Skip to main content
Log in

Categoricalism, dispositionalism, and the epistemology of properties

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Notoriously, the dispositional view of natural properties is thought to face a number of regress problems, one of which points to an epistemological worry. In this paper, I argue that the rival categorical view is also susceptible to the same kind of regress problem. This problem can be overcome, most plausibly, with the development of a structuralist epistemology. After identifying problems faced by alternative solutions, I sketch the main features of this structuralist epistemological approach, referring to graph-theoretic modelling in the process. Given that both the categoricalists and dispositionalists are under pressure to adopt this same epistemological approach in light of the regress problem, this suggests that the categoricalist versus dispositionalist debate is best fought on metaphysical rather than epistemological grounds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lewis expresses this thought in two different ways, by appealing to the permutation scenario and the replacement scenario. For further details see Lewis (2009).

  2. It is worth noting that the term ‘internal relation’ is a slippery one, and is used in different ways in different contexts. See for example Barker (2009), who distinguishes between Armstrongian, Leibnizian and Bradleyan internal relations (Barker 2009, pp. 246–247). The notion of internality described above is the Leibnizian one.

  3. The following regress objection can be framed without addressing the question of what, precisely, the nomic relation amounts to. Armstrong (1983, Ch. 6), takes the nomic relation to be a sui generis relation between properties. Other categoricalists view nomicity in terms of regularity relations: see for e.g. Lewis (1973, p. 73).

  4. This appears to be how Fales, who holds something like a dual aspect view of properties, thinks the epistemology of properties should be tackled (1990, p. 222).

  5. See Lewis for a related worry (2009. p. 217). He considers whether the fundamental quiddities could all be construed as qualia as a way of answering the global quidditistic scepticism discussed earlier, but he rejects this proposal on the grounds that qualia clash with his materialist commitments.

  6. In a recent book chapter, Paul (2013) draws a similar conclusion (though from a somewhat different angle) with regards to Lewisian metaphysical realism. Paul argues that our scientific terms can have determinate reference on Lewis’s system (thereby overcoming Putnam’s model-theoretic problem), but that this is contingent on our world having the right kind of (non-symmetrical) structure.

  7. Localised versions of the symmetry problem have also been raised in the philosophy of mind. Those who accept the possibility of inverted qualia, for example, accept that two distinct qualitative experiences could play identical functional roles. In the case of intersubjective qualia inversion (Shoemaker 1975, p. 197), because the functional roles of people’s differing experiences would be the same, the differences in those experiences would be completely undetectable (all the perceivers would still overtly agree on which objects count as having which colour, for example). This suggests, among other things, that purely functional theories of mind miss something out. See Shoemaker (1975) for a functionalist response. Needless to say, it would be nice for the categoricalists if they could find an argument to rule out functional symmetries in all cases, whether they be phenomenal or non-phenomenal ones.

  8. Hawthorne illustrates by asking us to consider the following scenario: ‘there are four properties, call them A, B, C, D. Here are the laws governing them: ANC, BNC, (A and B)ND’ (2006, p. 224). Here, A and B are distinct, since their coinstantiation has different effects than is produced by single instantiations of them. Such a structure, Hawthorne claims, is intuitively possible yet is clearly symmetrical.

  9. The same point applies to another structuralist view which would allow for symmetrical structures, one which was first suggested by Shoemaker and which Hawthorne calls ‘modest’ structuralism. For details of this view see Hawthorne 2006, appendix, pp. 226–227.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1978). A theory of universals, vol. 2 of Universals and scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Barker, S. (2009). Dispositional monism, relational constitution and quiddities. Analysis, 69, 242–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Properties and laws. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, R. (2000). Against quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 87–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 227–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1988). Quining qualia. In A. J. Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science (pp. 42–77). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2012). The categorical dimensions of the causal powers. In A. Bird, B. Ellis, & H. Sankey (Eds.), Properties, powers and structures (pp. 11–26). Abingdon: Routledge.

  • Fales, E. (1990). Causation and universals. Abingdon: Routledge.

  • Fales, E. (1993). Are causal laws contingent? In J. Bacon, K. Campbell, & L. Reinhardt (Eds.), Ontology, causality, and mind (pp. 121–144). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2006). Causal structuralism. In his Metaphysical essays (pp. 211–227). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist, 94, 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2004). Elusive knowledge of things in themselves. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2007). Phenomenal concepts and the materialist constraint. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism (pp. 145–166). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–222). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

  • Loar, B. (1990). Phenomenal states. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 4: Action theory and philosophy of mind (pp. 81–108). Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (2009). A partial defense of Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 223–241). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2010). On the individuation of powers. In A. Marmodoro (Ed.), The metaphysics of powers: their grounding and their manifestations (pp. 8–26). Abingdon: Routledge.

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. Abingdon: Routledge.

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Clarendon: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2013). Realism about structure and kinds. In S. Mumford and M. Tugby (Eds.), Metaphysics and science (pp. 183–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press, Mind Occasional Series.

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility, and consciousness. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 123, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1975). Functionalism and qualia. In his Identity, cause, and mind, 1984 (pp. 184–205). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In his Identity, cause, and mind, 1984 (pp. 206–32). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Shoemaker, S. (1981). Some varieties of functionalism. In his Identity, cause, and mind, 1984 (pp. 261–86). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Schroer, R. (2012). Two challenges that categorical properties pose to physicalism. Ratio, 25, 195–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

  • Swinburne, R. (1980). Properties, causation, and projectibility: Reply to Shoemaker. In L. J. Cohen & M. Hesse (Eds.), Applications of inductive logic (pp. 313–320). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Tugby, M. (2012). Rescuing dispositionalism from the ultimate problem: Response to Barker and Smart. Analysis, 72, 723–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks go to the anonymous referees for their very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Tugby.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tugby, M. Categoricalism, dispositionalism, and the epistemology of properties. Synthese 191, 1147–1162 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0316-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0316-y

Keywords

Navigation