little, Margaret, ‘Moral Generalities Revisited’, in Hooker, Brad and Little, Margaret (eds), Moral Particularism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 276304Google Scholar.

21 Bader, Ralf, ‘Conditions, Modifiers, and Holism’, in Lord, Errol and McGuire, Barry (eds), Weighing Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 2755CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 We say “arguably” because one might feel that what happens in the S&M chamber is consensual and therefore cannot really be torture. On the other hand, it might well be contended that if what is going on in the S&M chamber is not real torture then the masochists in the S&M chamber would not get a kick out of it. The fact that the masochists do get a kick, one might therefore suggest, indicates that what they experience is indeed torture. See Timmons, Mark, Moral Theory (Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002), 259Google Scholar.

23 Blackburn, Simon, ‘Through Thick and Thin’, in Practical Tortoise Raising and Other Philosophical Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), ch.7CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Disentangling Disentangling’, in Kirchin, Simon (ed.), Thick Concepts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 121135CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 See for instance Sparrow, ‘Better Living Through Chemistry? A Reply to Savulescu and Persson on “Moral Enhancement”’, and ‘Egalitarianism and Moral Bioenhancement’.

25 Swanton, Christine, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 244CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 It should be noted that situationist philosophers, such as John Doris and Gilbert Harman, often take the claim here to be falsified by empirical evidence (such as the Good Samaritan experiment) in social psychology. See Doris, John, Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harman, Gilbert, ‘Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99:1 (1999), 315332CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Situationism is roughly the view that our moral behaviour is very much of a function of the circumstances we are in; the virtues do not have much of a role to play. However, we are of the view that the empirical evidence adduced by the situationists might merely show that most people are not as virtuous as they should be, not that the virtues are usually causally inefficacious with regard to morally right actions. Before this alternative interpretation of the empirical evidence is ruled out, we do not think that situationism has much force against our claim.

27 Little, ‘Moral Generalities Revisited’, 296–298.

28 And after all, moral philosophers since the time of Aristotle have long been aware of moral (bad) luck.

29 Christine Swanston and John McDowell also interpret practical wisdom along these lines. See Swanton, Christine, ‘A Virtue Ethical Account of Right Action’, Ethics 112:1 (2001), 3252CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McDowell, John, ‘Virtue and Reason’, in Mind, Value & Reality (Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2002), 5073Google Scholar. For Aristotle's relevant characterisation of practical wisdom, see Nicomachean Ethics, VI.8.

30 Dancy, Jonathan, Ethics Without Principles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 2CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI.6.

32 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI.13.

33 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, II.3.

34 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI.8.

35 A passage from Elizabeth Telfer's work can illuminate why this is so: ‘it seems to be true that we do not call someone “wise” in English unless he is in general a good person, and it may be that the Greek noun “phronesis” carries a similar implication’. See Telfer, , ‘The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle's “Nicomachean Ethics”’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90:1 (1990), 3548CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 For relevant views of the BME supporters, see, for instance, DeGrazia, David, ‘Moral Enhancement, Freedom, and What We (Should) Value in Moral Behaviour’, Journal of Medical Ethics 40:6 (2014), 361368CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Douglas, ‘Moral Enhancement’; Persson and Savulescu, ‘The Perils of Cognitive Enhancement and the Urgent Imperative to Enhance the Moral Character of Humanity’; Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement; and ‘The Duty to be Morally Enhanced’; Jefferson, Will, et al. , ‘Enhancement and Civic Virtue’, Social Theory and Practice 40:3 (2014), 499527CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 See Nussbaum, Martha, ‘Finely Aware and Richly Responsible’, Love's Knowledge (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 148167Google Scholar.

38 Although it should be admitted that contemporary moral philosophy often involves a heavy use of thought experiments which are abstracted from the concrete details of the case. We are not against their use, for they can indeed help illuminate difficult cases from time to time. But we should also be careful in their use in that there can be morally relevant differences between them and the real cases we encounter. This is a point the particularists have been wont to emphasise. See Dancy, Jonathan, ‘The Role of Imaginary Cases in Ethics’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66:1/2 (1985), 141153CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

39 See for instance, Persson and Savulescu, ‘The Perils of Cognitive Enhancement and the Urgent Imperative to Enhance the Moral Character of Humanity’; Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement; and ‘The Duty to be Morally Enhanced’.

40 Something along these lines was suggested by Wiseman, Harris, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limit of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2016), 170CrossRefGoogle Scholar. He maintains that working alongside traditional moral education, BME might well serve as a supplementary support mechanism for those who are already morally oriented.

41 Indeed, there is good textual evidence in support of this interpretation in Nicomachean Ethics, VI.12, where Aristotle claims that ‘[m]anifestly, then, one cannot be practically wise without being good’.

42 Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limit of Moral Enhancement, 285–286. For a more detailed discussion, see Huang, Pei-Hua, ‘Authenticity, Autonomy and Enhancement’, Dilemata 19 (2015), 3952Google Scholar.

43 Christen, Markus and Narvaez, Darcia, ‘Moral Development in Early Childhood Is Key for Moral Enhancement’, AJOB Neuroscience 2:4 (2012), 25CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Irwin, Terence, ‘Ethics as an Inexact Science: Aristotle's Ambition for Moral Theory’, in Hooker, Brad and Little, Margaret (eds), Moral Particularism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 100129Google Scholar.

45 Agay, Nirit, et al. , ‘Non-Specific Effects of Methylphenidate (Ritalin) on Cognitive Ability and Decision-Making of ADHD and Healthy Adults’, Psychopharmacology 210:4 (2010), 511519CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

46 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI.12.

47 This chapter is a work of collaboration; both authors contributed equally to the writing of and research for it. We are immensely grateful to the following people for their helpful feedback: Robert Sparrow, Robert Mark Simpson, Andrew McLoughlin, and Hiroshi Miura. Tsu would also like to thank Taiwan's Ministry of Science and Technology for financial support (MOST-104-2628-H-194-001-MY2; MOST-105-2410-H-194-096-MY4).